Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Of mice and men: The comparative assumption in psychology.K. V. Wilkes - 1991 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5 (1):3 – 19.
    Abstract Surprisingly, little theoretical attention has so far been paid to the ?Comparative Assumption?: the attempt to extrapolate from species to species in psychology (and particularly to the human species). This paper examines the problems and the possibilities inherent in the Comparative Assumption. Perhaps the most important conclusion of the paper is that much more work is needed on this intriguing question.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tactical deception in primates.A. Whiten & R. W. Byrne - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):233-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   172 citations  
  • The Problem of Simple Minds: Is There Anything It Is Like to Be a Honey Bee? [REVIEW]Michael Tye - 1997 - Philosophical Studies 88 (3):289-317.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Misdescription and misuse of anecdotes and mental state concepts.Roger K. Thomas - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):265-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Deception and descriptive mentalism.Nicholas S. Thompson - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):266-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rationality and charity.Paul Thagard & Richard E. Nisbett - 1983 - Philosophy of Science 50 (2):250-267.
    Quine and others have recommended principles of charity which discourage judgments of irrationality. Such principles have been proposed to govern translation, psychology, and economics. After comparing principles of charity of different degrees of severity, we argue that the stronger principles are likely to block understanding of human behavior and impede progress toward improving it. We support a moderate principle of charity which leaves room for empirically justified judgments of irrationality.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Social strategies and primate psychology.Shirley C. Strum - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):264-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Family life and opportunities for deception.Peter K. Smith - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):264-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deception and adaptation: Multidisciplinary perspectives on presenting a neutral image.Thomas R. Shultz & Peter J. LaFrenière - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):263-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moving Ourselves, Moving Others: Motion and Emotion in Intersubjectivity, Consciousness, and Language.Andrea Schiavio - 2015 - Philosophical Psychology 28 (5):735-739.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deception: A need for theory and ethology.Carolyn A. Ristau - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):262-263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tactical deception: A likely kind of primate action.Vernon Reynolds - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):262-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Only external representations are needed.Howard Rachlin - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):261-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Which are more easily deceived, friends or strangers?Duane Quiatt - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):260-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Reason and Passion.R. S. Peters - 1970 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 4:132-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reason and Passion.R. S. Peters - 1970 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 4:132-153.
    I Once gave a series of talks to a group of psychoanalysts who had trained together and was rather struck by the statement made by one of them that, psychologically speaking, ‘reason’ means saying ‘No’ to oneself. Plato, of course, introduced the concept of ‘reason’ in a similar way in The Republic with the case of the thirsty man who is checked in the satisfaction of his thirst by reflection on the outcome of drinking. But Plato was also so impressed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ontogeny, biography, and evidence for tactical deception.Robert W. Mitchell - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):259-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Epistemological Significance of Practices.Alan Millar - 2011 - ProtoSociology 28:213-230.
    There are countless occasions when we find people’s thought or action intelligible, or anticipate what they will think or do, or are at least unsurprised by what they think or do, despite our having little if any information about their attitudes other than what we can gather from their situation and non-verbal behaviour. This article explores the role of practices, conceived as essentially rule-governed activities, is making this possible. Consideration is given to practicies for the use of words.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mindless behaviorism, bodiless cognitivism, or primatology?E. W. Menzel - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):258-259.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • You can't hide your lying eyes.W. C. McGrew - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):258-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • I. Graham on the logic of belief.John Krige - 1976 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 19 (1-4):355-360.
    The examples with which Keith Graham has tried (in Inquiry, Vol. 17 [1974], No. 3) to undermine certain general features of the concept of belief fail to do so. Roughly speaking, he has not shown that the persons who make the puzzling assertions which he describes really mean what they say. His discussion has the merit of emphasizing the limits of philosophical analysis in adjudicating on the application of concepts in borderline cases.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Closure on knowability.Mark Jago - 2010 - Analysis 70 (4):648-659.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Animal action in the space of reasons.Susan Hurley - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (3):231-256.
    I defend the view that we should not overintellectualize the mind. Nonhuman animals can occupy islands of practical rationality: they can have contextbound reasons for action even though they lack full conceptual abilities. Holism and the possibility of mistake are required for such reasons to be the agent's reasons, but these requirements can be met in the absence of inferential promiscuity. Empirical work with animals is used to illustrate the possibility that reasons for action could be bound to symbolic or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Animal Action in the Space of Reasons.Susan Hurley - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (3):231-257.
    I defend the view that we should not overintellectualize the mind. Nonhuman animals can occupy islands of practical rationality: they can have context‐bound reasons for action even though they lack full conceptual abilities. Holism and the possibility of mistake are required for such reasons to be the agent's reasons, but these requirements can be met in the absence of inferential promiscuity. Empirical work with animals is used to illustrate the possibility that reasons for action could be bound to symbolic or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Lies, damned lies and anecdotal evidence.Nicholas Humphrey - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):257-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The distant blast of Lloyd Morgan's Canon.Cecilia Heyes - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):256-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Depth of intention.Ingemund Gullvåg - 1983 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 26 (1):31 – 83.
    The paper attempts to reconstruct some notions of Naess's semantics, and at the same time to relate them to more recent developments. On Naess's view, there is no such thing as a language in the sense of a shared structure which determines clear-cut literal meanings like Fregean Gedanken or propositions. We use words, and try to interpret each other; but there is no a priori or intuitive basis for secure and precise knowledge about language. Interpretation or understanding, as well as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Subjective reality.Donald R. Griffin - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):256-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does mentality entail consciousness?Rocco J. Gennaro - 1995 - Philosophia 24 (3-4):331-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a taxonomy of mind in primates.Gordon G. Gallup - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):255-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Sprachspiel vs. vollständige Sprache: Einige Bemerkungen zum späten Wittgenstein, zur Übersetzung und Übersichtlichkeit, zum Handlungswissen und Diskurs.Audun Øfsti - 1990 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 21 (1):105 - 133.
    Language-Game vs. Complete Language. The article formulates a criticism of Wittgenstein's later philosophy which, in its substance, I would like to think, is fairly the same as the (hermeneutic) criticism issued by Apel and Habermas in the sixties. Contrary to these philosophers, however, I try to make the point by focusing on the distinction between language game and language, respectively between intralanguage relations of 'family resemblance' (between language games) and interlanguage translation relations. The notion of a 'complete language' is introduced (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A matter of opinion.Keith Frankish - 1998 - Philosophical Psychology 11 (4):423-442.
    This paper sets out the case for a two-level theory of human psychology. It takes its start from Daniel Dennett.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reason, emotion, and love.Mark Fisher - 1977 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 20 (1-4):189 – 203.
    Wittgenstein's private language argument is interpreted as an example of a kind of transcendental argument which, if valid, explains why a certain concept must possess certain features. Cognition and affect are shown to require each other by an application of Bennett's account of what beings capable of true cognition must be capable of, and the necessity of certain emotions to the existence of any rules in a community is argued in similar fashion. Hume's account of love and admiration being rejected, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How to break moulds.R. I. M. Dunbar - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):254-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The moral status of non-human beings and their ecosystems.Michel Dion - 2000 - Ethics, Place and Environment 3 (2):221 – 229.
    Environmental ethics is generally searching for the intrinsic value in natural beings. However, there are very few holistic models trying to reflect the various dimensions of the experience-to-be a natural being. We are searching for that intrinsic value, in order to determine which species are holders of rights. In this article, I suggest a set of moral and rational principles to be used for identifying the intrinsic value of a given species and for comparing it to that of other species.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The moral status of non‐human beings and their ecosystems.Michel Dion - 2000 - Philosophy and Geography 3 (2):221-229.
    Environmental ethics is generally searching for the intrinsic value in natural beings. However, there are very few holistic models trying to reflect the various dimensions of the experience‐to‐be a natural being. We are searching for that intrinsic value, in order to determine which species are holders of rights. In this article, I suggest a set of moral and rational principles to be used for identifying the intrinsic value of a given species and for comparing it to that of other species.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Emotional control.Frans B. M. de Waal - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):254-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • References.John Bengson & Marc A. Moffett - 2011 - In Knowing How: Essays on Knowledge, Mind, and Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 361-386.
    This compilation of references includes all references for the knowledge-how chapters included in Bengson & Moffett's edited volume. The volume and the compilation of references may serve as a good starting point for people who are unfamiliar with the philosophical literature on knowledge-how.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Pluralism Worth Having: Feyerabend's Well-Ordered Science.Jamie Shaw - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Western Ontario
    The goal of this dissertation is to reconstruct, critically evaluate, and apply the pluralism of Paul Feyerabend. I conclude by suggesting future points of contact between Feyerabend’s pluralism and topics of interest in contemporary philosophy of science. I begin, in Chapter 1, by reconstructing Feyerabend’s critical philosophy. I show how his published works from 1948 until 1970 show a remarkably consistent argumentative strategy which becomes more refined and general as Feyerabend’s thought matures. Specifically, I argue that Feyerabend develops a persuasive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language without communication intention.گالن استراوسن - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations at University of Tabriz 12 (24):15-54.
    This paper argues that a language can exist and flourish in a community even if none of of the members of the community has any communication intentions; and that reference to the notion of communication intention can therefore be dispensed with in the core account of the nature oflinguistic meaning. Certainly one cannot elucidate the notion of linguistic meaning without reference to psychological notions; the communication-intention theorists are right about this. They are, however, wrong about which psychological notions are needed. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Animal consciousness as a test case of cognitive science.Manuel Bremer - 2005 - In Bewusstsein: Interdisziplinäre Perspektiven.
    In our dealings with animals at least most of us see them as conscious beings. On the other hand the employment of human categories to animals seems to be problematic. Reflecting on the details of human beliefs, for example, casts serious doubt on whether the cat is able to believe anything at all. These theses try to reflect on methodological issues when investigating animal minds. Developing a theory of animal mentality seems to be a test case of the interdisciplinary research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The development of temporal concepts: Learning to locate events in time.Teresa McCormack & Christoph Hoerl - 2017 - Timing and Time Perception 5 (3-4):297-327.
    A new model of the development of temporal concepts is described that assumes that there are substantial changes in how children think about time in the early years. It is argued that there is a shift from understanding time in an event-dependent way to an event-independent understanding of time. Early in development, very young children are unable to think about locations in time independently of the events that occur at those locations. It is only with development that children begin to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations