Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Sociology Of Knowledge And The Epistemological Status Of Science.Alan Chalmers - 1988 - Thesis Eleven 21 (1):82-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The "strong programme", normativity, and social causes.Chris Calvert-Minor - 2008 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 38 (1):1–22.
    Barry Barnes and David Bloor of the Strong Programme of the sociology of knowledge advance a naturalized epistemology that reduces all accounts of normativity to social causes. I endorse their program of naturalizing one kind of normativity, but I argue that there is another kind they cannot naturalize. Within the context of sociological explanations of rationality, there are norms of rationality instantiated by scientists that Barnes and Bloor study, and Barnes and Bloor's own normative ascriptions of scientists as rational beings. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Thomas Kuhn's Relativistic Legacy.Alexander Bird - 2011 - In Steven D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 475–488.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Abstract Introduction Paradigms, Disciplinary Matrices, and Epistemological Relativism Incommensurability The Transcendence of Truth World ‐ Change, Idealism, and Ontological Relativism Relativism in the Sociology of Science and the History of Science References.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On consensus and stability in science.Brian S. Baigrie & J. N. Hattiangadi - 1992 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (4):435-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Fuller's civic republicanism and the question of scientific expertise.Brian S. Baigrie - 1995 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 25 (4):502-511.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • But is it sociology of knowledge? Wilhelm Jerusalem’s “sociology of cognition” in context.Thomas Uebel - 2012 - Studies in East European Thought 64 (1-2):5-37.
    This paper considers the charge that—contrary to the current widespread assumption accompanying the near-universal neglect of his work—Wilhelm Jerusalem (1854–1923) cannot count as one of the founders of the sociology of (scientific) knowledge. In order to elucidate the matter, Jerusalem’s “sociology of cognition” is here reconstructed in the context of his own work in psychology and philosophy as well as in the context of the work of some predecessors and contemporaries. It is argued that while it shows clear discontinuities with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Can relativism be reconciled with realism and causalism?Barbara Tuchańska - 1990 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (3):285 – 294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can relativism be reconciled with realism and causalism?Barbara Tuchańska - 1990 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (3):285-294.
    Abstract This paper deals with two fundamental assumptions of the Strong programme in the sociology of knowledge and the theoretical (im) possibility of their co?existence with the general relativist tendency of this programme. The first assumption is the realist thesis introduced into the Strong programme through the materialist presupposition that sense experience is reliable and humans are able to learn about the regularities of the non?social world in order to survive. The second assumption is the causal principle. Arguments developed in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Friends at last? Distributed cognition and the cognitive/social divide.Adam Toon - 2014 - Philosophical Psychology 27 (1):1-14.
    Distributed cognition (d-cog) claims that many cognitive processes are distributed across groups and the surrounding material and cultural environment. Recently, Nancy Nersessian, Ronald Giere, and others have suggested that a d-cog approach might allow us to bring together cognitive and social theories of science. I explore this idea by focusing on the specific interpretation of d-cog found in Edwin Hutchins' canonical text Cognition in the wild. First, I examine the scope of a d-cog approach to science, showing that there are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Muhammad Ali Khalidi: Natural Categories and Human Kinds. Classification in the Natural and Social Sciences.Georg Theiner - 2016 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 47 (1):247-255.
    The notion of 'natural kinds' has been central to contemporary discussions of metaphysics and philosophy of science. In recent years, essentialism has been the dominant account of natural kinds among philosophers, but the essentialist view has encountered resistance. Informed by detailed examination of classification in the natural and social sciences, Prof. Muhammad Ali Khalidi argues against essentialism and for a naturalist account of natural kinds. By looking at case studies drawn from diverse scientific disciplines, from fluid mechanics to virology and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Where do classifications come from? The DSM-III, the transformation of American psychiatry, and the problem of origins in the sociology of knowledge.Michael Strand - 2011 - Theory and Society 40 (3):273-313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hermeneutic culturalism and its double: a key problem in the reflexive modernization debate.Piet Strydom - 1999 - European Journal of Social Theory 2 (1):45-69.
    Proceeding from the debate opened by Beck, Giddens and Lash’s Reflexive Modernization, this paper seeks to clear the way for a more consistent and coherent concept of reflexivity in relation to the cultural-symbolic foundations of society. Seeing that Lash in his contribution to the debate inadvertently raises a key problem, i.e., the broad cognitive problem, the paper develops a critique of his hermeneutic culturalism. It focuses on the disparity between the position explicitly put forward in the debate with Beck and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sociology of scientific knowledge and scientific education: Part I.Peter Slezak - 1994 - Science & Education 3 (3):265-294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Muhammad Ali Khalidi: Natural Categories and Human Kinds. Classification in the Natural and Social Sciences.Carsten Seck & Jacob Rosenthal - 2016 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 47 (1):247-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relativism Due to a Theory of Natural Rationality. The research for this article was fully funded by TAFRESH University, TAFRESH, IRAN, and I should therefore acknowledge their kind support.Zibakalam Saeid - 1997 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 28 (2):337-357.
    Edinburgh School's theory of natural rationality, enunciated to render symmetrical explanation plausible, thereby providing support for its relativism, is presented and evaluated. I have endeavoured to demonstrate that there are gross misinterpretations of Hesse's theory of science, network model, and her conceptions of classification of objects and of universals; that Edinburgh School's theory of natural rationality suffers from a considerable area of ignorance concerning its foundation. I have further shown that not only the theory is not descriptive of the actuality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Critical discussion.David B. Resnik - 1993 - Erkenntnis 38 (2):261 - 271.
    InExplaining Science: A Cognitive Approach, Ronald Giere (1988), proposes what he calls a cognitive theory of science (p. 2). Giere intends his view to be a broadly scientific account employing the resources of the cognitive sciences (Giere, 1988, p. 2). This paper argues that Giere does not secure a firm foundation for a cognitive theory of science because he leaves the door wide open for social constructivist interpretations of his views. In order to avoid social constructivism, Giere needs to adopt (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modeling the Gender Politics in Science.Elizabeth Potter - 1988 - Hypatia 3 (1):19-33.
    Feminist science scholars need models of science that allow feminist accounts, not only of the inception and reception of scientific theories, but of their content as well. I argue that a "Network Model," properly modified, makes clear theoretically how race, sex and class considerations can influence the content of scientific theories. The adoption of the "corpuscular philosophy" by Robert Boyle and other Puritan scientists during the English Civil War offers us a good case on which to test such a model. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The rhetoric of modern economics.Mirowski Philip - 1990 - History of the Human Sciences 3 (2):243-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Grid/Group Analysis for Historians of Science?David R. Oldroyd - 1986 - History of Science 24 (2):145-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Shall I Compare Thee to a Minkowski-Ricardo-Leontief-Metzler Matrix of the Mosak-Hicks Type?: Or, Rhetoric, Mathematics, and the Nature of Neoclassical Economic Theory.Philip Mirowski - 1987 - Economics and Philosophy 3 (1):67-95.
    Is rhetoric just a new and trendy way toépater les bourgeois?Unfortunately, I think that the newfound interest of some economists in rhetoric, and particularly Donald McCloskey in his new book and subsequent responses to critics, gives that impression. After economists have worked so hard for the past five decades to learn their sums, differential calculus, real analysis, and topology, it is a fair bet that one could easily hector them about their woeful ignorance of the conjugation of Latin verbs or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Looking for Those Natural Numbers: Dimensionless Constants and the Idea of Natural Measurement.Philip Mirowski - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (1):165-188.
    The ArgumentMany find it “notoriously difficult to see how societal context can affect in any essential way how someone solves a mathematical problem or makes a measurement.” That may be because it has been a habit of western scientists to assert their numerical schemes were untainted by any hint of anthropomorphism. Nevertheless, that Platonist penchant has always encountered obstacles in practice, primarily because the stability of any applied numerical scheme requires some alien or external warrant.This paper surveys the history of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • In search of the chemical revolution: Interpretive strategies in the history of chemistry.John G. McEvoy - 2000 - Foundations of Chemistry 2 (1):47-73.
    In recent years the Chemical Revolution has become a renewed focus of interest among historians of science. This interest isshaped by interpretive strategies associated with the emergence anddevelopment of the discipline of the history of science. The disciplineoccupies a contested intellectual terrain formed in part by thedevelopment and cultural entanglements of science itself. Threestages in this development are analyzed in this paper. Theinterpretive strategies that characterized each stage are elucidatedand traced to the disciplinary interests that gave rise to them. Whilepositivists (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why Map Issues? On Controversy Analysis as a Digital Method.Noortje Marres - 2015 - Science, Technology, and Human Values 40 (5):655-686.
    This article takes stock of recent efforts to implement controversy analysis as a digital method in the study of science, technology, and society and beyond and outlines a distinctive approach to address the problem of digital bias. Digital media technologies exert significant influence on the enactment of controversy in online settings, and this risks undermining the substantive focus of controversy analysis conducted by digital means. To address this problem, I propose a shift in thematic focus from controversy analysis to issue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On Some Uses and Abuses of Topology in the Social Analysis of Technology.Noortje Marres - 2012 - Theory, Culture and Society 29 (4-5):288-310.
    This paper examines the limits and possibilities of topological approaches in the social analysis of technology. It proposes that topology should be considered not just as a theory to be adopted, but equally as a device that is deployed in social life in a variety of ways. Digital technologies help to make clear why: these technologies have facilitated the spread of a topological imagination, but they have also enabled a weak form of topological imagination, one that leaves in place deterministic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The sociophilosophy of folk psychology.Martin Kusch - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (1):1-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Metaphysical deja vu: Hacking and Latour on science studies and metaphysics - the social construction of what? Ian Hacking; Harvard university press, cambridge, mass. And London, England, 1999, pp. X+261, price £18.50 hardback, ISBN 0-674-81200-X.Pandora's hope: Essays on the reality of science studies Bruno Latour; Harvard university press, cambridge, mass. And London, England, 1999, pp. X+324, price £12.50, $19.95 paperback, ISBN 0-67-465336-X, £27.95, $45.00 hardback, ISBN 0-67-465335-. [REVIEW]M. Kusch - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (3):639-647.
    Ian Hacking, Hacking and Latour on science studies and metaphysics: The Social Construction of What?Harvard University Press, ISBN 0-674-81200-X Bruno Latour, Pandora's Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science StudiesHarvard University Press, ISBN0-67-465336-X.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Social science-based understandings of science: Reflections on Fuller.Arie W. Kruglanski - 1991 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 21 (2):223-231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Realism, Reliabilism, and the 'Strong Programme' in the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.Jeff Kochan - 2008 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 22 (1):21 – 38.
    In this essay, I respond to Tim Lewens's proposal that realists and Strong Programme theorists can find common ground in reliabilism. I agree with Lewens, but point to difficulties in his argument. Chief among these is his assumption that reliabilism is incompatible with the Strong Programme's principle of symmetry. I argue that the two are, in fact, compatible, and that Lewens misses this fact because he wrongly supposes that reliabilism entails naturalism. The Strong Programme can fully accommodate a reliabilism which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hierarchy of scientific consensus and the flow of dissensus over time.Kyung-Man Kim - 1996 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 26 (1):3-25.
    During the last few years, several sociological accounts of scientific consensus appeared in which a radically skeptical view of cognitive consensus in science was advocated. Challenging the traditional realist conception of scientific consensus as a sui generis social fact, the radical skeptics claim to have shown that the traditional historical sociologist's supposedly definitive account of scientific consensus is only a linguistic chimera that easily can be deconstructed by the application of different interpretive schema to the given data. I will argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Durkheim, Wittgenstein and the Norms of Thought.Razmig Keucheyan - 2010 - Diogenes 57 (4):63-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Durkheim, Wittgenstein et les normes de la pensée.Razmig Keucheyan - 2009 - Diogène 228 (4):82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Durkheim, Wittgenstein et les normes de la pensée.Razmig Keucheyan - 2011 - Diogène 4:82-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Science Inside Law: The Making of a New Patent Class in the International Patent Classification.Hyo Yoon Kang - 2012 - Science in Context 25 (4):551-594.
    ArgumentRecent studies of patents have argued that the very materiality and techniques of legal media, such as the written patent document, are vital for the legal construction of a patentable invention. Developing the centrality placed on patent documents further, it becomes important to understand how these documents are ordered and mobilized. Patent classification answers the necessity of making the virtual nature of textual claims practicable by linking written inscription to bureaucracy. Here, the epistemological organization of documents overlaps with the grid (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Mannheim for All Seasons: Bloor, Merton, and the Roots of the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge.David Kaiser - 1998 - Science in Context 11 (1):51-87.
    The ArgumentDavid Bloor often wrote that Karl Mannheim had “stopped short” in his sociology of knowledge, lacking the nerve to consider the natural sciences sociologically. While this assessment runs counter to Mannheim's own work, which responded in quite specific ways both to an encroaching “modernity” and a looming fascism, Bloor's depiction becomes clearer when considered in the light of his principal introduction to Mannheim's work — a series of essays by Robert Merton. Bloor's reading and appropriation of Mannheim emerged from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Rethinking The “strong Programme” In The Sociology Of Knowledge.Adrian Haddock - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (1):19-40.
    It is widely believed that the “strong programme” in the sociology of knowledge comes into serious conflict with mainstream epistemology. I argue that the programme has two aspects—one modest, and the other less so. The programme’s modest aspect—best represented by the “symmetry thesis”—does not contain anything to threaten much of the epistemological mainstream, but does come into conflict with a certain kind of epistemological “externalism”. The immodest aspect, however—in the form of “finitism”—pushes the programme towards a radical form of relativism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Is history and philosophy of science withering on the Vine?Steve Fuller - 1991 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 21 (2):149-174.
    Nearly thirty years after the first stirrings of the Kuhnian revolution, history and philosophy of science continues to galvanize methodological discussions in all corners of the academy except its own. Evidence for this domestic stagnation appears in Warren Schmaus's thoughtful review of Social Epistemology in which Schmaus takes for granted that history of science is the ultimate court of appeal for disputes between philosophers and sociologists. As against this, this essay argues that such disputes may be better treated by experimental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Durkheim’s Epistemology: The Neglected Argument.Ann Rawls & Andrei Korbut - 2014 - Russian Sociological Review 13 (2):84-140.
    Durkheim’s epistemology, the argument for the social origins of the categories of the understanding, is his most important and most neglected argument. This argument has been confused with his sociology of knowledge and Durkheim’s overall position has been misunderstood as a consequence. This lead to the argument that there are two Durkheims: a functionalist positivist and an idealist. The current popularity of a “cultural" or “ideological” interpretation of Durkheim is as much a misunderstanding of his position as the “functional" interpretation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • É a ciência a razão em ação ou ação social sem razão?Alberto Oliva - 2009 - Scientiae Studia 7 (1):105-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark