Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Childbirth Is Not an Emergency: Informed Consent in Labor and Delivery.Allison B. Wolf & Sonya Charles - 2018 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 11 (1):23-43.
    Despite the fact that the requirement to obtain informed consent for medical procedures is deeply enshrined in both U.S. moral and legal doctrine, empirical studies and anecdotal accounts show that women's rights to informed consent and refusal of treatment are routinely undermined and ignored during childbirth. For example, citing the most recent Listening to Mothers survey, Marianne Nieuwenhuijze and Lisa Kane Low state that "a significant number of women said they felt pressure from a caregiver to agree to having an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Informed consent: its origins, purpose, problems, and limits.Nancy M. Kettle - unknown
    The doctrine of informed consent, defined as respect for autonomy, is the tool used to govern the relationship between physicians and patients. Its framework relies on rights and duties that mark these relationships. The main purpose of informed consent is to promote human rights and dignity. Some researchers claim that informed consent has successfully replaced patients' historical predispositions to accept physicians' advice without much explicit resistance. Although the doctrine of informed consent promotes ideals worth pursuing, a successful implementation of these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reconceiving the Therapeutic Obligation.D. Merli & J. A. Smith - 2014 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 39 (1):55-74.
    The “therapeutic obligation” is a physician’s duty to provide his patients with what he believes is the best available treatment. We begin by discussing some prominent formulations of the obligation before raising two related considerations against those formulations. First, they do not make sense of cases where doctors are permitted to provide suboptimal care. Second, they give incorrect results in cases where doctors are choosing treatments in challenging epistemic environments. We then propose and defend an account of the therapeutic obligation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Person-Centered Care, Autonomy, and the Definition of Health.Lily Frank - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (8):59-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Epistemic Humility and Medical Practice: Translating Epistemic Categories into Ethical Obligations.A. Schwab - 2012 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 37 (1):28-48.
    Physicians and other medical practitioners make untold numbers of judgments about patient care on a daily, weekly, and monthly basis. These judgments fall along a number of spectrums, from the mundane to the tragic, from the obvious to the challenging. Under the rubric of evidence-based medicine, these judgments will be informed by the robust conclusions of medical research. In the ideal circumstance, medical research makes the best decision obvious to the trained professional. Even when practice approximates this ideal, it does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Physician-Patient Relationship and a National Health Information Network.Leslie Pickering Francis - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (1):36-49.
    The growing use of interoperable electronic health records is likely to have significant effects on the physician-patient relationship. This relationship involves two-way trust: of the physician in patients, and of the patients in their providers. Interoperable records opens up this relationship to further view, with consequences that may both enhance and undermine trust. On the one hand, physicians may learn that information from their patients is — or is not — to be trusted. On the other hand, patients may learn (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Informed Consent Revisited.Amnon Goldworth - 1996 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 5 (2):214.
    More than three decades after its introduction as a legal requirement for medical treatment in the clinical setting, informed consent continues to be viewed with skepticism as to its need or effectiveness. Some maintain that it is not required because the ordinary individual believes that doctors can be trusted to behave In the best interests of their patients. This issue will be discussed in a later portion of this article. Others are persuaded that informed consent is an unattainable ideal given (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Physicians' silent decisions: Because patient autonomy does not always come first.Simon N. Whitney & Laurence B. McCullough - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):33 – 38.
    Physicians make some medical decisions without disclosure to their patients. Nondisclosure is possible because these are silent decisions to refrain from screening, diagnostic or therapeutic interventions. Nondisclosure is ethically permissible when the usual presumption that the patient should be involved in decisions is defeated by considerations of clinical utility or patient emotional and physical well-being. Some silent decisions - not all - are ethically justified by this standard. Justified silent decisions are typically dependent on the physician's professional judgment, experience and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Ethics in long-term care: Are the principles different?Mark G. Kuczewski - 1999 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 20 (1):15-29.
    It has become common in medical ethics to discuss difficult cases in terms of the principles of respect for autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence, and justice. These moral concepts or principles serve as maxims that are suggestive of appropriate clinical behavior. Because this language evolved primarily in the acute care setting, I consider whether it is in need of supplementation in order to be useful in the long-term care setting. Through analysis of two typical cases involving residents of long-term care facilities, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Spirituality: Respect but don't reveal.Daniel S. Goldberg & Howard Brody - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):21 – 22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Animating Clinical Ethics: A Structured Method to Teach Ethical Analysis Through Movies.Diego Real de Asúa, Karmele Olaciregui Dague, Andrés Arriaga & Benjamin Herreros - 2023 - HEC Forum 35 (4):325-335.
    Movies can serve valuable didactic purposes teaching clinical ethics to medical students. However, using film sequences as means to develop critical thinking is not a straightforward task. There is a significant gap in the literature regarding how to analyse the ethical content embedded in these clips systematically, in a way that facilitates the students’ transition from anecdotal reflections to abstract thinking. This article offers a pedagogical proposal to approach the ethical analysis of film sequences in a systematic fashion. This structured (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Consent Continuum: A New Model of Consent, Assent, and Nondissent for Primary Care.Marc Tunzi, David J. Satin & Philip G. Day - 2021 - Hastings Center Report 51 (2):33-40.
    The practice around informed consent in clinical medicine is both inconsistent and inadequate. Indeed, in busy, contemporary health care settings, getting informed consent looks little like the formal process developed over the past sixty years and presented in medical textbooks, journal articles, and academic lectures. In this article, members of the Society of Teachers of Family Medicine (STFM) Collaborative on Ethics and Humanities review the conventional process of informed consent and its limitations, explore complementary and alternative approaches to doctor‐patient interactions, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Knowledge from scientific expert testimony without epistemic trust.Jon Leefmann & Steffen Lesle - 2020 - Synthese 197 (8):3611-3641.
    In this paper we address the question of how it can be possible for a non-expert to acquire justified true belief from expert testimony. We discuss reductionism and epistemic trust as theoretical approaches to answer this question and present a novel solution that avoids major problems of both theoretical options: Performative Expert Testimony. PET draws on a functional account of expertise insofar as it takes the expert’s visibility as a good informant capable to satisfy informational needs as equally important as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Knowledge from Scientific Expert Testimony without Epistemic Trust.Jon Leefmann & Steffen Lesle - 2018 - Synthese:1-31.
    In this paper we address the question of how it can be possible for a non-expert to acquire justified true belief from expert testimony. We discuss reductionism and epistemic trust as theoretical approaches to answer this question and present a novel solution that avoids major problems of both theoretical options: Performative Expert Testimony (PET). PET draws on a functional account of expertise insofar as it takes the expert’s visibility as a good informant capable to satisfy informational needs as equally important (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Nothing to Fear but Fear itself: HIV-Infected Physicians and the Law of Informed Consent.Kenneth A. De Ville - 1994 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 22 (2):163-175.
    On March 9, 1993, in the first ruling of its kind, the Maryland Court of Appeals declared that physicians and hospitals may be sued for failing to inform patients of a practitioner’s human immunodeficiency virus status. What is more significant, these suits may be pursued even in instances when the physician has followed universal precautions and the patient did not contract the virus that causes acquired immunodeficiency syndrome. The Maryland court addressed two central questions in Faya v. Almaraz. First, do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Informed Consent for Comparative Effectiveness Research Should Include Risks of Standard Care.Lois Shepherd - 2017 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 45 (3):352-364.
    This paper explains why informed consent for randomized comparative effectiveness research must include risks of standard care. Disclosures of such risks are both legally and ethically required and, for reasons discussed in the paper, should remain so.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Physician-Patient Relationship and a National Health Information Network.Leslie Pickering Francis - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (1):36-49.
    The United States, like other countries facing rising health care costs, is pursuing a commitment to interoperable electronic health records. Electronic records, it is thought, have the potential to reduce the risks of error, improve care coordination, monitor care quality, enable patients to participate more fully in care management, and provide the data needed for research and surveillance. Interoperable electronic health records on a national scale — the ideal of a national health information network — seem likely to magnify these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Nothing to Fear But Fear Itself: HIV-Infected Physicians and the Law of Informed Consent.Kenneth A. Ville - 1994 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 22 (2):163-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Truce on the Battlefield: A Proposal for a Different Approach to Medical Informed Consent.August Piper - 1994 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 22 (4):301-313.
    What is informed consent in medicine? For more than a generation, this deceptively simple question has vexed the law, discomfited medicine, and generated much inspired, provocative, and even contentious commentary.The question has also spawned several lawsuits. On one side stand patients who claim that, at the time of consent, they were ignorant of a particular risk; who state that, with more or different information, they would have chosen a different treatment; and who argue that, because of an adverse outcome, they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Health Care Decision Making.S. Joseph Tham & Marie Catherine Letendre - 2014 - The New Bioethics 20 (2):174-185.
    This paper addresses three factors that have contributed to shifts in decision making in health care. First, the notion of patient autonomy, which has changed due to the rise of patient-centred approaches in contemporary health care and the re-conceptualization of the physician-patient relationship. Second, the understanding of patient autonomy has broadened to better engage patient participation. Third, the need to develop cross-cultural health care ethics. Our paper shows that the shift in the West from the individual to the relational self (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Avoiding Surprises: A Model for Informing Patients.Heather J. Gert - 2002 - Hastings Center Report 32 (5):23-32.
    The standard models for what doctors must tell their patients are based on the idea of informed consent: physicians must provide the information that patients need to make treatment decisions. In fact, though, they usually provide considerably more information than this model requires. And rightly so: patients should receive enough information that they will not be surprised by whatever happens—unless the physician is also surprised.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ethics in medicine: Are we blind? In support of teaching medical ethics at the bedside. [REVIEW]John M. Wiecha - 1991 - Journal of Medical Humanities 12 (3):111-117.
    The ability to recognize and respond to the ethical dimension of medicine is integral to providing health care that is comprehensive and humane. However, this aspect of medical practice is underemphasized in clinical and academic medicine, despite attempts to devise curricula in this field. This paper examines the origins and consequences of this deficiency through a case history of a Jehovah's Witness who reluctantly accepted a blood transfusion. It emphasizes the ubiquity of the ethical context in medicine and argues that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Silence about Screening.Peter H. Schwartz - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):46-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Responses to Open Peer Commentaries on "Physicians' Silent Decisions: Because Patient Autonomy Doesn't Always Come First".Simon N. Whitney & Laurence B. McCullough - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):1-3.
    Physicians make some medical decisions without disclosure to their patients. Nondisclosure is possible because these are silent decisions to refrain from screening, diagnostic or therapeutic interventions. Nondisclosure is ethically permissible when the usual presumption that the patient should be involved in decisions is defeated by considerations of clinical utility or patient emotional and physical well-being. Some silent decisions—not all—are ethically justified by this standard. Justified silent decisions are typically dependent on the physician's professional judgment, experience and knowledge, and are not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transparency and Self-Censorship in Shared Decision-Making.Howard Brody - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):44-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truce on the Battlefield: A Proposal for a Different Approach to Medical Informed Consent.August Piper - 1994 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 22 (4):301-313.
    What is informed consent in medicine? For more than a generation, this deceptively simple question has vexed the law, discomfited medicine, and generated much inspired, provocative, and even contentious commentary.The question has also spawned several lawsuits. On one side stand patients who claim that, at the time of consent, they were ignorant of a particular risk; who state that, with more or different information, they would have chosen a different treatment; and who argue that, because of an adverse outcome, they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nothing to Fear But Fear Itself: HIV-Infected Physicians and the Law of Informed Consent.Kenneth A. Ville - 1994 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 22 (2):163-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Informed Consent in the Human Genome Enterprise.Amnon Goldworth - 1995 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 4 (3):296.
    When Jean-Paul Sartre, the French existentialist philosopher, declared some four decades ago that man makes himself, this assertion was based on Sartre's belief that human beings do not possess an essential human nature. Man's self creation had to do with his freedom to choose the roles that he played or could play, and their attendant effects on his attitudes and responsibilities. It said nothing about his freedom to alter his biological nature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consent for organ retrieval cannot be presumed.Mike Collins - 2009 - HEC Forum 21 (1):71-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Silence is not always golden in medical decision-making.John J. Paris & Michael P. Moreland - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):39 – 40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Talking about spirituality in the clinical setting: Can being professional require being personal?Mark G. Kuczewski - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):4 – 11.
    Spirituality or religion often presents as a foreign element to the clinical environment, and its language and reasoning can be a source of conflict there. As a result, the use of spirituality or religion by patients and families seems to be a solicitation that is destined to be unanswered and seems to open a distance between those who speak this language and those who do not. I argue that there are two promising approaches for engaging such language and helping patients (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • From informed consent to substituted judgment: Decision-making at the end-of-life. [REVIEW]Mark Kuczewski - 2004 - HEC Forum 16 (1):27-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Silent decisions or veiled paternalism? Physicians are not experts in judging character.Alexander A. Kon - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):40 – 42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What's wrong with deliberately proselytizing patients?Russell DiSilvestro - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):22 – 24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Healthcare ethics committees and the law: Uneasy but inevitable bedfellows. [REVIEW]Kenneth De Ville & Gregory Hassler - 2001 - HEC Forum 13 (1):13-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations