Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Logic in mathematics and computer science.Richard Zach - forthcoming - In Filippo Ferrari, Elke Brendel, Massimiliano Carrara, Ole Hjortland, Gil Sagi, Gila Sher & Florian Steinberger (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Logic. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    Logic has pride of place in mathematics and its 20th century offshoot, computer science. Modern symbolic logic was developed, in part, as a way to provide a formal framework for mathematics: Frege, Peano, Whitehead and Russell, as well as Hilbert developed systems of logic to formalize mathematics. These systems were meant to serve either as themselves foundational, or at least as formal analogs of mathematical reasoning amenable to mathematical study, e.g., in Hilbert’s consistency program. Similar efforts continue, but have been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tarski’s Undefinability Theorem and the Diagonal Lemma.Saeed Salehi - 2022 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 30 (3):489-498.
    We prove the equivalence of the semantic version of Tarski’s theorem on the undefinability of truth with the semantic version of the diagonal lemma and also show the equivalence of a syntactic version of Tarski’s undefinability theorem with a weak syntactic diagonal lemma. We outline two seemingly diagonal-free proofs for these theorems from the literature and show that the syntactic version of Tarski’s theorem can deliver Gödel–Rosser’s incompleteness theorem.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Finitistic Arithmetic and Classical Logic.Mihai Ganea - 2014 - Philosophia Mathematica 22 (2):167-197.
    It can be argued that only the equational theories of some sub-elementary function algebras are finitistic or intuitive according to a certain interpretation of Hilbert's conception of intuition. The purpose of this paper is to investigate the relation of those restricted forms of equational reasoning to classical quantifier logic in arithmetic. The conclusion reached is that Edward Nelson's ‘predicative arithmetic’ program, which makes essential use of classical quantifier logic, cannot be justified finitistically and thus requires a different philosophical foundation, possibly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Propositional Proof Systems and Fast Consistency Provers.Joost J. Joosten - 2007 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 48 (3):381-398.
    A fast consistency prover is a consistent polytime axiomatized theory that has short proofs of the finite consistency statements of any other polytime axiomatized theory. Krajíček and Pudlák have proved that the existence of an optimal propositional proof system is equivalent to the existence of a fast consistency prover. It is an easy observation that NP = coNP implies the existence of a fast consistency prover. The reverse implication is an open question. In this paper we define the notion of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Weak theories of nonstandard arithmetic and analysis.Jeremy Avigad - manuscript
    A general method of interpreting weak higher-type theories of nonstandard arithmetic in their standard counterparts is presented. In particular, this provides natural nonstandard conservative extensions of primitive recursive arithmetic, elementary recursive arithmetic, and polynomial-time computable arithmetic. A means of formalizing basic real analysis in such theories is sketched.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Partially definable forcing and bounded arithmetic.Albert Atserias & Moritz Müller - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (1):1-33.
    We describe a method of forcing against weak theories of arithmetic and its applications in propositional proof complexity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • PROOF THEORY. Gödel and the metamathematical tradition.Jeremy Avigad - 2010 - In Kurt Gödel, Solomon Feferman, Charles Parsons & Stephen G. Simpson (eds.), Kurt Gödel: essays for his centennial. Ithaca, NY: Association for Symbolic Logic.
    At the turn of the nineteenth century, mathematics exhibited a style of argumentation that was more explicitly computational than is common today. Over the course of the century, the introduction of abstract algebraic methods helped unify developments in analysis, number theory, geometry, and the theory of equations; and work by mathematicians like Dedekind, Cantor, and Hilbert towards the end of the century introduced set-theoretic language and infinitary methods that served to downplay or suppress computational content. This shift in emphasis away (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Number theory and elementary arithmetic.Jeremy Avigad - 2003 - Philosophia Mathematica 11 (3):257-284.
    is a fragment of first-order aritlimetic so weak that it cannot prove the totality of an iterated exponential fimction. Surprisingly, however, the theory is remarkably robust. I will discuss formal results that show that many theorems of number theory and combinatorics are derivable in elementary arithmetic, and try to place these results in a broader philosophical context.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Strict Finitism and the Happy Sorites.Ofra Magidor - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 41 (2):471-491.
    Call an argument a ‘happy sorites’ if it is a sorites argument with true premises and a false conclusion. It is a striking fact that although most philosophers working on the sorites paradox find it at prima facie highly compelling that the premises of the sorites paradox are true and its conclusion false, few (if any) of the standard theories on the issue ultimately allow for happy sorites arguments. There is one philosophical view, however, that appears to allow for at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Quantified propositional calculus and a second-order theory for NC1.Stephen Cook & Tsuyoshi Morioka - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (6):711-749.
    Let H be a proof system for quantified propositional calculus (QPC). We define the Σqj-witnessing problem for H to be: given a prenex Σqj-formula A, an H-proof of A, and a truth assignment to the free variables in A, find a witness for the outermost existential quantifiers in A. We point out that the Σq1-witnessing problems for the systems G*1and G1 are complete for polynomial time and PLS (polynomial local search), respectively. We introduce and study the systems G*0 and G0, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ordinal analysis without proofs.Jeremy Avigad - manuscript
    An approach to ordinal analysis is presented which is finitary, but highlights the semantic content of the theories under consideration, rather than the syntactic structure of their proofs. In this paper the methods are applied to the analysis of theories extending Peano arithmetic with transfinite induction and transfinite arithmetic hierarchies.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Independence results for variants of sharply bounded induction.Leszek Aleksander Kołodziejczyk - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (12):981-990.
    The theory , axiomatized by the induction scheme for sharply bounded formulae in Buss’ original language of bounded arithmetic , has recently been unconditionally separated from full bounded arithmetic S2. The method used to prove the separation is reminiscent of those known from the study of open induction.We make the connection to open induction explicit, showing that models of can be built using a “nonstandard variant” of Wilkie’s well-known technique for building models of IOpen. This makes it possible to transfer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Simple Proof of Parsons' Theorem.Fernando Ferreira - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (1):83-91.
    Let be the fragment of elementary Peano arithmetic in which induction is restricted to -formulas. More than three decades ago, Parsons showed that the provably total functions of are exactly the primitive recursive functions. In this paper, we observe that Parsons' result is a consequence of Herbrand's theorem concerning the -consequences of universal theories. We give a self-contained proof requiring only basic knowledge of mathematical logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Implicit Commitment of Arithmetical Theories and Its Semantic Core.Carlo Nicolai & Mario Piazza - 2019 - Erkenntnis 84 (4):913-937.
    According to the implicit commitment thesis, once accepting a mathematical formal system S, one is implicitly committed to additional resources not immediately available in S. Traditionally, this thesis has been understood as entailing that, in accepting S, we are bound to accept reflection principles for S and therefore claims in the language of S that are not derivable in S itself. It has recently become clear, however, that such reading of the implicit commitment thesis cannot be compatible with well-established positions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Length and structure of proofs.Rohit Parikh - 1998 - Synthese 114 (1):41-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Independence and large cardinals.Peter Koellner - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Saturated models of universal theories.Jeremy Avigad - 2002 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 118 (3):219-234.
    A notion called Herbrand saturation is shown to provide the model-theoretic analogue of a proof-theoretic method, Herbrand analysis, yielding uniform model-theoretic proofs of a number of important conservation theorems. A constructive, algebraic variation of the method is described, providing yet a third approach, which is finitary but retains the semantic flavor of the model-theoretic version.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Transfer principles in nonstandard intuitionistic arithmetic.Jeremy Avigad & Jeffrey Helzner - 2002 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 41 (6):581-602.
    Using a slight generalization, due to Palmgren, of sheaf semantics, we present a term-model construction that assigns a model to any first-order intuitionistic theory. A modification of this construction then assigns a nonstandard model to any theory of arithmetic, enabling us to reproduce conservation results of Moerdijk and Palmgren for nonstandard Heyting arithmetic. Internalizing the construction allows us to strengthen these results with additional transfer rules; we then show that even trivial transfer axioms or minor strengthenings of these rules destroy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Closed Fragment of the Interpretability Logic of PRA with a Constant for $\mathrm{I}\Sigma_1$.Joost J. Joosten - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (2):127-146.
    In this paper we carry out a comparative study of $\mathrm{I}\Sigma_1$ and PRA. We will in a sense fully determine what these theories have to say about each other in terms of provability and interpretability. Our study will result in two arithmetically complete modal logics with simple universal models.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Typical forcings, NP search problems and an extension of a theorem of Riis.Moritz Müller - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (4):102930.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consistency statements and iterations of computable functions in IΣ1 and PRA.Joost J. Joosten - 2010 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 49 (7-8):773-798.
    In this paper we will state and prove some comparative theorems concerning PRA and IΣ1. We shall provide a characterization of IΣ1 in terms of PRA and iterations of a class of functions. In particular, we prove that for this class of functions the difference between IΣ1 and PRA is exactly that, where PRA is closed under iterations of these functions, IΣ1 is moreover provably closed under iteration. We will formulate a sufficient condition for a model of PRA to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark