Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Aesop's fox: Consequentialist virtue meets egocentric bias.Dale L. Clark - 2009 - Philosophical Psychology 22 (6):727 – 737.
    In her book Uneasy Virtue, Julia Driver presents an account of motive or trait utilitarianism, one that has been taken as “the most detailed and thoroughly defended recent formulation” of consequential virtue ethics. On Driver's account character traits are morally virtuous if and only if they generally lead to good consequences for society. Various commentators have taken Driver to task over this account of virtue, which she terms “pure evaluational externalism.” They object that, on Driver's account of virtue, it could (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aspects and algorithms.Andy Clark - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):601-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Did Freud rely on the tally argument to meet the argument from suggestibility?F. Cioffi - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):230-231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Speculative Nature of Our Self Conception: A Reply to Some Criticisms.Paul M. Churchland - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 11:157-173.
    I must begin by thanking the editors for offering me the opportunity to respond to two of the other papers in this collection: ‘A Materialist's Misgivings about Eliminative Materialism,’ by Jeff Foss; and ‘Sensation, Theory, and Meaning,’ by Bonnie Thurston and Sam Coval. In some earlier publications I have defended eliminative materialism at some length, and in others I have argued that the semantics of common observation terms is exhausted by their inferential or conceptual role, to the exclusion of any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Speculative Nature of Our Self Conception: A Reply to Some Criticisms.Paul M. Churchland - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 11:157-173.
    I must begin by thanking the editors for offering me the opportunity to respond to two of the other papers in this collection: ‘A Materialist's Misgivings about Eliminative Materialism,’ by Jeff Foss; and ‘Sensation, Theory, and Meaning,’ by Bonnie Thurston and Sam Coval. In some earlier publications I have defended eliminative materialism at some length, and in others I have argued that the semantics of common observation terms is exhausted by their inferential or conceptual role, to the exclusion of any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leapfrog over the brain.Patricia Smith Churchland - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):73-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cognitive Biases and Errors as Cause—and Journalistic Best Practices as Effect.Sue Ellen Christian - 2013 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 28 (3):160-174.
    This article argues that basic ethical principles of U.S. journalism as described in the Society of Professional Journalists' Code of Ethics are the result of, and a response to, cognitive bias and error. Cognitive biases and errors necessitate journalistic best practices to correct or attenuate them. Social cognitive processes explored include stereotyping, confirmation bias, and attribution. These concepts are noteworthy because each may be activated by the practice of journalism, and each has been shown to be susceptible to attenuation through (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Moral belief attribution: A reply to Roskies.Michael Cholbi - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (5):629 – 638.
    I here defend my earlier doubts that VM patients serve as counterexamples to motivational internalism by highlighting the difficulties of belief attribution in light of holism about the mental and by suggesting that a better understanding of the role of emotions in the self-attribution of moral belief places my earlier Davidsonian "theory of mind" argument in a clearer light.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Belief attribution and the falsification of motive internalism.Michael Cholbi - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (5):607 – 616.
    The metatethical position known as motive internalism (MI) holds that moral beliefs are necessarily motivating. Adina Roskies (in Philosophical Psychology, 16) has recently argued against MI by citing patients with injuries to the ventromedial (VM) cortex as counterexamples to MI. Roskies claims that not only do these patients not act in accordance with their professed moral beliefs, they exhibit no physiological or affective evidence of being motivated by these beliefs. I argue that Roskies' attempt to falsify MI is unpersuasive because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Accessibility “in principle”.Noam Chomsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):600-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Assimilating evidence: The key to revision?Michelene T. H. Chi - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):470-471.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explanatory coherence as a psychological theory.P. C.-H. Cheng & M. Keane - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):469-470.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Covariation in natural causal induction.Patricia W. Cheng & Laura R. Novick - 1992 - Psychological Review 99 (2):365-382.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • A Framework for Unrestricted Prenatal Whole-Genome Sequencing: Respecting and Enhancing the Autonomy of Prospective Parents.Stephanie C. Chen & David T. Wasserman - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (1):3-18.
    Noninvasive, prenatal whole genome sequencing may be a technological reality in the near future, making available a vast array of genetic information early in pregnancy at no risk to the fetus or mother. Many worry that the timing, safety, and ease of the test will lead to informational overload and reproductive consumerism. The prevailing response among commentators has been to restrict conditions eligible for testing based on medical severity, which imposes disputed value judgments and devalues those living with eligible conditions. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • The naked truth about first-person knowledge.Michael Chandler & Jeremy Carpendale - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):36-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Theories or fragments?Nick Chater & Mike Oaksford - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-ascription without qualia: A case study.David J. Chalmers - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):35-36.
    In Section 5 of his interesting article, Goldman suggests that the consideration of imaginary cases can be valuable in the analysis of our psychological concepts. In particular, he argues that we can imagine a system that is isomorphic to us under any functional description, but which lacks qualitative mental states, such as pains and color sensations. Whether or not such a being is empirically possible, it certainly seems to be logically possible, or conceptually coherent. Goldman argues from this possibility to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mental models and nonmonotonic reasoning.Nick Chater - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):340-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mechanistic and rationalistic explanations are complementary.B. Chandrasekaran - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):489-491.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computing the thinkable.David J. Chalmers - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):658-659.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Categorization, theories and folk psychology.Nick Chater - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):37-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The scaffolding of psychoanalysis.Peter Caws - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):229-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • There's more to mental states than meets the inner “l”.Kimberly Wright Cassidy - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • False beliefs and naive beliefs: They can be good for you.Roberto Casati & Marco Bertamini - 2009 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32 (6):512-513.
    Naive physics beliefs can be systematically mistaken. They provide a useful test-bed because they are common, and also because their existence must rely on some adaptive advantage, within a given context. In the second part of the commentary we also ask questions about when a whole family of misbeliefs should be considered together as a single phenomenon.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious mental episodes and skill acquisition.Richard A. Carlson - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):599-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness and content in learning: Missing or misconceived?Richard A. Carlson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):673-674.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • With a friend like Professor Grünbaum does psychoanalysis need any enemies?Arthur Caplan - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):228-229.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowing levels and the child's understanding of mind.Robert L. Campbell & Mark H. Bickhard - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):33-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Kane and Double on the Principle of Rational Explanation.Neil Campbell - 2017 - Dialogue 56 (1):45-63.
    En utilisant le cadre théorique développé par Jaegwon Kim, soit l’opposition entre le réalisme explicatif et l’irréalisme explicatif, ainsi que quelques observations sur la métaphysique et l’épistémologie de l’explication, je réexamine le désaccord opposant Robert Kane à Richard Double au sujet du principe de l’explication rationnelle. Je défends la position de Kane sur la double rationalité et je soutiens que le principe proposé par Double possède un champ d’application plus limité qu’il le prétend. Je montre aussi que, contrairement à ce (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • If human cognition is adaptive, can human knowledge consist of encodings?Robert L. Campbell & Mark H. Bickhard - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):488-489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • How to (Consistently) Reject the Options Argument.Stephen M. Campbell, Joseph A. Stramondo & David Wasserman - 2021 - Utilitas 33 (2):237-245.
    It is commonly thought that disability is a harm or “bad difference” because having a disability restricts valuable options in life. In his recent essay “Disability, Options and Well-Being,” Thomas Crawley offers a novel defense of this style of reasoning and argues that we and like-minded critics of this brand of argument are guilty of an inconsistency. Our aim in this article is to explain why our view avoids inconsistency, to challenge Crawley's positive defense of the Options Argument, and to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The implications of Koehler's approach for fact finding.Craig R. Callen - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):18-18.
    Koehler's work will assist the effort to understand legal fact finding. It leaves two questions somewhat open: (i) the extent to which empirical research can measure correctness of fact-finding, a function that involves the resolution of normative questions and (ii) the standards judges should use in the absence of the research he advocates.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A tale of two cities: emotion and reason in the formation of moral judgement and possible metaethical implications.Susana Cadilha - 2022 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 44 (3):1-27.
    The project of naturalizing ethics has multiple contributions, from cognitive and moral psychology to primatology, neuroscience or evolutionary theory. One of the strategies for naturalizing ethics has been to argue that moral norms and values can be explained away if we focus on their causal history, if it is possible to offer both an ultimate and proximate causal explanation for them. In this article, I will focus on the contribution of cognitive and moral psychology as a way of offering a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The evolutionary point of view: Rationality is elsewhere.Michel Cabanac - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):322-322.
    Baron has provided some examples of nonconsequentialism in decision making and describes them as biases; these may be the remnants of the biological origin of decision making. One may argue that decisions are made on the basis not of rationality but affective processes. Behavior follows the trend toward maximizing pleasure. This mechanism might explain apparent nonconsequentialism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Criteria for optimality.Michel Cabanac - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):218-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The quest for plausibility: A negative heuristic for science?R. W. Byrne - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):217-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards an ecology of mind.George Butterworth - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):31-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Lucas revived? An undefended flank.Jeremy Butterfield - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):658-658.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • “Semantic procedure” is an oxymoron.Alan Bundy - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):339-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Morgan’s Canon, meet Hume’s Dictum: avoiding anthropofabulation in cross-species comparisons.Cameron Buckner - 2013 - Biology and Philosophy 28 (5):853-871.
    How should we determine the distribution of psychological traits—such as Theory of Mind, episodic memory, and metacognition—throughout the Animal kingdom? Researchers have long worried about the distorting effects of anthropomorphic bias on this comparative project. A purported corrective against this bias was offered as a cornerstone of comparative psychology by C. Lloyd Morgan in his famous “Canon”. Also dangerous, however, is a distinct bias that loads the deck against animal mentality: our tendency to tie the competence criteria for cognitive capacities (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Black Boxes or Unflattering Mirrors? Comparative Bias in the Science of Machine Behaviour.Cameron Buckner - 2023 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 74 (3):681-712.
    The last 5 years have seen a series of remarkable achievements in deep-neural-network-based artificial intelligence research, and some modellers have argued that their performance compares favourably to human cognition. Critics, however, have argued that processing in deep neural networks is unlike human cognition for four reasons: they are (i) data-hungry, (ii) brittle, and (iii) inscrutable black boxes that merely (iv) reward-hack rather than learn real solutions to problems. This article rebuts these criticisms by exposing comparative bias within them, in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Acceptance and Managerial Doxastic Agency.Andrei A. Buckareff - 2022 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 99 (3):359-378.
    Managerial doxastic agency is one species of indirect doxastic agency. In this article, the author builds on some earlier work and sketches an account of managerial doxastic agency. In particular, he argues that fairly robust doxastic agency can be exercised by performing metamental actions of non-doxastically accepting propositions as true as part of a general strategy involving various means of mental control. That the sort of control counts as a form of internal control and, hence, as a form of genuine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Theory of How Rumours Arise.Gérald Bronner - 2007 - Diogenes 54 (1):83-105.
    As it happens, we are quite well aware of the origin of a group belief. For instance, the history of baseball in the USA is a kind of contemporary myth whose origin, however, is not mysterious. In the US there is a place called the Hall of Fame dedicated to the great figures in baseball history. The spot can be found in Cooperstown, a small American town in the middle of New York state, that is otherwise totally unremarkable. Why was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intention itself will disappear when its mechanisms are known.Bruce Bridgeman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):598-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • AI and the Turing model of computation.Thomas M. Breuel - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):657-657.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental models cannot exclude mental logic and make little sense without it.Martin D. S. Braine - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):338-339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Algorithms and physical laws.Franklin Boyle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):656-657.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious influences in everyday life and cognitive research.Kenneth S. Bowers - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):672-673.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Moral Manager.Michael G. Bowen & F. Clark Power - 1993 - Business Ethics Quarterly 3 (2):97-115.
    For many, the case of the Exxon Valdez oil spill has become a symbol of unethical corporate behavior. Had Exxon’s managers not callously pursued their own interests at the expense of the environment and other parties, the accident would not have happened. In this paper, we (1) present a short case study of the Valdez incident; (2) argue that many analyses of the case either ignore or fail to give sufficient weight to the uncertainties managers often face when they make (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On “seeing” the truth of the Gödel sentence.George Boolos - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):655-656.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations