Switch to: References

Citations of:

The philosophical disenfranchisement of art

New York: Columbia University Press (1986)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Rorty and Literature.Serge Grigoriev - 2020 - In Alan Malachowski (ed.), A companion to Rorty. Hoboken: Wiley. pp. 411–426.
    This chapter addresses the relationship between Rorty's pragmatist philosophy and his view of literature and literary writing. It begins by examining the relationship between philosophy and literature, construed by Rorty in terms of the opposition between “normal,” professionalized, argument‐centered philosophical discourse and the kind of cultural criticism which emphasizes human finitude and contingency, seeking through the use of irony and literary inventiveness to transform our prevalent visions of what it means to be human. This humanist side of Rorty's argument is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Development of the Sense of 'the End of Art’ in Arthur Danto.Raquel Cascales - 2018 - Rivista di Estetica 68 (2):131-148.
    The striking title The End of Art managed to draw attention to the philosophical work of Arthur Danto. However, the lack of a systematic development which could support this thesis made him face harsh criticism. However, strong foundations for his statements can be deduced from his writings. In this paper, I analyse how to understand the thesis of the ‘end of art’. It should be approached not as a monolitical notion but as a complex concept that combines three different senses: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger’s Philosophy of Art.Kieran Cashell - 2014 - Journal of Critical Realism 13 (1):84-97.
    This essay builds on a review of Iain Thomson’s recent monograph, Heidegger, Art, and Postmodernity, the theme of which is Heidegger’s post-Kehre thinking. Through a series of close textual exegeses, and attentive analyses of concepts, Thomson traces the philosopher’s concern to envisage a means of escaping the late-modern comprehension of being. The latter is characterized, in Thomson’s interpretation, by the ‘technological’ or Nietzschesque understanding of ontology in terms of the eternally recurring will-to-power, according to which objects are identified as intrinsically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Art and ethical criticism: An overview of recent directions of research.Noël Carroll - 2000 - Ethics 110 (2):350-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • The emergence of value: human norms in a natural world.Lawrence Cahoone - 2023 - Albany: State University of New York Press.
    Argues that truth, moral right, political right, and aesthetic value may be understood as arising out of a naturalist account of humanity, if naturalism is rightly conceived.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bernard Smith’s Formalesque and the end of the history of art.Jim Berryman - 2014 - Thesis Eleven 123 (1):3-16.
    The concept of the Formalesque preoccupied Bernard Smith during the last decades of his life. First propounded in Modernism's History (1998), the Formalesque is a proposed period style describing the art of the 20th century. Yet, despite his ambitions for the Formalesque as a new classification for modern art, the idea failed to appeal to academic art history. This paper does not attempt to salvage the Formalesque from art-historical obscurity. But it does argue Smith's work on this topic is relevant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art, politics and knowledge: Feminism, modernity, and the separation of spheres.Amy Mullin - 1996 - Metaphilosophy 27 (1-2):118-145.
    Feminist epistemology and feminist art theory are characterized by an opposition to modernity's separation of art, politics, and knowledge into three autonomous spheres. However, this opposition is not enough to distinguish them from other philosophies. In this paper I examine parallels between the two fields of inquiry in order to discover what makes them distinctively feminist. Feminist epistemology sees interconnections between knowledge and politics, feminist art theory sees connections between art and politics. We need to explore as well connections between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The practical absolute: Fichte’s hidden poetics.Anthony Curtis Adler - 2007 - Continental Philosophy Review 40 (4):407-433.
    The following paper argues that J.G. Fichte, despite his apparent philosophical neglect of art and aesthetics, does develop a strong, original, and coherent account of art, which not only allows the theorization of modern, non-representative art forms, but indeed anticipates Nietzsche and Heidegger in conceiving of truth in terms of art rather than scientific rationality. While the basis of Fichte’s philosophy of art is presented in the essay “On Spirit and Letter in Philosophy,” it is not developed systematically either in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology.Herman Cappelen, Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.) - 2016 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    This is the most comprehensive book ever published on philosophical methodology. A team of thirty-eight of the world's leading philosophers present original essays on various aspects of how philosophy should be and is done. The first part is devoted to broad traditions and approaches to philosophical methodology. The entries in the second part address topics in philosophical methodology, such as intuitions, conceptual analysis, and transcendental arguments. The third part of the book is devoted to essays about the interconnections between philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Philosophy, literature, and the death of art.Stephanie Ross - 1989 - Philosophical Papers 18 (1):95-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paths from the Philosophy of Art to Everyday Aesthetics.Oiva Kuisma, Sanna Lehtinen & Harri Mäcklin (eds.) - 2019 - Helsinki, Finland: Finnish Society for Aesthetics.
    During the past few decades, everyday aesthetics has established itself as a new branch of philosophical aesthetics alongside the more traditional philosophy of art. The Paths from Philosophy of Art to Everyday Aesthetics explores the intimate relations between these two branches of contemporary aesthetics. The essays collected in this volume discuss a wide range of topics from aesthetic intimacy to the nature of modernity and the essence of everydayness, which play important roles both in the philosophy of art and everyday (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Origin of the Discussion of Author’s Intention in American Criticism and Philosophy.Alexander Yudin - 2015 - Sententiae 32 (1):60-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Sport Unique? A Question of Definability.S. K. Wertz - 1995 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 22 (1):83-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Metaphor and Prop Oriented Make‐Believe.Kendall L. Walton - 1993 - European Journal of Philosophy 1 (1):39-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • ¿Qué es el arte y qué constituye el valor artístico?Jordi Tena Sánchez & Indira Centellas - 2022 - Pensamiento. Revista de Investigación E Información Filosófica 78 (297):199-228.
    El presente artículo se basa en la teoría de la creatividad artística de Jon Elster para tratar de ofrecer un esbozo de definición del concepto de arte, así como las bases para una teoría del valor artístico. Se sostiene que una obra de arte es una creación humana realizada con la intención de provocar una experiencia estética, así como que el principal valor de una obra de arte radica en su capacidad para producir emociones estéticas y no estéticas. Dicha concepción (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Artistic Disenfranchisement of Philosophy.Carole Talon-Hugon - 2012 - Diogenes 59 (1-2):168-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Què és la “filosofia del cinema”? Una panoràmica sobre l’estat de la qüestió.Javier Ruiz Moscardó - 2018 - Quaderns de Filosofia 5 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Interpret?Joseph Raz - 1996 - Ratio Juris 9 (4):349-363.
    My article is about legal interpretation, but not about the question: how to interpret the law. Rather its aim is to make us consider seriously the question: Why is interpretation central to legal practices? After all not all normative practices assign interpretation such a central role. In this regard the law contrasts with morality. The reason for the contrast has to do with the status of sources in the law. There are no “moral sources” while legal sources are central to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Literature, Ethics, and Richard Rorty’s Pragmatist Theory of Interpretation.Kalle Puolakka - 2008 - Philosophia 36 (1):29-41.
    This article considers the validity and strength of Richard Rorty’s pragmatist theory of interpretation in the light of two ethical issues related to literature and interpretation. Rorty’s theory is rejected on two grounds. First, it is argued that his unrestrained account of interpretation is incompatible with the distinctive moral concerns that have been seen to restrict the scope and nature of valid approaches to artworks. The second part of the paper claims that there is no indispensable relationship between supporting Rorty’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The aesthetics of nature.Glenn Parsons - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (3):358–372.
    The aesthetics of nature is a growing sub-field of contemporary aesthetics. In this article, I outline the view called ‘Scientific cognitivism’, which has been central in recent discussions of nature aesthetics. In assessing two important arguments for this view, I outline some recent thinking about key issues for the aesthetics of nature, including the relationship between nature and art and the relevance of ethical considerations to the aesthetic appreciation of nature.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Technical Creativity, Material Engagement and the (Controversial) Role of Language.Pietro Montani - 2019 - Aisthesis. Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 12 (2):27-37.
    For several hundred thousand years, the genus homo deployed a characteristic technical creativity, communicating and transmitting its outcomes, together with its operative protocols, without the available recourse to articulated language. The thesis proposed here is that the aforementioned functions should be attributed to a complex intertwining of embodied abilities, which can in turn be ascribed to the classic philosophical concept of imagination. It is through imagination that the human becomes involved in material engagement, by virtue of which its extended mind (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Literary Fictions as Utterances and Artworks.Jukka Mikkonen - 2010 - Theoria 76 (1):68-90.
    During the last decades, there has been a debate on the question whether literary works are utterances, or have utterance meaning, and whether it is reasonable to approach them as such. Proponents of the utterance model in literary interpretation, whom I will refer to as “utterance theorists”, such as Noël Carroll and especially Robert Stecker, suggest that because of their nature as linguistic products of intentional human action, literary works are utterances similar to those used in everyday discourse. Conversely, those (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • In quest of modern culture: Hysterical or historical humanism.J. G. Merquior - 1991 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 5 (3):399-420.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art and philosophy: Rivals or partners?Llewellyn Negrin - 2005 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 31 (7):801-822.
    Ever since the time of Hegel, there has been a growing philosophization of art in which artists increasingly make works where visual/formal concerns are supplanted by philosophical questions concerning the definition of art itself. At the same time, however, an equally vociferous defence of art against its subsumption by philosophy has been made by theorists such as Nietzsche, Sontag and Barthes who have sought to rescue the sensuous immediacy of art from the abstractness of philosophical thought by advocating a more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art and philosophy: Rivals or partners?Negrin Llewellyn - 2005 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 31 (7):801-822.
    Ever since the time of Hegel, there has been a growing philosophization of art in which artists increasingly make works where visual/formal concerns are supplanted by philosophical questions concerning the definition of art itself. At the same time, however, an equally vociferous defence of art against its subsumption by philosophy has been made by theorists such as Nietzsche, Sontag and Barthes who have sought to rescue the sensuous immediacy of art from the abstractness of philosophical thought by advocating a more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sensory Force, Sublime Impact, and Beautiful Form.Eli I. Lichtenstein - 2019 - British Journal of Aesthetics 59 (4):449-464.
    Can a basic sensory property like a bare colour or tone be beautiful? Some, like Kant, say no. But Heidegger suggests, plausibly, that colours ‘glow’ and tones ‘sing’ in artworks. These claims can be productively synthesized: ‘glowing’ colours are not beautiful; but they are sensory forces—not mere ‘matter’, contra Kant—with real aesthetic impact. To the extent that it inheres in sensible properties, beauty is plausibly restricted to structures of sensory force. Kant correspondingly misrepresents the relation of beautiful wholes to their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Re-enfranchising Art: Feminist Interventions in the Theory of Art.Estella Lauter - 1990 - Hypatia 5 (2):91-106.
    Feminist analyses of the roles gender has played in art lead to an alternative theory that emphasizes art's complex interactions with culture(s) rather than the autonomy within culture claimed for it by formalism. Focusing on the visual arts, I extrapolate the new theory from feminist research and compare it with formalist precepts. Sharing Arthur Danto's concern that art has been disenfranchised in the twentieth century by its preoccupation with theory, I claim that feminist thought re-enfranchises art by revisioning its relationship (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Sport as a drama.Lev Kreft - 2012 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39 (2):219-234.
    Argument of this text is that: to develop aesthetics of sport, we should not begin with aesthetics as philosophy of art but with aesthetics of everyday life; to start with aesthetics of sport, we should not begin with beautiful of ‘pure aesthetics’ but with the dramatic; to analyze the dramatic in sport, we should not open the analysis with analogy between theater and sport, but with sport as a sort of performance; to get at the meaning of sport as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The end of high culture and the Anthropocene.Harriet Johnson - 2020 - Thesis Eleven 160 (1):84-94.
    Theories of a new phase of earth history, the Anthropocene, position human world-making activity as a bio-geological force. Social interventions into earth systems have been extensive and malignant, altering the earth’s surface, atmosphere, oceans, and systems of nutrient cycling. To adapt and respond to emerging planetary dangers requires the collaboration of scholars from many different disciplines. In this paper, I argue that a coalition of the arts and sciences might draw upon György Márkus’s extensive studies of the topography of ‘high’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sobre la historia del arte que nos merecemos.Vicente Jarque Soriano - 2018 - Estudios de Filosofía (Universidad de Antioquia) 58:197-213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nothing New Under the Sun: Holism and the Pursuit of Excellence.Jesús Ilundáin-Agurruza - 2014 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 8 (3):230-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Theoretical Practice: the Bohm-Pines Quartet.R. I. G. Hughes - 2006 - Perspectives on Science 14 (4):457-524.
    Quite rightly, philosophers of physics examine the theories of physics, theories like Quantum Mechanics, Quantum Field Theory, the Special and General Theories of Relativity, and Statistical Mechanics. Far fewer, however, examine how these theories are put to use; that is to say, little attention is paid to the practices of theoretical physicists. In the early 1950s David Bohm and David Pines published a sequence of four papers, collectively entitled, ‘A Collective Description of Electron Interaction.’ This essay uses that quartet as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Beyond the nature-culture dualism.Yrjö Haila - 2000 - Biology and Philosophy 15 (2):155-175.
    It is commonly accepted that thewestern view of humanity's place in nature isdominated by a dualistic opposition between nature andculture. Historically this has arisen fromexternalization of nature in both productive andcognitive practices; instances of such externalizationhave become generalized. I think the dualism can bedecomposed by identifying dominant elements in eachparticular instantiation and showing that their strictseparation evaporates under close scrutiny. The philosophical challenge this perspective presents isto substitute concrete socioecological analysis forfoundational metaphysics. A review of majorinterpretations of the history of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The institutional theory of art: A survey.David Graves - 1997 - Philosophia 25 (1-4):51-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Searching for the 'popular' and the 'art' of popular art.Theodore Gracyk - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (3):380–395.
    Philosophy of art presupposes differences between art and other cultural activity. Philosophers have recently paid more attention to this excluded activity, particularly to the range of cultural production known as popular art. Three issues have dominated these discussions. First, there is debate about the basis of the distinction. Some philosophers contend that fine art is essentially different from popular art, but others hold that the distinction is entirely social in origin. Second, philosophers disagree on the degree of continuity or discontinuity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • El discurso del fin: historia, arte y filosofía.Marta García Rodríguez - 2018 - Daimon: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 73:151-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Isto é um cachimbo.Virginia Figueiredo - 2005 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 46 (112):442-457.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quaderns de filosofia V, 1.Quad Fia - 2018 - Quaderns de Filosofia 5 (1).
    Quaderns de filosofia V, 1 Número complet / Número completo / Full Issue.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art and Aesthetics: From Modern to Contemporary.Aleš Erjavec - 2012 - Diogenes 59 (1-2):148-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Aesthetics of The Olympic Art Competitions.Andrew Edgar - 2012 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39 (2):185-199.
    In the Olympic Art Competitions (1912–1948) Pierre de Coubertin expresses his conception of both sport and art as instruments of moral renewal. In this paper, this conception is criticised for failing to appreciate art and sport as necessary manifestations of modernism. The Art Competitions were informed by a traditionalist aesthetic, and thus played a highly conservative role within Olympism. A modernist art about sport, in contrast, would have been a source of critical reflection, potentially protecting the Olympic movement from corrupting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Poetics of Conspiracy and Hermeneutics of Suspicion in Tacitus's Dialogus de Oratoribus.Alex Dressler - 2013 - Classical Antiquity 32 (1):1-34.
    This article argues that the end of Tacitus's Dialogus de Oratoribus is inconclusive in ways that draw attention to the difficulty of interpretation not only of the dialogue, as by modern scholars, but also in the dialogue, as by its leading characters. The inconclusiveness is especially marked by a commonly noted, but little discussed, feature of the end: when the rest of the characters laugh at the point of departure, Tacitus himself does not. Arguing that this difference of affective response (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The concept of the aesthetic.James Shelley - 2017 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Introduced into the philosophical lexicon during the Eighteenth Century, the term ‘aesthetic’ has come to be used to designate, among other things, a kind of object, a kind of judgment, a kind of attitude, a kind of experience, and a kind of value. For the most part, aesthetic theories have divided over questions particular to one or another of these designations: whether artworks are necessarily aesthetic objects; how to square the allegedly perceptual basis of aesthetic judgments with the fact that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The Buck Passing Theory of Art.James O. Young - 2016 - Symposion: Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences 3 (4): 421-433.
    In Beyond Art (2014), Dominic Lopes proposed a new theory of art, the buck passing theory. Rather than attempting to define art in terms of exhibited or genetic featured shared by all artworks, Lopes passes the buck to theories of individual arts. He proposes that we seek theories of music, painting, poetry, and other arts. Once we have these theories, we know everything there is to know about the theory of art. This essay presents two challenges to the theory. First, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • El lugar común de la transfiguración. Historia, representación y filosofía de las asimetrías en Arthur Danto.Nicolás Lavagnino - 2015 - Páginas de Filosofía (Universidad Nacional del Comahue) 16 (19):33-57.
    El presente artículo se propone mostrar la vinculación conceptual que se establece en el conjunto de la obra de Arthur Danto –un autor clave en la consideración analítica del concepto de representación- entre asimetrías cognitivas, teoría de la representación y criterio transfigurativo de realidad. Esa articulación nos entrega un modelo de particular predilección por las asimetrías cognitivas vinculadas a la estructura trágica, que es limitativa de las posibilidades aventuradas por el mismo Danto respecto de nuestra capacidad para captar la apertura (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Danto y la mímesis: más allá del fin del arte.Mariana Castillo Merlo - 2015 - Páginas de Filosofía (Universidad Nacional del Comahue) 16 (19):114-133.
    En Después del fin del arte, Danto se refiere a la mímesis como un estilo artístico y como la respuesta filosófica a la pregunta acerca de qué es el arte. En el panorama del arte contemporáneo, la mímesis se habría agotado y no tendría ningún papel activo que cumplir. El objetivo de mi trabajo será mostrar cómo Danto construye un relato legitimador en torno a la mímesis que le permite justificar su tesis sobre el fin del arte. Luego, señalaré los (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tomándose la historia en serio. Danto, esencialismo histórico e indiscernibles.Veronica Tozzi - 2007 - Revista de Filosofía (Madrid) 32 (2):109-126.
    The place that Arthur Danto gives to history, as constitutive to as and our world, as well as a discipline able to produce knowledge of the past, reach its cenit with his philosophy of art. In “the End of Art”, Danto announces an end of the history of the search of the philosophical definition of art and the beginning of the era of pluralism. It is in this account where essencialism and historicism are combined in a way that estimules a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Imperceptibility of Style in Danto's Theory of Art: Metaphor and the Artist's Knowledge.Stephen Snyder - 2015 - CounterText 1 (3).
    Arthur Danto’s analytic theory of art relies on a form of artistic interpretation that requires access to the art theoretical concepts of the artworld, ‘an atmosphere of artistic theory, a knowledge of the history of art: an artworld’. Art, in what Danto refers to as post-history, has become theoretical, yet it is here contended that his explanation of the artist’s creative style lacks a theoretical dimension. This article examines Danto’s account of style in light of the role the artistic metaphor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From the "mere thing" to the meaning of the work of art in the philosophy of Arthur Danto.Adryan Fabrizio Pineda Repizzo - 2012 - Universitas Philosophica 29 (58):277-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark