Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Limits of Mindfulness: Emerging Issues for Education.Terry Hyland - 2016 - British Journal of Educational Studies 64 (1):97-117.
    Mindfulness-based interventions (MBIs) are being actively implemented in a wide range of fields – psychology, mind/body health care and education at all levels – and there is growing evidence of their effectiveness in aiding present-moment focus, fostering emotional stability, and enhancing general mind/body well-being. However, as often happens with popular innovations, the burgeoning interest in and appeal of mindfulness practice has led to a reductionism and commodification – popularly labelled ‘McMindfulness’ – of the underpinning principles and ethical foundations of such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The ‘Physically Educated’ Person: Physical education in the philosophy of Reid, Peters and Aristotle.James MacAllister - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (9):908-920.
    This article will derive a definition and account of the physically educated person, through an examination of the philosophy of Andrew Reid, Richard Peters and Aristotle. Initially, Reid’s interpretation of Peters’ views about the educational significance of practical knowledge (and physical education) will be considered. While it will be acknowledged that Peters was rather disparaging about the educational merit of some practical activities in Ethics and Education, it will be argued that he elsewhere suggests that such practical activities could be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the Possible Non‐Existence of Emotions: The Passions.John Sabini & Maury Silver - 1996 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 26 (4):375-398.
    This paper attempts to demonstrate, at least for the passions, that while emotions are important elements of common sense psychological thought, they are not psychological, neural, or mental entities. People talk of emotions, we claim, in two sorts of cases: Firstly, when it is believed that someone has done something that she shouldn't because she has been overwhelmed by desire and secondly, when someone is found to be compelled to devote cognitive resources to an act she knows she will never (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Lack of Discipline.R. A. Becher - 1974 - Philosophy 49 (188):205 - 211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can Kant have an account of moral education?Kate A. Moran - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (4):471-484.
    There is an apparent tension between Immanuel Kant's model of moral agency and his often-neglected philosophy of moral education. On the one hand, Kant's account of moral knowledge and decision-making seems to be one that can be self-taught. Kant's famous categorical imperative and related 'fact of reason' argument suggest that we learn the content and application of the moral law on our own. On the other hand, Kant has a sophisticated and detailed account of moral education that goes well beyond (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Autonomy, emotions and desires: Some problems concerning R. F. Dearden's account of autonomy.Carolyn M. Stone - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 24 (2):271–283.
    Carolyn M Stone; Autonomy, Emotions and Desires: some problems concerning R. F. Dearden's account of autonomy, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 24, Is.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Child-centred education and the 'growth' metaphysic.Charles Clark - 1988 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 22 (1):75–88.
    Charles Clark; Child-centred Education and the ‘Growth’ Metaphysic, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 22, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 75–88, https://do.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A “Strong” Approach to Sustainability Literacy: Embodied Ecology and Media.Cary Campbell, Nataša Lacković & Alin Olteanu - 2021 - Philosophies 6 (1):14.
    This article outlines a “strong” theoretical approach to sustainability literacy, building on an earlier definition of strong and weak environmental literacy (Stables and Bishop 2001). The argument builds upon a specific semiotic approach to educational philosophy (sometimes called edusemiotics), to which these authors have been contributing. Here, we highlight how a view of learning that centers on embodied and multimodal communication invites bridging biosemiotics with critical media literacy, in pursuit of a strong, integrated sustainability literacy. The need for such a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Romanticism and Romantic Science: Their Contribution to Science Education.Yannis Hadzigeorgiou & Roland Schulz - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (10):1963-2006.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ideals of freedom and the ethics of thought – meaning and mystique.Suninn Yun - 2016 - Ethics and Education 11 (2):197-212.
    This paper considers prominent forms of discourse in educational research, the nature of their appeal and the force of the idea of freedom within that appeal. For this, two different aspects of research are juxtaposed, aspects in which the value of freedom is articulated in contrasting ways. First, evidence-based education is considered as a prominent manifestation of faith in scientific method in education: in this, it might be said, there is an obsession with freedom – the freedom of the research (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Liberty and Compulsory Education.Peter Gardner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 15:109-129.
    Although it is primarily concerned with the value of liberty and the justification of compulsory education, what lies behind much of this paper is the question ‘;Why treat children like children?’ The fact is that we do not regard children as having the same rights, privileges and liberties as adults, and children may not be thought of as deserving the same degree of respect or consideration as their seniors. In the past this has led to some horrific states of affairs, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • My two 'difficulties'.Charlene Tan - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (4):639–662.
    I shall respond to Michael Hand’s rejoinder in respect of the two ‘difficulties’ he has identified with my arguments.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A defence of autonomy as an educational ideal.Jeffrey Morgan - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 30 (2):239–252.
    This paper argues that autonomy is an educational ideal. Since personal autonomy is essentially a matter of the person governing herself, a plausible account of autonomy presupposes an account of u person's identity. I support a conception of autonomy which presupposes a hierarchical theory of the self, yet allows rationality a significant place in a person's identity. I defend this conception of autonomy as an educational ideal from recent criticisms by Stone (1990) and Cuypers (1992).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Teaching and Learning: Epistemic, Metaphysical and Ethical Dimensions—Introduction.David Bakhurst - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (2):255-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Wittgenstein's Impact on the Philosophy of Education.Paul Standish - 2018 - Philosophical Investigations 41 (2):223-240.
    On the strength of a clarification of the nature of philosophy of education, a critical overview is offered of Wittgenstein's impact on the field. The focus then narrows to give attention to Wittgenstein's claim that “Nothing is hidden”, pitched here in a questionable relation to contemporary concerns with transparency. Familiar readings of this passage are challenged in connection with Wittgenstein's late writings on psychology, especially with regard to imagination and pretence. These are argued to be essential to the development of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • ‘‘‘don’t Know Much About The French I Took’: A Contemporary Case For Second Language Study In The Liberal Arts.Timothy Reagan - 2004 - Arts and Humanities in Higher Education 3 (2):229-239.
    Language study can be immensely valuable, but language educators have typically relied on arguments and defenses of second/foreign language study that confuse the benefits of language knowledge with those of language study. In this article, an effort is made to identify three kinds of alternative arguments that might be used for advocating second/ foreign language study as part of the general education of the university student.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant on education and improvement: Themes and problems.Martin Sticker & David Bakhurst - 2021 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 55 (6):909-920.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Rethinking educational theory and practice in times of visual media: Learning as image-concept integration.Nataša Lacković & Alin Olteanu - 2020 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 53 (6):597-612.
    We propose a new relational direction in higher education that acknowledges external and internal images as integrated in thinking and learning. We expand educational theory and practice that commonly rely on discrete conceptual developments that exclude images. Our argument epistemologically relies on certain semiotic views that consider the role of iconic signs and iconicity (meaning making by the virtue of similarity) as significant in relation to knowledge and learning. The analogical and imaginative work required to discover similarity between external pictures (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Basic problems of a critical theory of education.Helmut Peukertruth - 1993 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 27 (2):159–169.
    ABSTRACT Education is in itself a project of Enlightenment. The critical theory of the Frankfurt School, whose origin and development bear the imprint of self-destructive social-cultural processes of modernity and of the Holocaust, can count as an attempt to continue the process of Enlightenment through radical self-criticism. The paper presents the approach of the first generation of critical theory and then Jurgen Habermas' critique of this approach and his reconstruction of critical theory in his theory of communicative action. Special emphasis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Education for autonomy: The role of religious elementary schools.Ian MacMullen - 2004 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (4):601–615.
    I argue that religious elementary schools whose pedagogical methods satisfy the principle of rational authority have distinctive advantages over secular elementary schools for the purpose of laying the foundations for ethical autonomy in the children of religious parents. Insights from developmental psychology bolster the argument from conceptual analysis. Before children have the cognitive capacities to engage in authentically autonomous reflection, their long-run interest in developing autonomy is best served by developing their understanding of and provisional identity within their primary culture (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Knowledge, mind and the curriculum.David Carr - 1984 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 16 (1):12–22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophy of Education: Becoming Less Western, More African?Penny Enslin & Kai Horsthemke - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 50 (2):177-190.
    Posing the question ‘How diverse is philosophy of education in the West?’ this paper responds to two recent defences of African philosophy of education which endorse its communitarianism and oppose individualism in Western philosophy of education. After outlining Thaddeus Metz's argument that Western philosophy of education should become more African by being more communitarian, and Yusef Waghid's defence of communitarianism in African philosophy of education, we develop a qualified defence of aspects of individualism in education. Our reservations about some aspects (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Encouraging a “Romantic Understanding” of Science: The Effect of the Nikola Tesla Story.Yannis Hadzigeorgiou, Stephen Klassen & Cathrine Froese Klassen - 2012 - Science & Education 21 (8):1111-1138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Practical rationality in education: beyond the Hirst–Carr debate.Koichiro Misawa - 2023 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 57 (1):164-181.
    Paul Hirst’s philosophical ‘conversion’ from forms of knowledge to forms of social practices was largely prompted by his radical reappraisal of the philosophical underpinnings that had validated his classic conception of liberal education. The primary motivation for Hirst’s later works was to remedy his own neglect of practical reason, whose sharp distinction from theoretical reason he acknowledged he had failed to appreciate. There is much to commend in his ‘practical’ turn. The main challenge that remains, however, is that the social (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Liberty and Compulsory Education.Peter Gardner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 15:109-129.
    Although it is primarily concerned with the value of liberty and the justification of compulsory education, what lies behind much of this paper is the question ‘;Why treat children like children?’ The fact is that we do not regard children as having the same rights, privileges and liberties as adults, and children may not be thought of as deserving the same degree of respect or consideration as their seniors. In the past this has led to some horrific states of affairs, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Critique of Science Education as Sociopolitical Action from the Perspective of Liberal Education.Yannis Hadzigeorgiou - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (3):259-280.
    This paper outlines the rationale underpinning the conception of science education as sociopolitical action, and then presents a critique of such a conception from the perspective of liberal education. More specifically, the paper discusses the importance of the conception of science education as sociopolitical action and then raises questions about the content of school science, about the place and value of scientific inquiry, and about the opportunities students have for self-directed inquiry. The central idea behind the critique is that a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Education for Critical Thinking: Can it be non‐indoctrinative?Ishtiyaque Haji Stefaan E. Cuypers - 2006 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 38 (6):723-743.
    An ideal of education is to ensure that our children develop into autonomous critical thinkers. The ‘indoctrination objection’, however, calls into question whether education, aimed at cultivating autonomous critical thinkers, is possible. The core of the concern is that since the young child lacks even modest capacities for assessing reasons, the constituent components of critical thinking have to be indoctrinated if there is to be any hope of the child's attaining the ideal. Our primary objective is to defuse this objection. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations