Switch to: References

Citations of:

Καθαρσισ παθηματων

Hermes 75 (1):81-92 (1940)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Anaximander and the origins of Greek cosmology.Charles H. Kahn - 1960 - Indianapolis: Hackett.
    Through criticism and analysis of ancient traditions, Kahn reconstructs the pattern of Anaximander’s thought using historical methods akin to the reconstructive techniques of comparative linguists.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • O que é "verdadeiro, mas não esclarecedor" segundo a Ética Eudêmia.Raphael Zillig - 2017 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 20:231-254.
    In Eudemian Ethics I 6, Aristotle describes the progress of the ethical investigation as a drift from a) what is true but not clarifying to b) what is true and clarifying. The drift from a) to b) is usually interpreted as the overcome of a first obscure and confused grasp of the subject by a more accurate and reliable account. In this paper, I claim that the understanding of the methodological role of a) depends upon its dissociation from the notions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Complete Life in the Eudemian Ethics.Hilde Vinje - 2023 - Apeiron: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 53 (2):299–323.
    In the Eudemian Ethics II 1, 1219a34–b8, Aristotle defines happiness as ‘the activity of a complete life in accordance with complete virtue’. Most scholars interpret a complete life as a whole lifetime, which means that happiness involves virtuous activity over an entire life. This article argues against this common reading by using Aristotle’s notion of ‘activity’ (energeia) as a touchstone. It argues that happiness, according to the Eudemian Ethics, must be a complete activity that reaches its end at any and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotelian Piety.Sarah Broadie - 2003 - Phronesis 48 (1):54-70.
    Aristotle seems to omit discussing the virtue piety. Such an omission should surprise us. Piety is not covertly dealt with under the more general heading of justice, nor under that of philia. But piety does make a veiled appearance at NE X.8, 1179a22-32. Many interpreters have refused to take this passage seriously, but this is shown to be a mistake.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dossier: eudemian ethics.Raphael Zillig - 2017 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 20:79-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Standard Aversion to the Agrapha Dogmata.Thomas A. Szlezák - 2010 - Peitho 1 (1):57-74.
    The present paper deals with eight charges that are frequently leveled against any research that focuses on the agrapha dogmata. The charges are demonstrated to be completely unfounded and, therefore, duly dismissed. In particular, it is argued here that the phrase ta legomena is by no means to be understood as ironic. Consequently, the article rejects the very common picture of Plato as some sort of dogmatist and author of a fixed philosophical system. However, Plato’s philosophy is presented as rather (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Colloquium 4.David Sedley - 1991 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 7 (1):146-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bestiary of the aristotelian Ethics.Louise Rodrigue - 2015 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 15:21-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O método para a investigação da definição da justiça na Ética Nicomachea V.Carlo Natali - 2013 - Doispontos 10 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What Aristotelian Decisions Cannot Be.Jozef Müller - 2016 - Ancient Philosophy 36 (1):173-195.
    I argue that Aristotelian decisions (προαιρέσεις) cannot be conceived of as based solely on wish (βούλησις) and deliberation (βούλευσις), as the standard picture (most influentially argued for in Anscombe's "Thought and Action in Aristotle", in R. Bambrough ed. New Essays on Plato and Aristotle. London: Routledge, 1965) suggests. Although some features of the standard view are correct (such as that decisions have essential connection to deliberation and that wish always plays a crucial role in the formation of a decision), Aristotelian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Mesocosmological Descriptions: An Essay in the Extensional Ontology of History.Nikolay Milkov - 2006 - Essays in Philosophy 7 (2):1-17.
    The following paper advances a new argument for the thesis that scientific and historical knowledge are not different in type. This argument makes use of a formal ontology of history which dispenses with generality, laws and causality. It views the past social world as composed of Wittgenstein’s Tractarian objects: of events, ordered in ontological dependencies. Theories in history advance models of past reality which connect—in experiment—faces of past events in complexes. The events themselves are multi-grained so that we can connect (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle on Prohairesis.Liu Wei - 2016 - Labyrinth: An International Journal for Philosophy, Value Theory and Sociocultural Hermeneutics 18 (2):50-74.
    Prohairesis plays a central role in Aristotle's moral psychology. It is prohairesis that determines an action to be rational, that provides the proximate efficient or moving cause of rational action, and that better reveals one's character than the action itself. This paper will discuss Aristotle's shifted emphases when speaking of prohairesis in different ethical treatises; Aristotle's pursuit of the nature of prohairesis and his special argumentative strategy in dealing with prohairesis; the structure, i.e., the desiderative and deliberative components of prohairesis; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle on Self-Perception and Pleasure.Manuel C. Ortiz de Landázuri - 2012 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 6 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Conflict and Cosmopolitanism in Plato and the Stoics.Owen Goldin - 2011 - Apeiron 44 (3):264-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fundamentos físicos y metafísicos de la ética para Aristóteles.John Dudley - 2018 - Areté. Revista de Filosofía 30 (1):7-21.
    “Physical and Metaphysical Foundations of Aristotelian Ethics”. Leading scholars have regarded Aristotle’s ethics as a kind of dialectical reasoning based on popular opinions and without any sound philosophical foundation. In this paper I shall attempt to show, against them, that Aristotle’s ethics has a physical and a metaphysical foundation as well. Aristotle conceives of ethics metaphysically, given the centrality of his concept of God in his ethical thought. Furthermore, the conception of life behind it comes from his natural philosophy, specifically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Phaedo 100B3-9.Ravi Sharma - 2015 - Mnemosyne 68 (3):393-412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations