Switch to: References

Citations of:

Mathematical Psychics

Mind 6 (24):581-583 (1881)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Paradoxical experimental outcomes and animal suffering.Jaylan Sheila Turkkan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):42-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pain, suffering, and distress.Aubrey Townsend - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):41-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Broadening the welfare index.Frederick Toates - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):40-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The attribution of suffering.William Timberlake - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):38-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sociobiology and Darwinism.Donald Symons - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):208-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Measuring opportunity: Toward a contractarian measure of individual interest*: Robert Sugden.Robert Sugden - 1998 - Social Philosophy and Policy 15 (2):34-60.
    Liberals have often been attracted by contractarian modes of argument— and with good reason. Any system of social organization requires that some constraints be imposed on individuals' freedom of action; it is a central problem for any liberal political theory to show which constraints can be justified, and which cannot. A contractarian justification works by showing that the constraints in question can be understood as if they were the product of an agreement, voluntarily entered into by every member of society. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What is adaptive?Robert J. Sternberg - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):207-208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Measuring the hedonimeter.Brian Skyrms & Louis Narens - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (12):3199-3210.
    We revisit classical Utilitarianism by connecting and generalizing two ideas. The first is that there is a representation theorem possible for hedonic value similar to, but also importantly different from, the one provided by von Neumann and Morgenstern to measure decision utility. The idea is to use objective time, in place of objective chance, to measure hedonic value. This representation for hedonic value delivers a stronger kind of scale than von Neumann–Morgenstern utility, a ratio scale rather than merely an interval (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The significance of animal suffering.Peter Singer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):9-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Ethics and animals.Peter Singer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):45-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • What is sociobiology's central dogma?James Silverberg & J. Patrick Gray - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):206-207.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From one subjectivity to another.S. J. Shettleworth & N. Mrosovsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):37-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Animal well-being: There are many paths to enlightenment.Evalyn F. Segal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):36-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Just society.Rakesh K. Sarin - 2021 - Theory and Decision 91 (4):417-444.
    I examine the foundations of a just society using the lens of decision theory. The conception of just society is from an individual’s viewpoint: where would I rather live if I have an equal chance of being any individual? Three alternative designs for a just society are examined. These are: laissez-faire, maximin and social minimum. Two assumptions about human nature clarify the distinction among three societies. The first assumption is that a representative individual’s utility function is concave. The second assumption (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The meaning of speciesism and the forms of animal suffering.S. F. Sapontzis - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):35-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Emotion, empathy, and suffering.Eric A. Salzen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To suffer, or not to suffer? That is the question.Andrew N. Rowan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):33-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Science and value.Bernard E. Rollin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):32-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Demography and sociobiology.Robert D. Retherford - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):205-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Effects of fixed costs in two-person sequential bargaining.Amnon Rapoport, Eythan Weg & Dan S. Felsenthal - 1990 - Theory and Decision 28 (1):47-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Values of Economics.Girts Racko - 2019 - Journal of Business Ethics 154 (1):35-48.
    This study addresses a fundamental concern of research on economic ethics by examining the values of economics. While other studies have linked the study of economics to the adoption of rational economic behavior, this study goes one level deeper, investigating the values that underpin neoclassical economics and whether they are transmitted to students. We find that the study of economics is associated with an increase in hedonism and power values, a decrease self-direction value, and possibly a decrease in universalism value. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Suffering as a behaviourist views it.Howard Rachlin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):32-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Economists on private incentives, economic models, and the administrative state: The clash between happiness and the so-called public good.Sandra J. Peart - 2021 - Social Philosophy and Policy 38 (1):152-169.
    This essay examines the administrative state as a ubiquitous phenomenon that results in part from the mismatch of incentives. Using two dramatic episodes in the history of economics, the essay considers two types of mismatch. It then examines how economists increasingly endorsed the “general good” as a unitary goal for society, even at the expense of private hopes and desires. More than this, their procedures and models gave them warrant to design mechanisms and advocate for legislation and regulations to “fix” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Seeking the sources of simian suffering.Melinda A. Novak & Jerrold S. Meyer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):31-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The case for and difficulties in using “demand areas” to measure changes in well-being.Yew-Kwang Ng - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):30-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From separability to unweighted sum: A case for utilitarianism. [REVIEW]Yew-Kwang Ng - 2000 - Theory and Decision 49 (4):299-312.
    After reviewing the compelling case for separability (`social welfare is a separable function of individual utilities'), an argument is advanced for utilitarianism (defined as `social welfare is the unweighted sum of individual utilities'). Basically, a compelling individualism-type axiom leads us to (social welfare as an) unweighted sum (of individual utilities), given separability.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An Argument for Utilitarianism.Yew-Kwang Ng & Peter Singer - 1981 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):229 - 239.
    Many utilitarians accept Bentham's view that to argue for the principle of utility is as ‘impossible as it is needless'. They take utilitarianism as a first principle which one either accepts or does not. They do, of course, defend utilitarianism against objections, and make objections to other ethical positions; but the principle of utility itself, they hold, must stand on its own merits. In this article we use a different approach. We introduce a principle, which we call ‘Weak Majority Preference', (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The “eugenic dilemma” revisited.James V. Neel - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):205-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Imagination and imaging in model building.Mary S. Morgan - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (5):753-766.
    Modelling became one of the primary tools of mathematical economic research in the twentieth century, but when we look at examples of how nonanalogical models were first built in economics, both the process of making representations and aspects of the representing relation remain opaque. Like early astronomers, economists have to imagine how the hidden parts of their world are arranged and to make images, that is, create models, to represent how they work. The case of the Edgeworth Box, a model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Leaving the Road to Abilene: A Pragmatic Approach to Addressing the Normative Paradox of Responsible Management Education.Dirk C. Moosmayer, Sandra Waddock, Long Wang, Matthias P. Hühn, Claus Dierksmeier & Christopher Gohl - 2019 - Journal of Business Ethics 157 (4):913-932.
    We identify a normative paradox of responsible management education. Business educators aim to promote social values and develop ethical habits and socially responsible mindsets through education, but they attempt to do so with theories that have normative underpinnings and create actual normative effects that counteract their intentions. We identify a limited conceptualization of freedom in economic theorizing as a cause of the paradox. Economic theory emphasizes individual freedom and understands this as the freedom to choose from available options. However, conceptualizing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Consumer demand: Can we deal with differing priorities?P. Monaghan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):29-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shall I Compare Thee to a Minkowski-Ricardo-Leontief-Metzler Matrix of the Mosak-Hicks Type?: Or, Rhetoric, Mathematics, and the Nature of Neoclassical Economic Theory.Philip Mirowski - 1987 - Economics and Philosophy 3 (1):67-95.
    Is rhetoric just a new and trendy way toépater les bourgeois?Unfortunately, I think that the newfound interest of some economists in rhetoric, and particularly Donald McCloskey in his new book and subsequent responses to critics, gives that impression. After economists have worked so hard for the past five decades to learn their sums, differential calculus, real analysis, and topology, it is a fair bet that one could easily hector them about their woeful ignorance of the conjugation of Latin verbs or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Development experience and the potential for suffering: Does “out of experience” mean “out of mind”?Michael Mendl - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):28-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Consumer demand theory and social behavior: All chickens are not equal.Joy A. Mench & W. Ray Stricklin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):28-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Human Rights versus Corporate Rights: Life Value, the Civil Commons and Social Justice.John McMurtry - 2011 - Studies in Social Justice 5 (1):11-61.
    This analysis maps the deepening global crisis and the principles of its resolution by life-value analysis and method. Received theories of economics and justice and modern rights doctrines are shown to have no ground in life value and to be incapable of recognizing universal life goods and the rising threats to them. In response to this system failure at theoretical and operational levels, the unifying nature and measure of life value are defined to provide the long-missing basis for understanding the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Human Rights versus Corporate Rights: Understanding Life Value, the Civil Commons, and Social Justice.John McMurtry - 2011 - Studies in Social Justice 5 (1):2011.
    This analysis maps the deepening global crisis and the principles of its resolution by life-value analysis and method. Received theories of economics and justice and modern rights doctrines are shown to have no ground in life value and to be incapable of recognizing universal life goods and the rising threats to them. In response to this system failure at theoretical and operational levels, the unifying nature and measure of life value are defined to provide the long-missing basis for understanding the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Behind Global System Collapse: The Life-Blind Structure of Economic Rationality. [REVIEW]John McMurtry - 2012 - Journal of Business Ethics 108 (1):49-60.
    This study examines the system-deciding principle of economic rationality for its logical soundness and effects in global practice. Analysis demonstrates the fallacious structure of the underlying assumptions of homo economicus across theories and institutions, and explains how cumulative destruction of global economic, social, and ecological life systems follows from its life-blind mechanism. Higher-order concepts of life-capital, life-value efficiency, and life-good supply and demand are then defined to bring economic rationality into coherence with terrestrial and human life requirements.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Suffering by analogy.David McFarland - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):27-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rational cooperation.Edward McClennen - 2012 - Synthese 187 (1):65-93.
    The Nash-Harsanyi theory of bargaining is usually taken as the correct theory of rational bargaining, and, as such, as the correct theory for the basic political contract for a society. It grafts a theory of cooperation to a base that essentially articulates the perspective of non-cooperative interaction. The resultant theory is supposed make clear how rational bargaining can fully realize the mutual gains that cooperation can make possible. However, its underlying commitment to the concepts of non-cooperative interaction renders this doubtful. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Obtaining and applying objective criteria in animal welfare.Anne E. Magurran - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):26-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hidden adaptationism.David Magnus & Peter Thiel - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):26-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fertility, intelligence, and socioeconomic status: No cause for surprise or alarm.Euan M. Macphail - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):204-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Further evidence for secular increases in intelligence in Britain, Japan, and the United States.Richard Lynn & Susan Hampson - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):203-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “The moral arithmetic”: morality in the age of mathematics.Mordechai Levy-Eichel - 2021 - Intellectual History Review 31 (2):267-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Proletarian hominids on the rampage.Jeffrey A. Kurland - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):202-203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • How to Deter Financial Misconduct if Crime Pays?Karol Marek Klimczak, Alejo José G. Sison, Maria Prats & Maximilian B. Torres - 2022 - Journal of Business Ethics 179 (1):205-222.
    Financial misconduct has come into the spotlight in recent years, causing market regulators to increase the reach and severity of interventions. We show that at times the economic benefits of illicit financial activity outweigh the costs of litigation. We illustrate our argument with data from the US Securities and Exchanges Commission and a case of investment misconduct. From the neoclassical economic paradigm, which follows utilitarian thinking, it is rational to engage in misconduct. Still, the majority of professionals refrain from misconduct, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The trouble with human sociobiology is ….Philip Kitcher - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):201-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sexual strategies and social-class differences in fitness in modern industrial societies.Hillard Kaplan & Kim Hill - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):198-201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Economics and Ethics under the Same Umbrella: Edgeworth's 'Exact Utilitarianism', 1877–1881.Shiri Cohen Kaminitz - 2013 - Utilitas 25 (4):487-503.
    Edgeworth's original mathematical formalization of utilitarianism as presented in his works of 1877–81 illustrates an intriguing phase in the mutually intertwined history of economics and utilitarianism. In this article I analyse Edgeworth's motivations and point to its interesting implications. In particular, it is pointed out that the starting point of Edgeworth's project had little to do with the field of economics, but formed part of an attempt to present utilitarianism in the most scientific way possible; an attempt made in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • "Utility".John Broome - 1991 - Economics and Philosophy 7 (1):1-12.
    “Utility,” in plain English, means usefulness. In Australia, a ute is a useful vehicle. Jeremy Bentham specialized the meaning to a particular sort of usefulness. “By utility,” he said, “is meant that property in any object, whereby it tends to produce benefit, advantage, pleasure, good, or happiness or to prevent the happening of mischief, pain, evil, or unhappiness to the party whose interest is considered”. The “principle of utility” is the principle that actions are to be judged by their usefulness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations