Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Must we mean what we say?Stanley Cavell - 1964 - In Vere Claiborne Chappell (ed.), Ordinary language: essays in philosophical method. New York: Dover Publications. pp. 172 – 212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   161 citations  
  • Russellian description and Smith’s suicide.Stefano Predelli - 2003 - Acta Analytica 18 (1-2):125-141.
    When discussing the distinction between referential and attributive uses of definite descriptions, Keith Donnellan also mentions cases such as ‘Smith’s murderer is insane’, uttered in a scenario in which Smith committed suicide. In this essay, I defend a two-fold thesis: (i) the alleged intuition that utterances of ‘Smith’s murderer is insane’ are true in the scenario in question is independent from the phenomenon of referential uses of definite description, and, most importantly, (ii) even if such intuition is granted semantic relevance, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Meaning-as-Use and Meaning-as-Correspondence.Panayot Butchvarov - 1960 - Philosophy 35 (135):314 - 325.
    The purpose of this article is to examine two major arguments in favour of the philosophical thesis that the meaning of an expression is its use, and not its referent or what it corresponds to. A second philosophical thesis which is closely related to the first is that the study of the ordinary, “actual” uses of certain expressions is not of purely linguistic interest but in fact is a way, probably the only proper way, of solving the problems of traditional (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The semantics of singular terms.Gordon Matheson - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (4):439-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Contextual implication.Isabel C. Hungerland - 1960 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 3 (1-4):211 – 258.
    In this essay, I have rejected the inductive interpretation of the paradigm of contextual implication (to say “p”; is to imply that one believes that ) and proposed in its stead an explicatory model according to which a speaker in making a statement contextually implies whatever one is entitled to infer on the basis of the presumption that his act of stating is normal. In developing this model, I show how contextual implication depends on three distinct matters: a stating context, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A sense-based, process model of belief.Robert F. Hadley - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (3):279-320.
    A process-oriented model of belief is presented which permits the representation of nested propositional attitudes within first-order logic. The model (NIM, for nested intensional model) is axiomatized, sense-based (via intensions), and sanctions inferences involving nested epistemic attitudes, with different agents and different times. Because NIM is grounded upon senses, it provides a framework in which agents may reason about the beliefs of another agent while remaining neutral with respect to the syntactic forms used to express the latter agent's beliefs. Moreover, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Historical Relationship between Philosophy of Science and Analytic Philosophy in Japan日本における科学哲学と分析哲学の歴史的関係.Tomohisa Furuta - 2018 - Kagaku Tetsugaku 51 (2):47-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hare, Husserl, and Philosophic Discovery.John J. Compton - 1964 - Dialogue 3 (1):42-51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Presupposition and two-dimensional logic.Merrie Bergmann - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (1):27 - 53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Semantic Norms and Temporal Externalism.Henry Jackman - 1996 - Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh
    There has frequently been taken to be a tension, if not an incompatibility, between "externalist" theories of content (which allow the make-up of one's physical environment and the linguistic usage of one's community to contribute to the contents of one's thoughts and utterances) and the "methodologically individualist" intuition that whatever contributes to the content of one's thoughts and utterances must ultimately be grounded in facts about one's own attitudes and behavior. In this dissertation I argue that one can underwrite such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations