Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. O niektórych uwarunkowaniach Fregowskiej teorii kwantyfikacji.Jan Szot - 2013 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 61 (3):125-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Carnap’s Early Semantics.Georg Schiemer - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (3):487-522.
    This paper concerns Carnap’s early contributions to formal semantics in his work on general axiomatics between 1928 and 1936. Its main focus is on whether he held a variable domain conception of models. I argue that interpreting Carnap’s account in terms of a fixed domain approach fails to describe his premodern understanding of formal models. By drawing attention to the second part of Carnap’s unpublished manuscript Untersuchungen zur allgemeinen Axiomatik, an alternative interpretation of the notions ‘model’, ‘model extension’ and ‘submodel’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Hugh maccoll: eine bibliographische erschließung seiner hauptwerke und notizen zu ihrer rezeptionsgeschichte.Shahid Rahman - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (3):165-183.
    The work of Hugh MacColl (1837–1909) suffered the same fate after his death as before it:despite being vaguely alluded to and in part even commended, on the whole it has remained an unknown quantity. Even worse, those of his ideas which have played a decisive role in the history of logic have been credited to his successors; this is especially the case with the definition of strict implication and the first formal development of formal modal logic. This paper takes an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What did Frege take Russell to have proved?John Woods - 2019 - Synthese 198 (4):3949-3977.
    In 1902 there arrived in Jena a letter from Russell laying out a proof that shattered Frege’s confidence in logicism, which is widely taken to be the doctrine according to which every truth of arithmetic is re-expressible without relevant loss as a provable truth about a purely logical object. Frege was persuaded that Russell had exposed a pathology in logicism, which faced him with the task of examining its symptoms, diagnosing its cause, assessing its seriousness, arriving at a treatment option, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Arguments and Their Classification.Kazimierz Trzęsicki - 2011 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 23 (36).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Frege meets Brouwer.Stewart Shapiro & Øystein Linnebo - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (3):540-552.
    We show that, by choosing definitions carefully, a version of Frege's theorem can be proved in intuitionistic logic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Language And Logic In German Post-Hegelian Philosophy.Volker Peckhaus - 2008 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 4.
    The German debates concerning the need for a reform of logic in post-Hegelian times took place under the label “The logical question”, a label introduced by Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg. The main objective of these debates was to overcome the Hegelian identification of logic and metaphysics without re-establishing the old Aristotelian-scholastic formal logic. This paper presents the positions developed by Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg, Otto Friedrich Gruppe, and Carl v. Prantl, each of whom advocated the importance of language in logic in order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Problématique de la preuve en épistémologie contemporaine.Robert Nadeau - 1980 - Philosophiques 7 (2):217-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Main problems of diagrammatic reasoning. Part I: The generalization problem. [REVIEW]Zenon Kulpa - 2009 - Foundations of Science 14 (1-2):75-96.
    The paper attempts to analyze in some detail the main problems encountered in reasoning using diagrams, which may cause errors in reasoning, produce doubts concerning the reliability of diagrams, and impressions that diagrammatic reasoning lacks the rigour necessary for mathematical reasoning. The paper first argues that such impressions come from long neglect which led to a lack of well-developed, properly tested and reliable reasoning methods, as contrasted with the amount of work generations of mathematicians expended on refining the methods of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The modernity of Dedekind’s anticipations contained in What are numbers and what are they good for?J. Soliveres Tur & J. Climent Vidal - 2018 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 72 (2):99-141.
    We show that Dedekind, in his proof of the principle of definition by mathematical recursion, used implicitly both the concept of an inductive cone from an inductive system of sets and that of the inductive limit of an inductive system of sets. Moreover, we show that in Dedekind’s work on the foundations of mathematics one can also find specific occurrences of various profound mathematical ideas in the fields of universal algebra, category theory, the theory of primitive recursive mappings, and set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Context of Inference.Curtis Franks - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (4):365-395.
    There is an ambiguity in the concept of deductive validity that went unnoticed until the middle of the twentieth century. Sometimes an inference rule is called valid because its conclusion is a theorem whenever its premises are. But often something different is meant: The rule's conclusion follows from its premises even in the presence of other assumptions. In many logical environments, these two definitions pick out the same rules. But other environments are context-sensitive, and in these environments the second notion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophy of mathematics and computer science.Kazimierz Trzęsicki - 2010 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 22 (35).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truth and judgment.Jeremy J. Kelly - unknown
    I examine the difficulties that several philosophers of language are liable to encounter in their attempts to provide an account of the connection between truth and assertion. I then attempt to provide an account of this connection. The analysis is concerned chiefly with difficulties which consist in elucidating the conceptual connection between truth and assertion in a way that respects certain linguistic intuitions while at the same time rendering the concept of truth amenable to a semantic interpretation. The proposed view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Rigorisace infinitesimálního počtu a obrat k jazyku (Kant–Bolzano–Frege).Prokop SouSedík - 2006 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 13 (1):32-54.
    Mathematics in the 19th century underwent explosive development. The discussion among philosophers was motivated by new results which conflicted with Kant’s very influential conception. One of the most important areas which lead to the meeting of philosophy and mathematics was a rigorous account of the infinitesimal calculus. In his article the author shows that considerations of this type found in Bolzano and Frege are important not only for the overcoming of the Kantian conception, but as for what we today call (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The logic of empirical theories revisited.Johan van Benthem - 2012 - Synthese 186 (3):775-792.
    Logic and philosophy of science share a long history, though contacts have gone through ups and downs. This paper is a brief survey of some major themes in logical studies of empirical theories, including links to computer science and current studies of rational agency. The survey has no new results: we just try to make some things into common knowledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Space, number and structure: A tale of two debates.Stewart Shapiro - 1996 - Philosophia Mathematica 4 (2):148-173.
    Around the turn of the century, Poincare and Hilbert each published an account of geometry that took the discipline to be an implicit definition of its concepts. The terms ‘point’, ‘line’, and ‘plane’ can be applied to any system of objects that satisfies the axioms. Each mathematician found spirited opposition from a different logicist—Russell against Poincare' and Frege against Hilbert— who maintained the dying view that geometry essentially concerns space or spatial intuition. The debates illustrate the emerging idea of mathematics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A core ontology for requirements.Ivan J. Jureta, John Mylopoulos & Stéphane Faulkner - 2009 - Applied ontology 4 (3):169-244.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Bodies Divide, Minds Unite: Mirror Neurons and Leibniz’s Philosophy of Mind.Alessia Pannese - 2010 - Biological Theory 5 (3):264-270.
    Among Leibniz’s contributions to the philosophy of mind, two topics bear relevance to contemporary discussions in cognitive sciences: the mind-body problem, and the universal language. Leibniz’s deterministic view rejects inter-substance causality between mental and bodily states, as well as between mental or bodily states of different individuals. In addition, Leibniz believed in the need to enhance communication through a universal language based on symbolic representations. Here I reconsider Leibniz’s ideas in the light of experimental evidence coming from mirror neurons. These (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The analytic-synthetic distinction and the classical model of science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege.Willem R. De Jong - 2010 - Synthese 174 (2):237 - 261.
    This paper concentrates on some aspects of the history of the analyticsynthetic distinction from Kant to Bolzano and Frege. This history evinces considerable continuity but also some important discontinuities. The analytic-synthetic distinction has to be seen in the first place in relation to a science, i.e. an ordered system of cognition. Looking especially to the place and role of logic it will be argued that Kant, Bolzano and Frege each developed the analytic-synthetic distinction within the same conception of scientific rationality, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Logical Grammar.Glyn Morrill - 2012 - In Ruth M. Kempson, Tim Fernando & Nicholas Asher (eds.), Philosophy of linguistics. Boston: North Holland. pp. 63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Decompositions and Transformations: Conceptions of Analysis in the Early Analytic and Phenomenological Traditions.Michael Beaney - 2002 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 40 (S1):53-99.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Essay Review.Volker Peckhaus - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (2):115-120.
    Jarmo Pulkkinen, The threat of logical mathematism. A study on the critique of mathematical logic in Germany at the turn of the 20th century. Frankfurt a.M:Peter Lang, 1994. Scandinavian University Studies in the Humanities and Social Sciences; 7). 186 pp. 24 DM. ISBN 3-631-47409-1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lessons from the History and Philosophy of Science regarding the Research Assessment Exercise.Donald Gillies - 2007 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 61:37-73.
    The Research Assessment Exercise was introduced in 1986 by Thatcher, and was continued by Blair. So it has now been running for 21 years. During this time, the rules governing the RAE have changed considerably, and the interval between successive RAEs has also varied. These changes are not of great importance as far as the argument of this paper is concerned. We will concentrate on the main features of the RAE which can be summarised as follows.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The concept of “character” in Dirichlet’s theorem on primes in an arithmetic progression.Jeremy Avigad & Rebecca Morris - 2014 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 68 (3):265-326.
    In 1837, Dirichlet proved that there are infinitely many primes in any arithmetic progression in which the terms do not all share a common factor. We survey implicit and explicit uses ofDirichlet characters in presentations of Dirichlet’s proof in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, with an eye toward understanding some of the pragmatic pressures that shaped the evolution of modern mathematical method.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Zur Dynamik der Sprache aus linguistischer und neurokognitiver Perspektive.Krzysztof Sakowski - 2014 - Acta Universitatis Lodziensis. Folia Germanica 10.
    Cognitive sciences are grouped together according to their substantial disciplines such as neurobiology, psychology, linguistics and many others. From more than ten years a search has been undertaken for the best fitting cognitive research method, that does not influence the scientific output. More recently attention has been turned to systems which might operate through their dynamic aspect, called the dynamic approach. Their great advantage is to see the old linguistic axioms such as connectivity in a new way.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pieranna Garavaso and Nicla Vassallo, Frege on Thinking and Its Epistemic Significance. [REVIEW]Rasa Davidaviciute - 2018 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (8).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark