Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Hobbes’s Fool the Insipiens, and the Tyrant-King.Patricia Springborg - 2011 - Political Theory 39 (1):85-111.
    Hobbes in Leviathan, chapter xv, 4, makes the startling claim: “The fool hath said in his heart, ‘there is no such thing as justice,’” paraphrasing Psalm 52:1: “The fool hath said in his heart there is no God.” These are charges of which Hobbes himself could stand accused. His parable of the fool is about the exchange of obedience for protection, the backslider, regime change, and the tyrant; but given that Hobbes was himself likely an oath-breaker, it is also self-reflexive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Accountability and Parenthood in Locke's Theological Ethics.Daniel Layman - 2014 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 31 (2):101-118.
    According to John Locke, the conditions of human happiness establish the content of natural law, but God’s commands make it morally binding. This raises two questions. First, why does moral obligation require an authority figure? Second, what gives God authority? I argue that, according to Locke, moral obligation requires an authority figure because to have an obligation is to be accountable to someone. I then argue that, according to Locke, God has a kind of parental authority inasmuch as he is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Derek Parfit and the history of ethics.Attfield Robin - 1989 - History of the Human Sciences 2 (3):357-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hobbes's Challenge to Descartes, Bramhall and Boyle: A Corporeal God.Patricia Springborg - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (5):903-934.
    This paper brings new work to bear on the perennial question about Hobbes's atheism to show that as a debate about scepticism it is falsely framed. Hobbes, like fellow members of the Mersenne circle, Descartes and Gassendi, was no sceptic, but rather concerned to rescue physics and metaphysics from radical scepticism by exploring corporealism. In his early letter of November 1640, Hobbes had issued a provocative challenge to Descartes to abandon metaphysical dualism and subscribe to a ?corporeal God?; a provocation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Causality and Morality in Politics: The Rise of Naturalism in Dutch Seventeenth-Century Political Thought.H. W. Blom - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Secular Faith.Annette Baier - 1980 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):131 - 148.
    Both in ethics and in epistemology one source of scepticism in its contemporary version is the realization, often belated, of the full consequences of atheism. Modern non-moral philosophy looks back to Descartes as its father figure, but disowns the Third Meditation. But if God does not underwrite one's cognitive powers, what does? The largely unknown evolution of them, which is just a version of Descartes’ unreliable demon? “Let us … grant that all that is here said of God is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Locke's Theory of Education as a Philosophical Anthropology.Béla Mester - 2014 - Metodicki Ogledi 21 (2):71-84.
    My article offers an overview of the role of the theory of education in John Locke’s system of ideas. First and second sections outline main interpretations of Locke’s educational work, from a religious point of view. Important interpretations of John Locke’s work within the framework of history of education are discussed in the third section. In the section that follows, I present my hypothesis on the influence of John Locke’s philosophical anthropology, as described in his educational writing, on his political (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark