Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Pięćdziesiąt twarzy Graya. Uwagi na marginesie książki Beaty Polanowskiej-Sygulskiej John Gray i krytyka liberalnego legalizmu.Paweł Kłoczowski - 2018 - Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal 8 (`1):119-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Respecting Children's Choices.Kalle Grill - 2020 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 7 (2):199-218.
    The traditional liberal view on conflicts between care for wellbeing and respect for choice and desire is that we should look to degrees of competence and voluntariness to determine which moral imperative should take priority. This view has likely influenced the common view that children’s choices should be considered only to the extent that this promotes their future autonomy and helps us determine their best interests. I reject both the general traditional liberal view and its application to children. Competence and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Paternalism by and towards groups.Kalle Grill - 2018 - In Kalle Grill & Jason Hanna (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Paternalism. New York: Routledge. pp. 46-58.
    In many or most instances of paternalism, more than one person acts paternalistically, or more than one person is treated paternalistically. This chapter discusses some complications that arise in such group cases, which are largely ignored in the conceptual debate. First, a group of people who together perform an action may do so for different reasons, which makes it more challenging to determine whether the action is paternalistic. This gives us some reason not to pin the property of being paternalistic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mill's Political Perception of Liberty: Idiosyncratic, Perfectionist but essentially Liberal.Leonidas Makris - 2018 - Public Reason 10 (1).
    There is a dominant perception of liberty among most contemporary liberals. It is one close to empiricism’s portrayal of freedom as a natural right of every person to advance her interests. According to this view, there are no demanding conditions under which people can be regarded as free agents but their unfettered behaviour from external inhibitions. It is widely thought that Mill’s liberalism does not deviate considerably from this tradition. The present text suggests a different reading of the gist of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mill’s Moral Standard.Ben Eggleston - 2016 - In Christopher Macleod & Dale E. Miller (eds.), A Companion to Mill. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.. pp. 358-373.
    A book chapter (about 7,000 words, plus references) on the interpretation of Mill’s criterion of right and wrong, with particular attention to act utilitarianism, rule utilitarianism, and sanction utilitarianism. Along the way, major topics include Mill’s thoughts on liberalism, supererogation, the connection between wrongness and punishment, and breaking rules when doing so will produce more happiness than complying with them will.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Cost of Free Speech: Pornography, Hate Speech, and Their Challenge to Liberalism.Abigail Levin - 2010 - Palgrave-Macmillan.
    The distinctly contemporary proliferation of pornography and hate speech poses a challenge to liberalism's traditional ideal of a 'marketplace of ideas' facilitated by state neutrality about the content of speech. This new study argues that the liberal state ought to depart from neutrality to meet this challenge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Is there a global harm principle?Richard Vernon - 2009 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 12 (1):1-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Utilitarian Liberalism: Between Gray and Mill.Jonathan Riley - 2006 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 9 (2):117-135.
    (2006). Utilitarian Liberalism: Between Gray and Mill. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy: Vol. 9, The Political Theory of John Gray, pp. 117-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Gray’s Elegy for Progress.Glyn Morgan - 2006 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 9 (2):227-241.
    (2006). Gray’s Elegy for Progress. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy: Vol. 9, The Political Theory of John Gray, pp. 227-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is political philosophy too ahistorical?Jonathan Floyd - 2009 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 12 (4):513-533.
    The accusation that contemporary political philosophy is carried out in too ahistorical a fashion depends upon it being possible for historical facts to ground normative political principles. This they cannot do. Each of the seven ways in which it might be thought possible for them to do so fails for one or more of four reasons: History yields no timeless set of universal moral values; it displays no convergence upon such a set; it reveals no univocal moral or cultural context (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Philosophical Foundations of Criminalization: Analysis of Moral Vices from the Perspective of the Theory of Self-Government and the Principle of Harm.Kamran Mahmoudian Esfahani, Mohammad Ali Ardabili & Nasrin Mehra - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Theological Research 24 (1):137-158.
    As a normative ethics theory, virtue ethics theory can present a criterion for criminalization. The revival of this theory brought about a great new change in new ethics philosophy in the second half of the 20th century. Its effects on criminalization are just like the two sides of a coin. On the one hand, it has the capacity of promoting ethics to reach its climax and even act as a permit for criminal intervention in the internal qualities of the individuals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is the Harm Principle For?John Stanton-Ife - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (2):329-353.
    In their excellent monograph, Crimes, Harms and Wrongs, Andrew Simester and Andreas von Hirsch argue for an account of legitimate criminalisation based on wrongfulness, the Harm Principle and the Offence Principle, while they reject an independent anti-paternalism principle. To put it at its simplest my aim in the present paper is to examine the relationship between ‘the harms’ and ‘the wrongs’ of the authors’ title. I begin by comparing the authors’ version of the Harm and Offence Principle with some other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Liberalism and Liberty: the Fragility of a Tradition.Keith Graham - 1988 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 24:207-223.
    My discussion in this lecture is structured as follows. In section 1 I consider the nature of philosophical enquiry and its affinity to liberalism. In section 2 I lay out some of the basic components of liberal theory and explore their interrelations. In section 3 I discuss two challenges to liberalism: one concerning the conception of liberty which it involves and one concerning the way in which it introduces the idea of legitimate political authority. In section 4 I suggest that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rhetoric, Harm, and the Personification of Progress in Mill's On Liberty.Brian Donohue - 2007 - Ratio Juris 20 (2):196-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Racial and Religious Hatred Act 2006: a Millian response.Alexander Brown - 2008 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 11 (1):1-24.
    The Racial and Religious Hatred Act 2006 represents a significant development in UK law. It extends the offence of incitement to racial hatred set out in the Public Order Act 1986 to make it also an offence to stir up hatred against persons on religious grounds. As the most celebrated liberal thinker of the nineteenth century, J.S. Mill might be expected to offer some lessons about the possible dangers of this sort of legislation. A Millian response to the 2006 Act (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reply to Critics.John Gray - 2006 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 9 (2):323-347.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Pluralism after liberalism? [REVIEW]Pratap B. Mehta - 1997 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 11 (4):503-518.
    John Gray argues that the doctrine of value pluralism poses a serious challenge for liberalisms of the Rawlsian and Millian kind. The only proper political doctrine that is compatible with value pluralism is a modus vivendi that can take various forms. But in truth, value pluralism does little to diminish the appeal of liberalism. Under modern conditions, any half‐decent modus vivendi will look more like liberalism than Gray supposes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Gray’s Blues: Pessimism as a Political Project.Glen Newey - 2006 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 9 (2):263--284.
    (2006). Gray’s Blues: Pessimism as a Political Project. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy: Vol. 9, The Political Theory of John Gray, pp. 263-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Liberalism, Nihilism and Modernity in the Political Thought of John Gray.NoëL O’Sullivan - 2006 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 9 (2):285-304.
    (2006). Liberalism, Nihilism and Modernity in the Political Thought of John Gray. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy: Vol. 9, The Political Theory of John Gray, pp. 285-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Legitimacy of Using the Harm Principle in Cases of Religious Freedom Within Education.Georgia du Plessis - 2016 - Human Rights Review 17 (3):349-370.
    John Stuart Mill’s famous “harm principle” has been popular in the limitation of freedoms within human rights jurisprudence. It has been used formally in court cases and also informally in legal argumentation and conversation. Shortly, it is described as a very simple principle that amounts to the notion that persons are at liberty to do what they want as long as their actions do not harm any other person or society in general. This article questions whether it is legitimate to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Freedom, Law and Authority: The State and Legitimacy.Norman Barry - 1988 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 24:191-206.
    Despite the emphasis on the state in the history of political philosophy, the twentieth century has been characterized by a remarkable lack of philosophical reflection on the concept. Until recently analytical philosophy had eschewed those evaluative arguments about political obligation and the limits of state authority that were typical of political theory in the past in favour of the explication of the meaning of the concept. However, even here the results have been disappointing. Logical Positivist attempts to locate some unique (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark