Switch to: References

Citations of:

Intuitionism: An Introduction

Amsterdam,: North-Holland Pub. Co. (1956)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On Logic in the Law: "Something, but not All".Susan Haack - 2007 - Ratio Juris 20 (1):1-31.
    In 1880, when Oliver Wendell Holmes (later to be a Justice of the U.S. Supreme Court) criticized the logical theology of law articulated by Christopher Columbus Langdell (the first Dean of Harvard Law School), neither Holmes nor Langdell was aware of the revolution in logic that had begun, the year before, with Frege's Begriffsschrift. But there is an important element of truth in Holmes's insistence that a legal system cannot be adequately understood as a system of axioms and corollaries; and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Logic, ontology, mathematical practice.Stewart Shapiro - 1989 - Synthese 79 (1):13 - 50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The meaning of mathematical expressions: Does philosophy shed any light on psychology?Paul Ernest - 1990 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (4):443-460.
    Mathematicians and physical scientists depend heavily on the formal symbolism of mathematics in order to express and develop their theories. For this and other reasons the last hundred years has seen a growing interest in the nature of formal language and the way it expresses meaning; particularly the objective, shared aspect of meaning as opposed to subjective, personal aspects. This dichotomy suggests the question: do the objective philosophical theories of meaning offer concepts which can be applied in psychological theories of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reinforcement schedules and “numerical competence”.John A. Nevin - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):594-595.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemic logic: All knowledge is based on our experience, and epistemic logic is the cognitive representation of our experiential confrontation in reality.Dan Nesher - 2021 - Semiotica 2021 (238):153-179.
    Epistemic Logic is our basic universal science, the method of our cognitive confrontation in reality to prove the truth of our basic cognitions and theories. Hence, by proving their true representation of reality we can self-control ourselves in it, and thus refuting the Berkeleyian solipsism and Kantian a priorism. The conception of epistemic logic is that only by proving our true representation of reality we achieve our knowledge of it, and thus we can prove our cognitions to be either true (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A complete negationless system.David Nelson - 1973 - Studia Logica 32 (1):41 - 49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logical foundations of applied mathematics.V. V. Nalimov - 1974 - Synthese 27 (1-2):211 - 250.
    In applied problems mathematics is used as language or as a metalanguage on which metatheories are built, E.G., Mathematical theory of experiment. The structure of pure mathematics is grammar of the language. As opposed to pure mathematics, In applied problems we must keep in mind what underlies the sign system. Optimality criteria-Axioms of applied mathematics-Prove mutually incompatible, They form a mosaic and not mathematical structures which, According to bourbaki, Make mathematics a unified science. One of the peculiarities of applied mathematical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Penser la négation: une introduction. [REVIEW]Denis Miéville - 1992 - Argumentation 6 (1):1-6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heyting’s contribution to the change in research into the foundations of mathematics.Miriam Franchella - 1994 - History and Philosophy of Logic 15 (2):149-172.
    After the 1930s, the research into the foundations of mathematics changed.None of its main directions (logicism, formalism and intuitionism) had any longer the pretension to be the only true mathematics.Usually, the determining factor in the change is considered to be Gödel?s work, while Heyting?s role is neglected.In contrast, in this paper I first describe how Heyting directly suggested the abandonment of the big foundational questions and the putting forward of a new kind of foundational research consisting in the isolation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Epistemology Versus Ontology: Essays on the Philosophy and Foundations of Mathematics in Honour of Per Martin-Löf.Peter Dybjer, Sten Lindström, Erik Palmgren & Göran Sundholm (eds.) - 2012 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This book brings together philosophers, mathematicians and logicians to penetrate important problems in the philosophy and foundations of mathematics. In philosophy, one has been concerned with the opposition between constructivism and classical mathematics and the different ontological and epistemological views that are reflected in this opposition. The dominant foundational framework for current mathematics is classical logic and set theory with the axiom of choice. This framework is, however, laden with philosophical difficulties. One important alternative foundational programme that is actively pursued (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intuitionistic mereology.Paolo Maffezioli & Achille C. Varzi - 2021 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 18):4277-4302.
    Two mereological theories are presented based on a primitive apartness relation along with binary relations of mereological excess and weak excess, respectively. It is shown that both theories are acceptable from the standpoint of constructive reasoning while remaining faithful to the spirit of classical mereology. The two theories are then compared and assessed with regard to their extensional import.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reply to Øystein Linnebo and Stewart Shapiro.Ian Rumfitt - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (7):842-858.
    ABSTRACTIn reply to Linnebo, I defend my analysis of Tait's argument against the use of classical logic in set theory, and make some preliminary comments on Linnebo's new argument for the same conclusion. I then turn to Shapiro's discussion of intuitionistic analysis and of Smooth Infinitesimal Analysis. I contend that we can make sense of intuitionistic analysis, but only by attaching deviant meanings to the connectives. Whether anyone can make sense of SIA is open to doubt: doing so would involve (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Five Observations Concerning the Intended Meaning of the Intuitionistic Logical Constants.Gustavo Fernández Díez - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (4):409-424.
    This paper contains five observations concerning the intended meaning of the intuitionistic logical constants: (1) if the explanations of this meaning are to be based on a non-decidable concept, that concept should not be that of `proof"; (2) Kreisel"s explanations using extra clauses can be significantly simplified; (3) the impredicativity of the definition of → can be easily and safely ameliorated; (4) the definition of → in terms of `proofs from premises" results in a loss of the inductive character of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Fitch's Paradox and the Problem of Shared Content.Thorsten Sander - 2006 - Abstracta 3 (1):74-86.
    According to the “paradox of knowability”, the moderate thesis that all truths are knowable – ... – implies the seemingly preposterous claim that all truths are actually known – ... –, i.e. that we are omniscient. If Fitch’s argument were successful, it would amount to a knockdown rebuttal of anti-realism by reductio. In the paper I defend the nowadays rather neglected strategy of intuitionistic revisionism. Employing only intuitionistically acceptable rules of inference, the conclusion of the argument is, firstly, not ..., (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a philosophical understanding of the logics of formal inconsistency.Walter Carnielli & Abílio Rodrigues - 2015 - Manuscrito 38 (2):155-184.
    In this paper we present a philosophical motivation for the logics of formal inconsistency, a family of paraconsistent logics whose distinctive feature is that of having resources for expressing the notion of consistency within the object language in such a way that consistency may be logically independent of non-contradiction. We defend the view according to which logics of formal inconsistency may be interpreted as theories of logical consequence of an epistemological character. We also argue that in order to philosophically justify (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Possibilities for the construction of a sense of number by animals.Leslie P. Steffe - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):598-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Numerical competence in animals: Definitional issues, current evidence, and a new research agenda.Hank Davis & Rachelle Pérusse - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):561-579.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  • An omniscience principle, the König Lemma and the Hahn‐Banach theorem.Hajime Ishihara - 1990 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 36 (3):237-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Deleuze and Mathematics.Simon B. Duffy - 2006 - In Simon Duffy (ed.), Virtual Mathematics: the logic of difference. Clinamen.
    The collection Virtual Mathematics: the logic of difference brings together a range of new philosophical engagements with mathematics, using the work of French philosopher Gilles Deleuze as its focus. Deleuze’s engagements with mathematics rely upon the construction of alternative lineages in the history of mathematics in order to reconfigure particular philosophical problems and to develop new concepts. These alternative conceptual histories also challenge some of the self-imposed limits of the discipline of mathematics, and suggest the possibility of forging new connections (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recovering Quantum Logic Within an Extended Classical Framework.Claudio Garola & Sandro Sozzo - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (2):399-419.
    We present a procedure which allows us to recover classical and nonclassical logical structures as concrete logics associated with physical theories expressed by means of classical languages. This procedure consists in choosing, for a given theory ${{\mathcal{T}}}$ and classical language ${{\fancyscript{L}}}$ expressing ${{\mathcal{T}}, }$ an observative sublanguage L of ${{\fancyscript{L}}}$ with a notion of truth as correspondence, introducing in L a derived and theory-dependent notion of C-truth (true with certainty), defining a physical preorder $\prec$ induced by C-truth, and finally selecting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On brouwer's definition of unextendable order.Carl J. Posy - 1980 - History and Philosophy of Logic 1 (1-2):139-149.
    It is argued that the tensed theory of the creative subject provides a natural formulation of the logic underlying Brouwer's notion of unextendable order and explains the link between that notion and virtual order. The tensed theory of the creative subject is also shown to be a useful tool for interpreting recent evidence about the stages of Brouwer's thinking concerning these two notions of order.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Crisis in the Foundations of Mathematics.J. Ferreiros - 2008 - In T. Gowers (ed.), Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press.
    A general introduction to the celebrated foundational crisis, discussing how the characteristic traits of modern mathematics (acceptance of the notion of an “arbitrary” function proposed by Dirichlet; wholehearted acceptance of infinite sets and the higher infinite; a preference “to put thoughts in the place of calculations” and to concentrate on “structures” characterized axiomatically; a reliance on “purely existential” methods of proof) provoked extensive polemics and alternative approaches. Going beyond exclusive concentration on the paradoxes, it also discusses the role of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Is it the thought that counts?Brendan McGonigle - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):593-594.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sur Une Extension Simple du Calcul Intuitionniste Des Predicats du Premier Ordre Appliquee a L'Analyse.Maurice Margenstern - 1984 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 30 (19-24):317-324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sur une extension simple du calcul intuitionniste Des predicats du premier ordre appliquee a l'analyse.Maurice Margenstern - 1984 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 30 (19‐24):317-324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Negationless intuitionism.Enrico Martino - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (2):165-177.
    The present paper deals with natural intuitionistic semantics for intuitionistic logic within an intuitionistic metamathematics. We show how strong completeness of full first order logic fails. We then consider a negationless semantics à la Henkin for second order intuitionistic logic. By using the theory of lawless sequences we prove that, for such semantics, strong completeness is restorable. We argue that lawless negationless semantics is a suitable framework for a constructive structuralist interpretation of any second order formalizable theory (classical or intuitionistic, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructively Complete Finite Sets.Mark Mandelkern - 1988 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 34 (2):97-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Constructively Complete Finite Sets.Mark Mandelkern - 1988 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 34 (2):97-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • You can't succeed without really counting.Euan M. Macphail - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):592-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wilson on relativism and teaching.Jim Mackenzie - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 21 (1):119–130.
    Jim Mackenzie; Wilson on Relativism and Teaching, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 21, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 119–130, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Numbers and counting: Intuitionistic and gestalt psychological viewpoints.Abraham S. Luchins & Edith H. Luchins - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):591-592.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructions and negationless logic.E. G. K. López-Escobar - 1972 - Studia Logica 30 (1):7 - 22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Introduction to special issue on ‘critical views of logic’.Øystein Linnebo, Frode Kjosavik & Mirja Hartimo - 2022 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 65 (6):631-637.
    Critical views of logic are presented. These are views that are critical of logic in a sense akin to the way in which Kant is critical rather than dogmatic about traditional metaphysics. Such approaches differ from the Fregean ‘logic-first’ view. In accordance with the latter, logic is often regarded as epistemologically and methodologically fundamental. Hence, all disciplines – including mathematics – are considered as answerable to logic, rather than vice versa. In critical views of logic, by contrast, the logical principles (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Number reckoning strategies: A basis for distinction.Eugene C. Lechelt - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):590-591.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some Obstacles Facing a Semantic Foundation for Constructive Mathematics.Michael R. Koss - 2015 - Erkenntnis 80 (5):1055-1068.
    This paper discusses Michael Dummett’s attempt to base the use of intuitionistic logic in mathematics on a proof-conditional semantics. This project is shown to face significant obstacles resulting from the existence of variants of standard intuitionistic logic. In order to overcome these obstacles, Dummett and his followers must give an intuitionistically acceptable completeness proof for intuitionistic logic relative to the BHK interpretation of the logical constants, but there are reasons to doubt that such a proof is possible. The paper concludes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Number concepts in animals: A multidimensional array.James E. King - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):590-590.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A New Approach to Constructive Topology and Measure Theory.A. K. Khalifa - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (6):539-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A New Approach to Constructive Topology and Measure Theory.A. K. Khalifa - 1989 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 35 (6):539-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Burgessian Critique of Nominalistic Tendencies in Contemporary Mathematics and its Historiography.Karin Usadi Katz & Mikhail G. Katz - 2012 - Foundations of Science 17 (1):51-89.
    We analyze the developments in mathematical rigor from the viewpoint of a Burgessian critique of nominalistic reconstructions. We apply such a critique to the reconstruction of infinitesimal analysis accomplished through the efforts of Cantor, Dedekind, and Weierstrass; to the reconstruction of Cauchy’s foundational work associated with the work of Boyer and Grabiner; and to Bishop’s constructivist reconstruction of classical analysis. We examine the effects of a nominalist disposition on historiography, teaching, and research.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Human versus nonhuman abilities: Is there a difference which really counts?Annette Karmiloff-Smith - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):589-590.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Proofs and Retributions, Or: Why Sarah Can’t Take Limits.Vladimir Kanovei, Karin U. Katz, Mikhail G. Katz & Mary Schaps - 2015 - Foundations of Science 20 (1):1-25.
    The small, the tiny, and the infinitesimal have been the object of both fascination and vilification for millenia. One of the most vitriolic reviews in mathematics was that written by Errett Bishop about Keisler’s book Elementary Calculus: an Infinitesimal Approach. In this skit we investigate both the argument itself, and some of its roots in Bishop George Berkeley’s criticism of Leibnizian and Newtonian Calculus. We also explore some of the consequences to students for whom the infinitesimal approach is congenial. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The surprise examination on the paradox of the Heap.Joseph Wayne Smith - 1984 - Philosophical Papers 13 (1):43-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Out for the count.Mark Johnson - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):589-589.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • ‘Whys’ and ‘Hows’ of Using Philosophy in Mathematics Education.Uffe Thomas Jankvist & Steffen Møllegaard Iversen - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (1):205-222.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Applied Mathematics in the Sciences.Dale Jacquette - 2006 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 6 (2):237-267.
    A complete philosophy of mathematics must address Paul Benacerraf’s dilemma. The requirements of a general semantics for the truth of mathematical theorems that coheres also with the meaning and truth conditions for non-mathematical sentences, according to Benacerraf, should ideally be coupled with an adequate epistemology for the discovery of mathematical knowledge. Standard approaches to the philosophy of mathematics are criticized against their own merits and against the background of Benacerraf’s dilemma, particularly with respect to the problem of understanding the distinction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An omniscience principle, the König Lemma and the Hahn-Banach theorem.Hajime Ishihara - 1990 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 36 (3):237-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Definitional constraints and experimental realities.Fabio Idrobo & David I. Mostofsky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):588-588.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lie-toe-tease: double negatives and unexcluded middles.Laurence Horn - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (1):79-103.
    Litotes, “a figure of speech in which an affirmative is expressed by the negative of the contrary” has had some tough reviews. For Pope and Swift, litotes—stock examples include “no mean feat”, “no small problem”, and “not bad at all”—is “the peculiar talent of Ladies, Whisperers, and Backbiters”; for Orwell, it is a means to affect “an appearance of profundity” that we can deport from English “by memorizing this sentence: A not unblack dog was chasing a not unsmall rabbit across (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The magical number four, plus or minus one: Working memory for numbers of items in animals.W. K. Honig - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (4):587-588.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intuitionistische Kennzeichnung der endlichen Spezies.Fritz Homagk - 1971 - Studia Logica 28 (1):41-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark