Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Nominalization, Specification, and Investigation.Richard Lawrence - 2017 - Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley
    Frege famously held that numbers play the role of objects in our language and thought, and that this role is on display when we use sentences like "The number of Jupiter's moons is four". I argue that this role is an example of a general pattern that also encompasses persons, times, locations, reasons, causes, and ways of appearing or acting. These things are 'objects' simply in the sense that they are answers to questions: they are the sort of thing we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is unsaying polite?Berislav Žarnić - 2011 - In Majda Trobok, Nenad Miščević & Berislav Žarnić (eds.), Between Logic and Reality: Modeling Inference, Action and Understanding. Dordrecht and New York: Springer. pp. 201--224.
    This paper is divided in five sections. Section 11.1 sketches the history of the distinction between speech act with negative content and negated speech act, and gives a general dynamic interpretation for negated speech act. “Downdate semantics” for AGM contraction is introduced in Section 11.2. Relying on semantically interpreted contraction, Section 11.3 develops the dynamic semantics for constative and directive speech acts, and their external negations. The expressive completeness for the formal variants of natural language utterances, none of which is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The fallacies of the new theory of reference.Jaakko Hintikka & Gabriel Sandu - 1995 - Synthese 104 (2):245 - 283.
    The so-called New Theory of Reference (Marcus, Kripke etc.) is inspired by the insight that in modal and intensional contexts quantifiers presuppose nondescriptive unanalyzable identity criteria which do not reduce to any descriptive conditions. From this valid insight the New Theorists fallaciously move to the idea that free singular terms can exhibit a built-in direct reference and that there is even a special class of singular terms (proper names) necessarily exhibiting direct reference. This fallacious move has been encouraged by a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • The pragmatization of semantics.Jaroslav Peregrin - 1999 - In Ken P. Turner (ed.), The semantics/pragmatics interface from different points of view. New York: Elsevier. pp. 419--442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Existence Assumptions and Logical Principles: Choice Operators in Intuitionistic Logic.Corey Edward Mulvihill - 2015 - Dissertation, University of Waterloo
    Hilbert’s choice operators τ and ε, when added to intuitionistic logic, strengthen it. In the presence of certain extensionality axioms they produce classical logic, while in the presence of weaker decidability conditions for terms they produce various superintuitionistic intermediate logics. In this thesis, I argue that there are important philosophical lessons to be learned from these results. To make the case, I begin with a historical discussion situating the development of Hilbert’s operators in relation to his evolving program in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • E-type interpretation without E-type pronoun: how Peirce’s Graphs capture the uniqueness implication of donkey pronouns in discourse anaphora.Chuansheng He - 2015 - Synthese 192 (4):1-20.
    In this essay, we propose that Peirce’s Existential Graphs can derive the desired uniqueness implication (or in a weaker claim, the definite description readings) of donkey pronouns in conjunctive discourse (A man walks in the park. He whistles), without postulating a separate category of E-type pronouns.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Games: Unifying Logic, Language, and Philosophy.Ondrej Majer, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Tero Tulenheimo (eds.) - 2009 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
    This volume presents mathematical game theory as an interface between logic and philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Negation in logic and in natural language.Jaakko Hintikka - 2002 - Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (5-6):585-600.
    In game-theoretical semantics, perfectlyclassical rules yield a strong negation thatviolates tertium non datur when informationalindependence is allowed. Contradictorynegation can be introduced only by a metalogicalstipulation, not by game rules. Accordingly, it mayoccur (without further stipulations) onlysentence-initially. The resulting logic (extendedindependence-friendly logic) explains several regularitiesin natural languages, e.g., why contradictory negation is abarrier to anaphase. In natural language, contradictory negationsometimes occurs nevertheless witin the scope of aquantifier. Such sentences require a secondary interpretationresembling the so-called substitutionalinterpretation of quantifiers.This interpretation is sometimes impossible,and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Review article.[author unknown] - 1994 - Semiotica 98 (1-2):157-236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Independence friendly logic.Tero Tulenheimo - 2010 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The logic of anaphora.Jaroslav Peregrin - manuscript
    The paper addresses foundational questions concerning the dynamic semantics of natural language based on dynamic logic of the Groenendijko-Stokhofian kind. Discussing a series of model calculi of increasing complexity, it shows in detail how the usual semantics of dynamic logic can be seen as emerging from the account for certain inferential patterns of natural language, namely those governing anaphora. In this way, the current ‘dynamic turn’ of logic is argued to be reasonably seen not as the product of changing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What is a quantifier?Jaakko Hintikka & Gabriel Sandu - 1994 - Synthese 98 (1):113 - 129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Games as formal tools versus games as explanations in logic and science.Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen - 2003 - Foundations of Science 8 (4):317-364.
    This paper addresses the theoretical notion of a game as it arisesacross scientific inquiries, exploring its uses as a technical andformal asset in logic and science versus an explanatory mechanism. Whilegames comprise a widely used method in a broad intellectual realm(including, but not limited to, philosophy, logic, mathematics,cognitive science, artificial intelligence, computation, linguistics,physics, economics), each discipline advocates its own methodology and aunified understanding is lacking. In the first part of this paper, anumber of game theories in formal studies are critically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Cognitive and Communicative Function of Language.Janina Buczkowska - 2001 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 23:25-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Extended Game-Theoretical Semantics.Manuel Rebuschi - 2011 - In Majda Trobok, Nenad Miščević & Berislav Žarnić (eds.), Between Logic and Reality: Modeling Inference, Action and Understanding. Dordrecht and New York: Springer. pp. 161--182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How's of why's and why's of how's: Relation of method and cause in inquiry.Roberta Kevelson - 1988 - Synthese 74 (1):91 - 106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Who plays semantical games?Michael Hand - 1989 - Philosophical Studies 56 (3):251 - 271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Some aspects of negation in English.Gabriel Sandu - 1994 - Synthese 99 (3):345 - 360.
    I introduce a formal language called the language of informational independence (IL-language, for short) that extends an ordinary first-order language in a natural way. This language is interpreted in terms of semantical games of imperfect information. In this language, one can define two negations: (i) strong or dual negation, and (ii) weak or contradictory negation. The latter negation, unlike the former, can occur only sentence-initially. Then I argue that, to a certain extent, the two negations match the distinction existing in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • In the Beginning was Game Semantics?Giorgi Japaridze - 2009 - In Ondrej Majer, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Tero Tulenheimo (eds.), Games: Unifying Logic, Language, and Philosophy. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag. pp. 249--350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Uniqueness in definite noun phrases.Craige Roberts - 2003 - Linguistics and Philosophy 26 (3):287-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Measure adverbials.Friederike Moltmann - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (6):629 - 660.
    This papers argues that the apparent constraint of adverbials like 'for two hours' (or 'throughout the house') should not be viewed as a restriction to telic events or event predicates, but should be explained entirely in terms of the quantificational status of such adverials, acting as quantifiers over (contextually individuated) parts of a time interval (or spatial region).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • On the logic of informational independence and its applications.Gabriel Sandu - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (1):29 - 60.
    We shall introduce in this paper a language whose formulas will be interpreted by games of imperfect information. Such games will be defined in the same way as the games for first-order formulas except that the players do not have complete information of the earlier course of the game. Some simple logical properties of these games will be stated together with the relation of such games of imperfect information to higher-order logic. Finally, a set of applications will be outlined.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • On the theory of anaphora: Dynamic predicate logic vs. game-theoretical semantics. [REVIEW]Gabriel Sandu - 1997 - Linguistics and Philosophy 20 (2):147-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Perspectival identification, demonstratives and “small worlds”.Jaakko Hintikka - 1998 - Synthese 114 (2):203-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Games, quantification and discourse structure.Robin Clark - 2009 - In Ondrej Majer, Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen & Tero Tulenheimo (eds.), Games: Unifying Logic, Language, and Philosophy. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag. pp. 139--150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intuitionistic categorial grammar.Aarne Ranta - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (2):203 - 239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Text and Its Structure.Andrzej Łachwa - 1990 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 19:118-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Meaning of Linguistic Expressions.Janina Buczkowska - 2001 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 24:65-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark