Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Hippocampal representations of DMS/DNMS in the rat.Robert E. Hampson & Sam A. Deadwyler - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):480-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Acquired equivalence and distinctiveness in human discrimination learning: evidence for associative mediation.Geoffrey Hall, Chris Mitchell, Steven Graham & Yvonna Lavis - 2003 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (2):266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Focus on language origins.Jack P. Hailman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):309-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Was it me when it happened too early? Experience of delayed effects shapes sense of agency.Carola Haering & Andrea Kiesel - 2015 - Cognition 136 (C):38-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Cultivating mindfulness through technology in higher education: a Buberian perspective.Linor L. Hadar & Oren Ergas - 2019 - AI and Society 34 (1):99-107.
    One of the most fundamental concepts within Martin Buber’s philosophy concerns two modes of being: I–it, which reflects an egocentric instrumental existence, and I–thou, which reflects dialogical encounter and interrelatedness. At the face of it, technology seems to be the ultimate example of that which engenders and I–it consciousness. Indeed, a recurrent concern in contemporary times suggests that the increase in our technology use is slowly but surely depriving us of meaningful encounters with the other. In this paper we propose (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Multiple personality disorder and its hosts.Ian Hacking - 1992 - History of the Human Sciences 5 (2):3-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The impending demise of the icon: A critique of the concept of iconic storage in visual information processing.Ralph Norman Haber - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):1-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • The icon is finally dead.Ralph Norman Haber - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):43-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness may still have a processing role to play.Robert Van Gulick - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):699-700.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • I Me Mine: on a Confusion Concerning the Subjective Character of Experience.Marie Guillot - 2016 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology (1):1-31.
    In recent debates on phenomenal consciousness, a distinction is sometimes made, after Levine (2001) and Kriegel (2009), between the “qualitative character” of an experience, i.e. the specific way it feels to the subject (e.g. blueish or sweetish or pleasant), and its “subjective character”, i.e. the fact that there is anything at all that it feels like to her. I argue that much discussion of subjective character is affected by a conflation between three different notions. I start by disentangling the three (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Physical Time Within Human Time.Ronald P. Gruber, Richard A. Block & Carlos Montemayor - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    A possible solution is offered to help resolve the “two times problem” regarding the veridical and illusory nature of time. First it is recognized that the flow of time is part of a wider array of temporal experiences referred to as manifest time, all of which need to be reconciled. Then, an information gathering and utilizing system model is used as a basis for a view of manifest time. The model IGUS robot of Hartle that solves the “unique present” debate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Much ado about the wrong thing.Yosef Grodzinsky - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):449-450.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hippocampal modulation of recognition, conditioning, timing, and space: Why so many functions?Stephen Grossberg - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):479-480.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dual Process Theory of Thought and Default Mode Network: A Possible Neural Foundation of Fast Thinking.Giorgio Gronchi & Fabio Giovannelli - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9:388597.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Classical conditioning: The role of interdisciplinary theory.Stephen Grossberg - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):144-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Attention and recognition learning by adaptive resonance.Stephen Grossberg - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):241-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Prošireno jastvo i identitet kroz vrijeme.Ana Grgić & Marina Novina - 2022 - Disputatio Philosophica 23 (1):65-76.
    U ovom članku raspravljamo o hipotezi proširenog jastva Andyja Clarka i Davida Chalmersa, a osobito o prigovoru prema kojemu proširenom jastvu nedostaje stabilnost i kontinuitet koji su potrebni da bismo ga smatrali identičnim kroz vrijeme. Pokušavamo pokazati da je taj prigovor neodrživ. Raspravljamo i o gledištu prema kojemu se drugi tip jastva, to jest narativno jastvo, također može shvatiti kao prošireno, i tvrdimo da stabilnost i kontinuitet toga tipa jastva također nisu ugroženi ako ga proširimo izvan granica čovjekova tijela. Stoga, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Social facts, social groups and social explanation.John D. Greenwood - 2003 - Noûs 37 (1):93–112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Nothing is instantaneous, even in sensation.Robert A. M. Gregson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):210-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implicit social cognition: Attitudes, self-esteem, and stereotypes.Anthony G. Greenwald & Mahzarin R. Banaji - 1995 - Psychological Review 102 (1):4-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   275 citations  
  • Has consciousness a sharp edge?Robert A. M. Gregson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):679-680.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Sensations to Concepts: a Proposal for Two Learning Processes.Peter Gärdenfors - 2019 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 10 (3):441-464.
    This article presents two learning processes in order to explain how children at an early age can transform a complex sensory input to concepts and categories. The first process constructs the perceptual structures that emerge in children’s cognitive development by detecting invariants in the sensory input. The invariant structures involve a reduction in dimensionality of the sensory information. It is argued that this process generates the primary domains of space, objects and actions and that these domains can be represented as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • What is the relation between language and consciousness?Jeffrey A. Gray - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):679-679.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychoarithmetic or pick your own?Jeffrey A. Gray, John Sinden & Helen Hodges - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):478-479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the construction of mental objects in third and in first persons.Arno L. Goudsmit - 2000 - Foundations of Science 5 (4):399-428.
    This paper deals with some formal properties of objects that are supposed to be internal to persons, that is, mental structures and mental functions. Depending on the ways of talking about these internal objects, they will appear different. Two types of discourse will be presented, to be called the realist and the nominalist discourses, and for eachdiscourse I will focus upon the construction of `self'.The realist discourse assumes an identity between the person and his construction of himself. I will illustrate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The possible futility of neuropsychology.Yonatan Goshen-Gottstein - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):448-449.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some distinctions among representations.M. Gopnik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):378-379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Bodies and minds, heaps and syllables.Erik Goodwyn - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):8831-8855.
    In this paper the explanatory gap of the philosophy of mind is explored, and found to have a similar structure even in different framings of the mind–body problem. This leads to the consideration that the MBP may be a special case of the more general whole-part problem: how do properties of wholes arise from the particular assembly of isolated parts? The conclusion is argued that only an approach of mereological holism offers solace from the explanatory gap problem, exchanging it for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A step linking memory to understanding?Mark A. Good & Richard G. M. Morris - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):477-478.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Working memory is not a natural kind and cannot explain central cognition.Javier Gomez-Lavin - 2020 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 12 (2):199-225.
    Working memory is a foundational construct of cognitive psychology, where it is thought to be a capacity that enables us to keep information in mind and to use that information to support goal directed behavior. Philosophers have recently employed working memory to explain central cognitive processes, from consciousness to reasoning. In this paper, I show that working memory cannot meet even a minimal account of natural kindhood, as the functions of maintenance and manipulation of information that tie working memory models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Iconoclasm avoided: What the single neuron tells the psychologist about the icon.Michael E. Goldberg - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):20-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are rules and instances subserved by separate systems?Robert L. Goldstone & John K. Kruschke - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):405-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Don’t forget the boundary problem! How EM field topology can address the overlooked cousin to the binding problem for consciousness.Andrés Gómez-Emilsson & Chris Percy - 2023 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 17:1233119.
    The boundary problem is related to the binding problem, part of a family of puzzles and phenomenal experiences that theories of consciousness (ToC) must either explain or eliminate. By comparison with the phenomenal binding problem, the boundary problem has received very little scholarly attention since first framed in detail by Rosengard in 1998, despite discussion by Chalmers in his widely cited 2016 work on the combination problem. However, any ToC that addresses the binding problem must also address the boundary problem. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Unconscious mental processes.Clark Glymour - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):606-607.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Cartesian Theater stance.Bruce Glymour, Rick Grush, Valerie Gray Hardcastle, Brian Keeley, Joe Ramsey, Oron Shagrir & Ellen Watson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):209-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A computational perspective on dissociating hippocampal and entorhinal function.Mark A. Gluck, Catherine E. Myers & James K. Goebel - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):476-477.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychology of Science/Theology of Science: Reaching Out or Narrowing?Robert B. Glassman - 2007 - Zygon 42 (3):651-676.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Phenomenological Psychology of J.H. van den Berg.Amedeo Giorgi - 2015 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 46 (2):141-162.
    J.H. van den Berg was a member of the Utrecht school of phenomenology that flourished in Holland during the 1950s and early 1960s. He was a psychiatrist who had a private practice and he taught at the University of Leiden. Along with other members of the Utrecht school, not all of whom were psychiatrists, he was among the first to apply the insights drawn from existential-phenomenological philosophy to psychology and psychiatry. As with the philosophers, he emphasized that subjectivity was engaged (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Descriptive Phenomenological Psychological Method.Amedeo Giorgi - 2012 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 43 (1):3-12.
    The author explains that his background was in experimental psychology but that he wanted to study the whole person and not fragmented psychological processes. He also desired a non-reductionistic method for studying humans. Fortunately he came across the work of Edmund Husserl and discovered in the latter’s thought a way of researching humans that met the criteria he was seeking. Eventually he developed a phenomenological method for researching humans in a psychological way based upon the work of Husserl and Merleau-Ponty. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Observation levels and units of time: A critical analysis of the main assumption of the theory of the artificial. [REVIEW]Giorgio Marchetti - 2000 - AI and Society 14 (3-4):331-347.
    Negrotti's theory of the artificial is based on the fundamental assumption that the human being cannot select more than one observation level per unit of time. Since this assumption has important consequences for the theory of knowledge — knowledge cannot be synthesised but only further differentiated — its plausibility is tested against two aspects that characterise any theory of knowledge: knowledge production and knowledge application. The way in which the human being produces and applies knowledge is analysed, and a model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lessons for the Future from the Margins of Psychology.Amedeo Giorgi - 2002 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 33 (2):179-201.
    Having spent 40 years as a psychologist in academia with a minority perspective at odds with the culture of his profession, the author was requested to reflect upon his experiences in order to offer advice to younger colleagues of the same persuasion. There are indeed prices to be paid when one's values place one outside the established view within the discipline of psychology, but remaining true to oneself is never theless posited as the highest value. The chief drawback of marginality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A theory of love and sexual desire.James Giles - 1994 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 24 (4):339–357.
    The experience of being in love involves a longing for union with the other, where an important part of this longing is sexual desire. But what is the relation between being in love and sexual desire? To answer this it must first be seen that the expression ‘in love’ normally refers to a personal relationship. This is because to be ‘in love’ is to want to be loved back. This much would be predicted by equity and social exchange theories of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Genetically determined neural modules versus mental constructional acts in the genesis of human intelligence.Kathleen R. Gibson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):308-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • More in the early selection process than the attentional-trace mechanism?Marie-Hélène Giard - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):240-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Corpo funzionale e corpo senziente. La tesi forte del carattere incarnato della mente in fenomenologia.Andrea Pace Giannotta - 2022 - Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 13 (1):41-56.
    In questo lavoro distinguo tra due versioni della tesi del carattere incarnato della mente: “debole” e “forte”. Secondo la versione debole, il possesso di stati mentali presuppone l’esistenza di un corpo che si muove ed agisce nell’ambiente, ossia un corpo funzionale. Secondo la versione forte, invece, il possesso di stati mentali presuppone l’esistenza di un corpo non solo funzionale ma anche senziente, ossia: il corpo come sede della sensibilità o coscienza fenomenica. Sostengo che alcuni approcci all’interno della “scienza cognitiva incarnata” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defense of a sensory process theory of psychophysical scaling.George A. Gescheider - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):194-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Quantum no-go theorems and consciousness.Danko D. Georgiev - 2013 - Axiomathes 23 (4):683-695.
    Our conscious minds exist in the Universe, therefore they should be identified with physical states that are subject to physical laws. In classical theories of mind, the mental states are identified with brain states that satisfy the deterministic laws of classical mechanics. This approach, however, leads to insurmountable paradoxes such as epiphenomenal minds and illusionary free will. Alternatively, one may identify mental states with quantum states realized within the brain and try to resolve the above paradoxes using the standard Hilbert (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Towards a common framework of grounded action cognition: Relating motor control, perception and cognition.Antje Gentsch, Arne Weber, Matthis Synofzik, Gottfried Vosgerau & Simone Schütz-Bosbach - 2016 - Cognition 146 (C):81-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Philosophical Thought Experiments, Intuitions, and Cognitive Equilibrium.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2007 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 31 (1):68-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Philosophical thought experiments, intuitions, and cognitive equilibrium.Tamar Szabó Gendler - 2007 - In Peter A. French & Howard K. Wettstein (eds.), Philosophy and the Empirical. Blackwell. pp. 68-89.
    It is a commonplace that contemplation of an imaginary particular may have cognitive and motivational effects that differ from those evoked by an abstract description of an otherwise similar state of affairs. In his Treatise on Human Nature, Hume ([1739] 1978) writes forcefully of this.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations