Switch to: References

Citations of:

The World of Mathematics

(1956)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On Abstraction and the Importance of Asking the Right Research Questions: Could Jordan have Proved the Jordan-Hölder Theorem?Dirk Schlimm - 2008 - Erkenntnis 68 (3):409-420.
    In 1870 Jordan proved that the composition factors of two composition series of a group are the same. Almost 20 years later Hölder (1889) was able to extend this result by showing that the factor groups, which are quotient groups corresponding to the composition factors, are isomorphic. This result, nowadays called the Jordan-Hölder Theorem, is one of the fundamental theorems in the theory of groups. The fact that Jordan, who was working in the framework of substitution groups, was able to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching.Michael R. Matthews (ed.) - 2014 - Springer.
    This inaugural handbook documents the distinctive research field that utilizes history and philosophy in investigation of theoretical, curricular and pedagogical issues in the teaching of science and mathematics. It is contributed to by 130 researchers from 30 countries; it provides a logically structured, fully referenced guide to the ways in which science and mathematics education is, informed by the history and philosophy of these disciplines, as well as by the philosophy of education more generally. The first handbook to cover the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Plasticity: conceptual and neuronal.Paul M. Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Deleuze and Mathematics.Simon B. Duffy - 2006 - In Simon Duffy (ed.), Virtual Mathematics: the logic of difference. Clinamen.
    The collection Virtual Mathematics: the logic of difference brings together a range of new philosophical engagements with mathematics, using the work of French philosopher Gilles Deleuze as its focus. Deleuze’s engagements with mathematics rely upon the construction of alternative lineages in the history of mathematics in order to reconfigure particular philosophical problems and to develop new concepts. These alternative conceptual histories also challenge some of the self-imposed limits of the discipline of mathematics, and suggest the possibility of forging new connections (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Entropy - A Guide for the Perplexed.Roman Frigg & Charlotte Werndl - 2011 - In Claus Beisbart & Stephan Hartmann (eds.), Probabilities in Physics. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 115-142.
    Entropy is ubiquitous in physics, and it plays important roles in numerous other disciplines ranging from logic and statistics to biology and economics. However, a closer look reveals a complicated picture: entropy is defined differently in different contexts, and even within the same domain different notions of entropy are at work. Some of these are defined in terms of probabilities, others are not. The aim of this chapter is to arrive at an understanding of some of the most important notions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundation of cognitive science.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):111-32.
    The computational view of mind rests on certain intuitions regarding the fundamental similarity between computation and cognition. We examine some of these intuitions and suggest that they derive from the fact that computers and human organisms are both physical systems whose behavior is correctly described as being governed by rules acting on symbolic representations. Some of the implications of this view are discussed. It is suggested that a fundamental hypothesis of this approach is that there is a natural domain of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   665 citations  
  • In the light of time.Arto Annila - 2009 - Proceedings of Royal Society A 465:1173–1198.
    The concept of time is examined using the second law of thermodynamics that was recently formulated as an equation of motion. According to the statistical notion of increasing entropy, flows of energy diminish differences between energy densities that form space. The flow of energy is identified with the flow of time. The non-Euclidean energy landscape, i.e. the curved space–time, is in evolution when energy is flowing down along gradients and levelling the density differences. The flows along the steepest descents, i.e. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cognitive representation and the process-architecture distinction.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):154-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • Computation and symbolization.William E. Smythe - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):151-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reductionism and cognitive flexibility.Frank Keil - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):141-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pylyshyn and perception.William T. Powers - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):148-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Emergence.John H. Holland - 1997 - Philosophica 59 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • (1 other version)What kind of space is cyberspace?Rebecca Bryant - 2001 - Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 5 (1).
    With the advent and growth of electronic communication, the word "cyberspace" has entered into everyday parlance. But what does this word signify? I begin by sketching an equivalence between physical space and cyberspace, showing that they share the concepts of place, distance, size and route in common. With this mutual framework in place, I go on to examine various theories—substantival, relational, Einsteinian and Kantian—concerning the nature of physical space. We see that, while cyberspace shares some of the properties of physical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How are Concepts of Infinity Acquired?Kazimierz Trzęsicki - 2015 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 40 (1):179-217.
    Concepts of infinity have been subjects of dispute since antiquity. The main problems of this paper are: is the mind able to acquire a concept of infinity? and: how are concepts of infinity acquired? The aim of this paper is neither to say what the meanings of the word “infinity” are nor what infinity is and whether it exists. However, those questions will be mentioned, but only in necessary extent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Hare and Others on the Proposition.John Corcoran - 2011 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 15 (1):51-76.
    History witnesses alternative approaches to “the proposition”. The proposition has been referred to as the object of belief, disbelief, and doubt: generally as the object of propositional attitudes, that which can be said to be believed, disbelieved, understood, etc. It has also been taken to be the object of grasping, judging, assuming, affirming, denying, and inquiring: generally as the object of propositional actions, that which can be said to be grasped, judged true or false, assumed for reasoning purposes, etc. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • New directions for nominalist philosophers of mathematics.Charles Chihara - 2010 - Synthese 176 (2):153 - 175.
    The present paper will argue that, for too long, many nominalists have concentrated their researches on the question of whether one could make sense of applications of mathematics (especially in science) without presupposing the existence of mathematical objects. This was, no doubt, due to the enormous influence of Quine's "Indispensability Argument", which challenged the nominalist to come up with an explanation of how science could be done without referring to, or quantifying over, mathematical objects. I shall admonish nominalists to enlarge (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Is nonstandard analysis relevant for the philosophy of mathematics?Jens Erik Fenstad - 1985 - Synthese 62 (2):289 - 301.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Functional architecture and free will.Henry E. Kyburg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):143-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Penetrating the impenetrable.Georges Rey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):149-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jacob Hermann and the Kinetic Theory.W. E. Knowles Middleton - 1965 - British Journal for the History of Science 2 (3):247-250.
    The beginning of the kinetic theory of gases is usually assigned to the year 1738, when Daniel Bernouilli's Hydrodynamica appeared at Strasbourg. The famous tenth section of this book pursued some of the consequences of the assumption that ‘elastic fluids’ consist of innumerable tiny particles in rapid motion. It was, as everyone knows, forgotten for many decades.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functional architectures for cognition: are simple inferences possible?Steven W. Zucker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):153-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computation, cognition, and representation.John Hell - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):139-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computation without representation.Stephen P. Stich - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):152-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Beautiful Art of Mathematics.Adam Rieger - 2018 - Philosophia Mathematica 26 (2):234-250.
    Mathematicians frequently use aesthetic vocabulary and sometimes even describe themselves as engaged in producing art. Yet aestheticians, in so far as they have discussed this at all, have often downplayed the ascriptions of aesthetic properties as metaphorical. In this paper I argue firstly that the aesthetic talk should be taken literally, and secondly that it is at least reasonable to classify some mathematics as art.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)On What There is—Infinitesimals and the Nature of Numbers.Jens Erik Fenstad - 2015 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 58 (1):57-79.
    This essay will be divided into three parts. In the first part, we discuss the case of infintesimals seen as a bridge between the discrete and the continuous. This leads in the second part to a discussion of the nature of numbers. In the last part, we follow up with some observations on the obvious applicability of mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human and computer rules and representations are not equivalent.Stephen Grossberg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):136-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From computational metaphor to consensual algorithms.Kenneth Mark Colby - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):134-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The pythagorean comma: Weber's anticipation of sociology in a new key. [REVIEW]Vito Signorile - 1980 - Human Studies 3 (1):115 - 136.
    Throughout its history the Game was closely allied with music, and usually proceeded according to musical or mathematical rules. One theme, two themes, or three themes were stated, elaborated, varied, and underwent a development quite similar to that of the theme in a Bach fugue or a concerto movement.… Experts and Masters of the Game freely wove the initial theme into unlimited combinations [p. 30].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Logician and the Biologist.George Englebretsen - 2019 - Acta Baltica Historiae Et Philosophiae Scientiarum 7 (1):39-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognition is not computation, for the reasons that computers don't solve the mind-body problems.Walter B. Weimer - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive penetrability: let us not forget about memory.James R. Miller - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):146-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gödel, Nagel, Minds, and Machines.Solomon Feferman - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy 106 (4):201-219.
    Ernest Nagel Lecture, Columbia University, Sept. 27, 2007.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Some remarks on the rationality of induction.Bipin Indurkhya - 1990 - Synthese 85 (1):95 - 114.
    This paper begins with a rigorous critique of David Stove''s recent bookThe Rationality of Induction. In it, Stove produced four different proofs to refute Hume''s sceptical thesis about induction. I show that Stove''s attempts to vindicate induction are unsuccessful. Three of his proofs refute theses that are not the sceptical thesis about induction at all. Stove''s fourth proof, which uses the sampling principle to justify one particular inductive inference, makes crucial use of an unstated assumption regarding randomness. Once this assumption (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The borders of cognition.Earl Hunt - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):140-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a definition of living systems: A theory of ecological support for behavior.Edward S. Reed & Rebecca K. Jones - 1977 - Acta Biotheoretica 26 (3):153-163.
    It is proposed that the Darwinian theoretical approach and account of living systems has not yet been clearly given. A first approximation to this is attempted, focussing on behavior in evolving environments. A theoretical terminology is defined emphasizing the mutuality of organism and environment and the existence of biologically theoretical entities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Role of Mathematics in Liberal Arts Education.Judith V. Grabiner - 2014 - In Michael R. Matthews (ed.), International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching. Springer. pp. 793-836.
    The history of the continuous inclusion of mathematics in liberal education in the West, from ancient times through the modern period, is sketched in the first two sections of this chapter. Next, the heart of this essay (Sects. 3, 4, 5, 6, and 7) delineates the central role mathematics has played throughout the history of Western civilization: not just a tool for science and technology, mathematics continually illuminates, interacts with, and sometimes challenges fields like art, music, literature, and philosophy – (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuroscience and psychology: should the labor be divided?Patricia Smith Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-133.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defence of the armchair.Michael Fortescue - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):135-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychology and computational architecture.John Haugeland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Universal turing machines: An exercise in coding.Hao Wang - 1957 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 3 (6-10):69-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Functional architecture and model validation.Martin Ringle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):150-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explanations in theories of language and of imagery.Steven Pinker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Criteria of cognitive impenetrability.Robert C. Moore - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):146-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computation, consciousness and cognition.George A. Miller - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):146-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The elusive visual processing mode: Implications of the architecture/algorithm distinction.Roberta L. Klatzky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):142-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The reification of the mind-body problem?Stewart H. Hulse - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):139-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A remark on the completeness of the computational model of mind.William Demopoulos - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):135-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark