Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Axiom of Choice

Journal of Symbolic Logic 41 (4):784-785 (1976)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Choice revision.Li Zhang - 2019 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 28 (4):577-599.
    Choice revision is a sort of non-prioritized multiple revision, in which the agent partially accepts the new information represented by a set of sentences. We investigate the construction of choice revision based on a new approach to belief change called descriptor revision. We prove that each of two variants of choice revision based on such construction is axiomatically characterized with a set of plausible postulates, assuming that the object language is finite. Furthermore, we introduce an alternative modelling for choice revision, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond the metrological viewpoint.Jean Baccelli - 2020 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 1:56-61.
    The representational theory of measurement has long been the central paradigm in the philosophy of measurement. Such is not the case anymore, partly under the influence of the critique according to which RTM offers too poor descriptions of the measurement procedures actually followed in science. This can be called the metrological critique of RTM. I claim that the critique is partly irrelevant. This is because, in general, RTM is not in the business of describing measurement procedures, be it in idealized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Relations between cardinalities of the finite sequences and the finite subsets of a set.Navin Aksornthong & Pimpen Vejjajiva - 2018 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 64 (6):529-534.
    We write and for the cardinalities of the set of finite sequences and the set of finite subsets, respectively, of a set which is of cardinality. With the axiom of choice (), for every infinite cardinal but, without, any relationship between and for an arbitrary infinite cardinal cannot be proved. In this paper, we give conditions that make and comparable for an infinite cardinal. Among our results, we show that, if we assume the axiom of choice for sets of finite (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Minimal axiomatic frameworks for definable hyperreals with transfer.Frederik S. Herzberg, Vladimir Kanovei, Mikhail Katz & Vassily Lyubetsky - 2018 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 83 (1):385-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Terminal notions in set theory.Jindřich Zapletal - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 109 (1-2):89-116.
    In mathematical practice certain formulas φ are believed to essentially decide all other natural properties of the object x. The purpose of this paper is to exactly quantify such a belief for four formulas φ, namely “x is a Ramsey ultrafilter”, “x is a free Souslin tree”, “x is an extendible strong Lusin set” and “x is a good diamond sequence”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Versions of Normality and Some Weak Forms of the Axiom of Choice.Paul Howard, Kyriakos Keremedis, Herman Rubin & Jean E. Rubin - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (3):367-382.
    We investigate the set theoretical strength of some properties of normality, including Urysohn's Lemma, Tietze-Urysohn Extension Theorem, normality of disjoint unions of normal spaces, and normality of Fσ subsets of normal spaces.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Extending Independent Sets to Bases and the Axiom of Choice.Kyriakos Keremedis - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (1):92-98.
    We show that the both assertions “in every vector space B over a finite element field every subspace V ⊆ B has a complementary subspace S” and “for every family [MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT CAPITAL A] of disjoint odd sized sets there exists a subfamily ℱ={Fj:j ϵω} with a choice function” together imply the axiom of choice AC. We also show that AC is equivalent to the statement “in every vector space over ℚ every generating set includes a basis”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Extending Partial Orders on o‐Minimal Structures to Definable Total Orders.Dugald Macpherson & Charles Steinhorn - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (4):456-464.
    It is shown that if is an o-minimal structure such that is a dense total order and ≾ is a parameter-definable partial order on M, then ≾ has an extension to a definable total order.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The theorem of the means for cardinal and ordinal numbers.George Rousseau - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):279-286.
    The theorem that the arithmetic mean is greater than or equal to the geometric mean is investigated for cardinal and ordinal numbers. It is shown that whereas the theorem of the means can be proved for n pairwise comparable cardinal numbers without the axiom of choice, the inequality a2 + b2 ≥ 2ab is equivalent to the axiom of choice. For ordinal numbers, the inequality α2 + β2 ≥ 2αβ is established and the conditions for equality are derived; stronger inequalities (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Notions of compactness for special subsets of ℝ I and some weak forms of the axiom of choice.Marianne Morillon - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (1):255-268.
    We work in set-theory without choice ZF. A set is Countable if it is finite or equipotent with ${\Bbb N}$ . Given a closed subset F of [0, 1] I which is a bounded subset of $\ell ^{1}(I)$ (resp. such that $F\subseteq c_{0}(I)$ ), we show that the countable axiom of choice for finite sets, (resp. the countable axiom of choice AC N ) implies that F is compact. This enhances previous results where AC N (resp. the axiom of Dependent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Jonsson-like partition relations and j: V → V.Arthur W. Apter & Grigor Sargsyan - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (4):1267-1281.
    Working in the theory “ZF + There is a nontrivial elementary embedding j: V → V ”, we show that a final segment of cardinals satisfies certain square bracket finite and infinite exponent partition relations. As a corollary to this, we show that this final segment is composed of Jonsson cardinals. We then show how to force and bring this situation down to small alephs. A prototypical result is the construction of a model for ZF in which every cardinal μ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Criticism and growth of mathematical knowledge.Gianluigi Oliveri - 1997 - Philosophia Mathematica 5 (3):228-249.
    This paper attempts to show that mathematical knowledge does not grow by a simple process of accumulation and that it is possible to provide a quasi-empirical (in Lakatos's sense) account of mathematical theories. Arguments supporting the first thesis are based on the study of the changes occurred within Eudidean geometry from the time of Euclid to that of Hilbert; whereas those in favour of the second arise from reflections on the criteria for refutation of mathematical theories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The mathematical development of set theory from Cantor to Cohen.Akihiro Kanamori - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):1-71.
    Set theory is an autonomous and sophisticated field of mathematics, enormously successful not only at its continuing development of its historical heritage but also at analyzing mathematical propositions cast in set-theoretic terms and gauging their consistency strength. But set theory is also distinguished by having begun intertwined with pronounced metaphysical attitudes, and these have even been regarded as crucial by some of its great developers. This has encouraged the exaggeration of crises in foundations and of metaphysical doctrines in general. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Relations between some cardinals in the absence of the axiom of choice.Lorenz Halbeisen & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (2):237-261.
    If we assume the axiom of choice, then every two cardinal numbers are comparable, In the absence of the axiom of choice, this is no longer so. For a few cardinalities related to an arbitrary infinite set, we will give all the possible relationships between them, where possible means that the relationship is consistent with the axioms of set theory. Further we investigate the relationships between some other cardinal numbers in specific permutation models and give some results provable without using (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Ramsey's theorem in the hierarchy of choice principles.Andreas Blass - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (3):387-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Hierarchies For Non-founded Models Of Set Theory. Von Michael & M. Von Rimscha - 1983 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 29 (4):253-288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A neglected resolution of Russell’s paradox of propositions.Gabriel Uzquiano - 2015 - Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):328-344.
    Bertrand Russell offered an influential paradox of propositions in Appendix B of The Principles of Mathematics, but there is little agreement as to what to conclude from it. We suggest that Russell's paradox is best regarded as a limitative result on propositional granularity. Some propositions are, on pain of contradiction, unable to discriminate between classes with different members: whatever they predicate of one, they predicate of the other. When accepted, this remarkable fact should cast some doubt upon some of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Rado's selection lemma does not imply the Boolean prime ideal theorem.Paul E. Howard - 1984 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 30 (9‐11):129-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Strongly Amorphous Sets and Dual Dedekind Infinity.Martin Goldstern - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (1):39-44.
    1. If A is strongly amorphous , then its power set P is dually Dedekind infinite, i. e., every function from P onto P is injective. 2. The class of “inexhaustible” sets is not closed under supersets unless AC holds.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Definitions of Compactness and the Axiom of Choice.Omar De La Cruz, Eric Hall, Paul Howard, Jean E. Rubin & Adrienne Stanley - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (1):143 - 161.
    We study the relationships between definitions of compactness in topological spaces and the roll the axiom of choice plays in these relationships.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • L'axiome de normalité pour Les espaces totalement ordonnés.Labib Haddad & Marianne Morillon - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):277-283.
    We show that the following property (LN) holds in the basic Cohen model as sketched by Jech: The order topology of any linearly ordered set is normal. This proves the independence of the axiom of choice from LN in ZF, and thus settles a question raised by G. Birkhoff (1940) which was partly answered by van Douwen (1985).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The model of set theory generated by countably many generic reals.Andreas Blass - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):732-752.
    Adjoin, to a countable standard model M of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF), a countable set A of independent Cohen generic reals. If one attempts to construct the model generated over M by these reals (not necessarily containing A as an element) as the intersection of all standard models that include M ∪ A, the resulting model fails to satisfy the power set axiom, although it does satisfy all the other ZF axioms. Thus, there is no smallest ZF model including M (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A-Minimal Lattices.John L. Hickman - 1980 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 26 (10-12):181-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem Plus Countable Choice Do Not Imply Dependent Choice.Paul Howard & Jean E. Rubin - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):410-420.
    Two Fraenkel-Mostowski models are constructed in which the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem is true. In both models, AC for countable sets is true, but AC for sets of cardinality 2math image and the 2m = m principle are both false. The Principle of Dependent Choices is true in the first model, but false in the second.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The axiom of choice for well-ordered families and for families of well- orderable sets.Paul Howard & Jean E. Rubin - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (4):1115-1117.
    We show that it is not possible to construct a Fraenkel-Mostowski model in which the axiom of choice for well-ordered families of sets and the axiom of choice for sets are both true, but the axiom of choice is false.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Hahn representation theorem for ℓ-groups in ZFA.D. Gluschankof - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (2):519-524.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Foundations of nominal techniques: logic and semantics of variables in abstract syntax.Murdoch J. Gabbay - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):161-229.
    We are used to the idea that computers operate on numbers, yet another kind of data is equally important: the syntax of formal languages, with variables, binding, and alpha-equivalence. The original application of nominal techniques, and the one with greatest prominence in this paper, is to reasoning on formal syntax with variables and binding. Variables can be modelled in many ways: for instance as numbers (since we usually take countably many of them); as links (since they may `point' to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Disjoint Unions of Topological Spaces and Choice.Paul Howard, Kyriakos Keremedis, Herman Rubin & Jean E. Rubin - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (4):493-508.
    We find properties of topological spaces which are not shared by disjoint unions in the absence of some form of the Axiom of Choice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Lattice Theoretical Equivalences of the Ultrafilter Principle.Yehuda Rav - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (2):131-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Issues in the foundations of science, I: Languages, structures, and models.Newton C. A. da Costa, Décio Krause & Otávio Bueno - unknown
    In this first paper of a series of works on the foundations of science, we examine the significance of logical and mathematical frameworks used in foundational studies. In particular, we emphasize the distinction between the order of a language and the order of a structure to prevent confusing models of scientific theories with first-order structures, and which are studied in standard model theory. All of us are, of course, bound to make abuses of language even in putatively precise contexts. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A completeness theorem for unrestricted first- order languages.Agustin Rayo & Timothy Williamson - 2003 - In J. C. Beall (ed.), Liars and heaps: new essays on paradox. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Here is an account of logical consequence inspired by Bolzano and Tarski. Logical validity is a property of arguments. An argument is a pair of a set of interpreted sentences (the premises) and an interpreted sentence (the conclusion). Whether an argument is logically valid depends only on its logical form. The logical form of an argument is fixed by the syntax of its constituent sentences, the meanings of their logical constituents and the syntactic differences between their non-logical constituents, treated as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Boolean universes above Boolean models.Friedrich Wehrung - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (4):1219-1250.
    We establish several first- or second-order properties of models of first-order theories by considering their elements as atoms of a new universe of set theory and by extending naturally any structure of Boolean model on the atoms to the whole universe. For example, complete f-rings are "boundedly algebraically compact" in the language $(+,-,\cdot,\wedge,\vee,\leq)$ , and the positive cone of a complete l-group with infinity adjoined is algebraically compact in the language (+, ∨, ≤). We also give an example with any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Subgroups of a free group and the axiom of choice.Paul E. Howard - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):458-467.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The consistency of the axiom of universality for the ordering of cardinalities.Marco Forti & Furio Honsell - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):502-509.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Successors of singular cardinals and measurability revisited.Arthur W. Apter - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):492-501.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Łoś's theorem and the axiom of choice.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2019 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 65 (3):280-292.
    In set theory without the Axiom of Choice (), we investigate the problem of the placement of Łoś's Theorem () in the hierarchy of weak choice principles, and answer several open questions from the book Consequences of the Axiom of Choice by Howard and Rubin, as well as an open question by Brunner. We prove a number of results summarised in § 3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Axiom of Choice in Second‐Order Predicate Logic.Christine Gaßner - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (4):533-546.
    The present article deals with the power of the axiom of choice within the second-order predicate logic. We investigate the relationship between several variants of AC and some other statements, known as equivalent to AC within the set theory of Zermelo and Fraenkel with atoms, in Henkin models of the one-sorted second-order predicate logic with identity without operation variables. The construction of models follows the ideas of Fraenkel and Mostowski. It is e. g. shown that the well-ordering theorem for unary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Semantics for first-order superposition logic.Athanassios Tzouvaras - 2019 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 27 (4):570-595.
    We investigate how the sentence choice semantics for propositional superposition logic developed in Tzouvaras could be extended so as to successfully apply to first-order superposition logic. There are two options for such an extension. The apparently more natural one is the formula choice semantics based on choice functions for pairs of arbitrary formulas of the basis language. It is proved however that the universal instantiation scheme of first-order logic, $\varphi \rightarrow \varphi $, is false, as a scheme of tautologies, with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transitivitätsbedingungen.Michael von Rimscha - 1982 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 28 (4‐7):67-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Weak Forms of the Axiom of Choice and the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis.Arthur L. Rubin & Jean E. Rubin - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):7-22.
    In this paper we study some statements similar to the Partition Principle and the Trichotomy. We prove some relationships between these statements, the Axiom of Choice, and the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis. We also prove some independence results. MSC: 03E25, 03E50, 04A25, 04A50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Extreme Choices on Complete Lexicographic Orders.Marianne Morillon - 1991 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 37 (23-24):353-355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Products of some special compact spaces and restricted forms of AC.Kyriakos Keremedis & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (3):996-1006.
    We establish the following results: 1. In ZF (i.e., Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory minus the Axiom of Choice AC), for every set I and for every ordinal number α ≥ ω, the following statements are equivalent: (a) The Tychonoff product of| α| many non-empty finite discrete subsets of I is compact. (b) The union of| α| many non-empty finite subsets of I is well orderable. 2. The statement: For every infinite set I, every closed subset of the Tychonoff product [0, 1] (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Definitions of compact.Paul E. Howard - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):645-655.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On a Remark by Sageev.John L. Hickman - 1979 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 25 (19-24):373-374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consequences of arithmetic for set theory.Lorenz Halbeisen & Saharon Shelah - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (1):30-40.
    In this paper, we consider certain cardinals in ZF (set theory without AC, the axiom of choice). In ZFC (set theory with AC), given any cardinals C and D, either C ≤ D or D ≤ C. However, in ZF this is no longer so. For a given infinite set A consider $\operatorname{seq}^{1 - 1}(A)$ , the set of all sequences of A without repetition. We compare $|\operatorname{seq}^{1 - 1}(A)|$ , the cardinality of this set, to |P(A)|, the cardinality of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • European Summer Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic (Logic Colloquium'88), Padova, 1988.R. Ferro - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):387-435.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some Aspects and Examples of Infinity Notions.J. W. Degen - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (1):111-124.
    I wish to thank Klaus Kühnle who streamlined in [8] several of my definitions and proofs concerning the subject matter of this paper. Some ideas and results arose from discussions with Klaus Leeb. Jan Johannsen discovered some mistakes in an earlier version.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Axiom of Choice in Quantum Theory.Norbert Brunner, Karl Svozil & Matthias Baaz - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):319-340.
    We construct peculiar Hilbert spaces from counterexamples to the axiom of choice. We identify the intrinsically effective Hamiltonians with those observables of quantum theory which may coexist with such spaces. Here a self adjoint operator is intrinsically effective if and only if the Schrödinger equation of its generated semigroup is soluble by means of eigenfunction series expansions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kategoriesätze und multiples auswahlaxiom.Norbert Brunner - 1983 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 29 (8):435-443.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Approximating beppo levi’s principio di approssimazione.Riccardo Bruni & Peter Schuster - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (2):141-169.
    We try to recast in modern terms a choice principle conceived by Beppo Levi, who called it the Approximation Principle. Up to now, there was almost no discussion about Levi’s contribution, due to the quite obscure formulation of AP the author has chosen. After briefly reviewing the historical and philosophical surroundings of Levi’s proposal, we undertake our own attempt at interpreting AP. The idea underlying the principle, as well as the supposed faithfulness of our version to Levi’s original intention, are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark