Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Generalized quantifiers and natural language.John Barwise & Robin Cooper - 1981 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (2):159--219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   603 citations  
  • The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint.Gila Sher - 1991 - MIT Press.
    The Bounds of Logic presents a new philosophical theory of the scope and nature of logic based on critical analysis of the principles underlying modern Tarskian logic and inspired by mathematical and linguistic development. Extracting central philosophical ideas from Tarski’s early work in semantics, Sher questions whether these are fully realized by the standard first-order system. The answer lays the foundation for a new, broader conception of logic. By generally characterizing logical terms, Sher establishes a fundamental result in semantics. Her (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Syllogistic inference.P. N. Johnson-Laird & Bruno G. Bara - 1984 - Cognition 16 (1):1-61.
    This paper reviews current psychological theories of syllogistic inference and establishes that despite their various merits they all contain deficiencies as theories of performance. It presents the results of two experiments, one using syllogisms and the other using three-term series problems, designed to elucidate how the arrangement of terms within the premises affects performance. These data are used in the construction of a theory based on the hypothesis that reasoners construct mental models of the premises, formulate informative conclusions about the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   136 citations  
  • Did Tarski commit "Tarski's fallacy"?Gila Sher - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):653-686.
    In his 1936 paper,On the Concept of Logical Consequence, Tarski introduced the celebrated definition oflogical consequence: “The sentenceσfollows logicallyfrom the sentences of the class Γ if and only if every model of the class Γ is also a model of the sentenceσ.” [55, p. 417] This definition, Tarski said, is based on two very basic intuitions, “essential for the proper concept of consequence” [55, p. 415] and reflecting common linguistic usage: “Consider any class Γ of sentences and a sentence which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Logic, Logics, and Logicism.Solomon Feferman - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (1):31-54.
    The paper starts with an examination and critique of Tarski’s wellknown proposed explication of the notion of logical operation in the type structure over a given domain of individuals as one which is invariant with respect to arbitrary permutations of the domain. The class of such operations has been characterized by McGee as exactly those definable in the language L∞,∞. Also characterized similarly is a natural generalization of Tarski’s thesis, due to Sher, in terms of bijections between domains. My main (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Did Tarski commit “Tarski's fallacy”?G. Y. Sher - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (2):653-686.
    In his 1936 paper,On the Concept of Logical Consequence, Tarski introduced the celebrated definition oflogical consequence: “The sentenceσfollows logicallyfrom the sentences of the class Γ if and only if every model of the class Γ is also a model of the sentenceσ.” [55, p. 417] This definition, Tarski said, is based on two very basic intuitions, “essential for the proper concept of consequence” [55, p. 415] and reflecting common linguistic usage: “Consider any class Γ of sentences and a sentence which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Stationary logic.Jon Barwise - 1978 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 13 (2):171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The foundational problem of logic.Gila Sher - 2013 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 19 (2):145-198.
    The construction of a systematic philosophical foundation for logic is a notoriously difficult problem. In Part One I suggest that the problem is in large part methodological, having to do with the common philosophical conception of “providing a foundation”. I offer an alternative to the common methodology which combines a strong foundational requirement with the use of non-traditional, holistic tools to achieve this result. In Part Two I delineate an outline of a foundation for logic, employing the new methodology. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Tarski's thesis.Gila Sher - 2008 - In Douglas Patterson (ed.), New essays on Tarski and philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 300--339.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Generalized quantifiers and pebble games on finite structures.Phokion G. Kolaitis & Jouko A. Väänänen - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 74 (1):23-75.
    First-order logic is known to have a severely limited expressive power on finite structures. As a result, several different extensions have been investigated, including fragments of second-order logic, fixpoint logic, and the infinitary logic L∞ωω in which every formula has only a finite number of variables. In this paper, we study generalized quantifiers in the realm of finite structures and combine them with the infinitary logic L∞ωω to obtain the logics L∞ωω, where Q = {Qi: iε I} is a family (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Definability hierarchies of general quantifiers.Lauri Hella - 1989 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 43 (3):235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Universal classes near ${\aleph _1}$.Marcos Mazari-Armida & Sebastien Vasey - 2018 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 83 (4):1633-1643.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On the general interpretation of first-order quantifiers.G. Aldo Antonelli - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (4):637-658.
    While second-order quantifiers have long been known to admit nonstandard, or interpretations, first-order quantifiers (when properly viewed as predicates of predicates) also allow a kind of interpretation that does not presuppose the full power-set of that interpretationgeneral” interpretations for (unary) first-order quantifiers in a general setting, emphasizing the effects of imposing various further constraints that the interpretation is to satisfy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Forcing and generalized quantifiers.J. Krivine - 1973 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 5 (3):199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Souslin forcing.Jaime I. Ihoda & Saharon Shelah - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (4):1188-1207.
    We define the notion of Souslin forcing, and we prove that some properties are preserved under iteration. We define a weaker form of Martin's axiom, namely MA(Γ + ℵ 0 ), and using the results on Souslin forcing we show that MA(Γ + ℵ 0 ) is consistent with the existence of a Souslin tree and with the splitting number s = ℵ 1 . We prove that MA(Γ + ℵ 0 ) proves the additivity of measure. Also we introduce (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Computing the Number of Types of Infinite Length.Will Boney - 2017 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 58 (1):133-154.
    We show that the number of types of sequences of tuples of a fixed length can be calculated from the number of 1-types and the length of the sequences. Specifically, if κ≤λ, then sup ‖M‖=λ|Sκ|=|)κ. We show that this holds for any abstract elementary class with λ-amalgamation. No such calculation is possible for nonalgebraic types. However, we introduce a subclass of nonalgebraic types for which the same upper bound holds.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kueker's conjecture for stable theories.Ehud Hrushovski - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):207-220.
    Kueker's conjecture is proved for stable theories, for theories that interpret a linear ordering, and for theories with Skolem functions. The proof of the stable case involves certain results on coordinatization that are of independent interest.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On the existence of regular types.Saharon Shelah & Steven Buechler - 1989 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 45 (3):277-308.
    The main results in the paper are the following. Theorem A. Suppose that T is superstable and M ⊂ N are distinct models of T eq . Then there is a c ϵ N⧹M such that t is regular. For M ⊂ N two models we say that M ⊂ na N if for all a ϵ M and θ such that θ ≠ θ , there is a b ∈ θ ⧹ acl . Theorem B Suppose that T is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Necessarily Maybe. Quantifiers, Modality and Vagueness.Alessandro Torza - 2015 - In Quantifiers, Quantifiers, and Quantifiers. Themes in Logic, Metaphysics, and Language. (Synthese Library vol. 373). Springer. pp. 367-387.
    Languages involving modalities and languages involving vagueness have each been thoroughly studied. On the other hand, virtually nothing has been said about the interaction of modality and vagueness. This paper aims to start filling that gap. Section 1 is a discussion of various possible sources of vague modality. Section 2 puts forward a model theory for a quantified language with operators for modality and vagueness. The model theory is followed by a discussion of the resulting logic. In Section 3, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)On Formalism Freeness: Implementing Gödel's 1946 Princeton Bicentennial Lecture.Juliette Kennedy - 2013 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 19 (3):351-393.
    In this paper we isolate a notion that we call “formalism freeness” from Gödel's 1946 Princeton Bicentennial Lecture, which asks for a transfer of the Turing analysis of computability to the cases of definability and provability. We suggest an implementation of Gödel's idea in the case of definability, via versions of the constructible hierarchy based on fragments of second order logic. We also trace the notion of formalism freeness in the very wide context of developments in mathematical logic in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Models with second order properties IV. A general method and eliminating diamonds.Saharon Shelah - 1983 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 25 (2):183-212.
    We show how to build various models of first-order theories, which also have properties like: tree with only definable branches, atomic Boolean algebras or ordered fields with only definable automorphisms. For this we use a set-theoretic assertion, which may be interesting by itself on the existence of quite generic subsets of suitable partial orders of power λ + , which follows from ♦ λ and even weaker hypotheses . For a related assertion, which is equivalent to the morass see Shelah (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Fragments of Martin's axiom and δ13 sets of reals.Joan Bagaria - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 69 (1):1-25.
    We strengthen a result of Harrington and Shelah by showing that, unless ω1 is an inaccessible cardinal in L, a relatively weak fragment of Martin's axiom implies that there exists a δ13 set of reals without the property of Baire.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Conservative generalized quantifiers and presupposition.Tim Fernando - manuscript
    Conservativity in generalized quantifiers is linked to presupposition filtering, under a propositions-as-types analysis extended with dependent quantifiers. That analysis is underpinned by modeltheoretically interpretable proofs which inhabit propositions they prove, thereby providing objects for quantification and hooks for anaphora.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • An exposition of the compactness of.Enrique Casanovas & Martin Ziegler - 2020 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 26 (3-4):212-218.
    We give an exposition of the compactness of L(QcfC), for any set C of regular cardinals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Omega-categoricity, relative categoricity and coordinatisation.Wilfrid Hodges, I. M. Hodkinson & Dugald Macpherson - 1990 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 46 (2):169-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Harmonious logic: Craig’s interpolation theorem and its descendants.Solomon Feferman - 2008 - Synthese 164 (3):341-357.
    Though deceptively simple and plausible on the face of it, Craig's interpolation theorem has proved to be a central logical property that has been used to reveal a deep harmony between the syntax and semantics of first order logic. Craig's theorem was generalized soon after by Lyndon, with application to the characterization of first order properties preserved under homomorphism. After retracing the early history, this article is mainly devoted to a survey of subsequent generalizations and applications, especially of many-sorted interpolation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A standard model of Peano Arithmetic with no conservative elementary extension.Ali Enayat - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 156 (2):308-318.
    The principal result of this paper answers a long-standing question in the model theory of arithmetic [R. Kossak, J. Schmerl, The Structure of Models of Peano Arithmetic, Oxford University Press, 2006, Question 7] by showing that there exists an uncountable arithmetically closed family of subsets of the set ω of natural numbers such that the expansion of the standard model of Peano arithmetic has no conservative elementary extension, i.e., for any elementary extension of , there is a subset of ω* (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Stability, the f.c.p., and superstability; model theoretic properties of formulas in first order theory.Saharon Shelah - 1971 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 3 (3):271-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • On models with power-like ordering.Saharon Shelah - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (2):247-267.
    We prove here theorems of the form: if T has a model M in which P 1 (M) is κ 1 -like ordered, P 2 (M) is κ 2 -like ordered ..., and Q 1 (M) if of power λ 1 , ..., then T has a model N in which P 1 (M) is κ 1 '-like ordered ..., Q 1 (N) is of power λ 1 ,.... (In this article κ is a strong-limit singular cardinal, and κ' is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Compact extensions of L(Q).Menachem Magidor & Jerome Malitz - 1977 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 11 (2):217--261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Ideal models and some not so ideal problems in the model theory of l(q).Kim B. Bruce - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (2):304-321.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Barwise: Abstract model theory and generalized quantifiers.Jouko Väänänen - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (1):37-53.
    §1. Introduction. After the pioneering work of Mostowski [29] and Lindström [23] it was Jon Barwise's papers [2] and [3] that brought abstract model theory and generalized quantifiers to the attention of logicians in the early seventies. These papers were greeted with enthusiasm at the prospect that model theory could be developed by introducing a multitude of extensions of first order logic, and by proving abstract results about relationships holding between properties of these logics. Examples of such properties areκ-compactness.Any set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Leibnizian models of set theory.Ali Enayat - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):775-789.
    A model is said to be Leibnizian if it has no pair of indiscernibles. Mycielski has shown that there is a first order axiom LM (the Leibniz-Mycielski axiom) such that for any completion T of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory ZF, T has a Leibnizian model if and only if T proves LM. Here we prove: THEOREM A. Every complete theory T extending ZF + LM has $2^{\aleph_{0}}$ nonisomorphic countable Leibnizian models. THEOREM B. If $\kappa$ is aprescribed definable infinite cardinal of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the expressibility hierarchy of Magidor-Malitz quantifiers.Matatyahu Rubin & Saharon Shelah - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (3):542-557.
    We prove that the logics of Magidor-Malitz and their generalization by Rubin are distinct even for PC classes. Let $M \models Q^nx_1 \cdots x_n \varphi(x_1 \cdots x_n)$ mean that there is an uncountable subset A of |M| such that for every $a_1, \ldots, a_n \in A, M \models \varphi\lbrack a_1, \ldots, a_n\rbrack$ . Theorem 1.1 (Shelah) $(\diamond_{\aleph_1})$ . For every n ∈ ω the class $K_{n + 1} = \{\langle A, R\rangle \mid \langle A, R\rangle \models \neg Q^{n + 1} (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Barwise: Abstract Model Theory and Generalized Quantifiers.Jouko Va An Anen - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (1):37-53.
    §1. Introduction. After the pioneering work of Mostowski [29] and Lindström [23] it was Jon Barwise's papers [2] and [3] that brought abstract model theory and generalized quantifiers to the attention of logicians in the early seventies. These papers were greeted with enthusiasm at the prospect that model theory could be developed by introducing a multitude of extensions of first order logic, and by proving abstract results about relationships holding between properties of these logics. Examples of such properties areκ-compactness.Any set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • δ-Logics and generalized quantifiers.J. A. Makowsky - 1976 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 10 (2):155-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Probability logic.Douglas N. Hoover - 1978 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 14 (3):287.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Decidability of Some Logics with Free Quantifier Variables.D. A. Anapolitanos & J. A. Väänänen - 1981 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 27 (2-6):17-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Models with second order properties II. Trees with no undefined branches.Saharon Shelah - 1978 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 14 (1):73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • A cut elimination theorem for stationary logic.M. E. Szabo - 1987 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 33 (C):181-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • In conjunction with qualitative probability.Tim Fernando - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 92 (3):217-234.
    Numerical probabilities are eliminated in favor of qualitative notions, with an eye to isolating what it is about probabilities that is essential to judgements of acceptability. A basic choice point is whether the conjunction of two propositions, each acceptable, must be deemed acceptable. Concepts of acceptability closed under conjunction are analyzed within Keisler's weak logic for generalized quantifiers — or more specifically, filter quantifiers. In a different direction, the notion of a filter is generalized so as to allow sets with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Notes on quasiminimality and excellence.John T. Baldwin - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (3):334-366.
    This paper ties together much of the model theory of the last 50 years. Shelah's attempts to generalize the Morley theorem beyond first order logic led to the notion of excellence, which is a key to the structure theory of uncountable models. The notion of Abstract Elementary Class arose naturally in attempting to prove the categoricity theorem for L ω 1 ,ω (Q). More recently, Zilber has attempted to identify canonical mathematical structures as those whose theory (in an appropriate logic) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Proofs of the Compactness Theorem.Alexander Paseau - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (1):73-98.
    In this study, several proofs of the compactness theorem for propositional logic with countably many atomic sentences are compared. Thereby some steps are taken towards a systematic philosophical study of the compactness theorem. In addition, some related data and morals for the theory of mathematical explanation are presented.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Craig Interpolation Theorem in abstract model theory.Jouko Väänänen - 2008 - Synthese 164 (3):401-420.
    The Craig Interpolation Theorem is intimately connected with the emergence of abstract logic and continues to be the driving force of the field. I will argue in this paper that the interpolation property is an important litmus test in abstract model theory for identifying “natural,” robust extensions of first order logic. My argument is supported by the observation that logics which satisfy the interpolation property usually also satisfy a Lindström type maximality theorem. Admittedly, the range of such logics is small.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • $L_a$.Kim Bruce & H. J. Keisler - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (1):15-28.
    The language $L_A$ is formed by adding the quantifier $\Finv x$ , "few x", to the infinitary logic L A on an admissible set A. A complete axiomatization is obtained for models whose universe is the set of ordinals of A and where $\Finv x$ is interpreted as there exist A-finitely many x. For well-behaved A, every consistent sentence has a model with an A-recursive diagram. A principal tool is forcing for $L_A$.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Characterising Context-Independent Quantifiers and Inferences.Stanisław Krajewski - 2024 - Studia Humana 13 (2):1-8.
    Context is essential in virtually all human activities. Yet some logical notions seem to be context-free. For example, the nature of the universal quantifier, the very meaning of “all”, seems to be independent of the context. At the same time, there are many quantifier expressions, and some are context-independent, while others are not. Similarly, purely logical consequence seems to be context-independent. Yet often we encounter strong inferences, good enough for practical purposes, but not valid. The two types of examples suggest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recursive logic frames.Saharon Shelah & Jouko Väänänen - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (2):151-164.
    We define the concept of a logic frame , which extends the concept of an abstract logic by adding the concept of a syntax and an axiom system. In a recursive logic frame the syntax and the set of axioms are recursively coded. A recursive logic frame is called complete , if every finite consistent theory has a model. We show that for logic frames built from the cardinality quantifiers “there exists at least λ ” completeness always implies .0-compactness. On (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Downward transfer of satisfiability for sentences of L 1,1.Jerome Malitz - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (4):1146-1150.
    The quantifier Q m,n binds m + n variables. In the κ-interpretation $M \models Q^{m,n} \bar{x}, \bar{y}\phi\bar{x}, \bar{y}$ means that there is a κ-powered proper subset X of |M| such that whenever ā ∈ mX and b̄ ∈ n X̃ then $M \models \phi\bar{a}, \bar{b}$. If σ ∈ L m,n has a model in the κ-interpretation does it have a model in the λ-interpretation? For σ ∈ L 1,1, κ regular and uncountable, and λ = ω 1 the answer is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Preserving Non-null with Suslin+ Forcings.Jakob Kellner - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (6):649-664.
    We introduce the notion of effective Axiom A and use it to show that some popular tree forcings are Suslin+. We introduce transitive nep and present a simplified version of Shelah’s “preserving a little implies preserving much”: If I is a Suslin ccc ideal (e.g. Lebesgue-null or meager) and P is a transitive nep forcing (e.g. P is Suslin+) and P does not make any I-positive Borel set small, then P does not make any I-positive set small.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An axiomatic approach to rank in model theory.J. T. Baldwin - 1974 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 7 (2-3):295-324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations