Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Leo Esakia on Duality in Modal and Intuitionistic Logics.Guram Bezhanishvili (ed.) - 2014 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This volume is dedicated to Leo Esakia's contributions to the theory of modal and intuitionistic systems. Consisting of 10 chapters, written by leading experts, this volume discusses Esakia’s original contributions and consequent developments that have helped to shape duality theory for modal and intuitionistic logics and to utilize it to obtain some major results in the area. Beginning with a chapter which explores Esakia duality for S4-algebras, the volume goes on to explore Esakia duality for Heyting algebras and its generalizations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Lifschitz realizability for intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.Ray-Ming Chen & Michael Rathjen - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (7-8):789-818.
    A variant of realizability for Heyting arithmetic which validates Church’s thesis with uniqueness condition, but not the general form of Church’s thesis, was introduced by Lifschitz (Proc Am Math Soc 73:101–106, 1979). A Lifschitz counterpart to Kleene’s realizability for functions (in Baire space) was developed by van Oosten (J Symb Log 55:805–821, 1990). In that paper he also extended Lifschitz’ realizability to second order arithmetic. The objective here is to extend it to full intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, IZF. The machinery (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Empirical Negation.Michael De - 2013 - Acta Analytica 28 (1):49-69.
    An extension of intuitionism to empirical discourse, a project most seriously taken up by Dummett and Tennant, requires an empirical negation whose strength lies somewhere between classical negation (‘It is unwarranted that. . . ’) and intuitionistic negation (‘It is refutable that. . . ’). I put forward one plausible candidate that compares favorably to some others that have been propounded in the literature. A tableau calculus is presented and shown to be strongly complete.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Constructions, proofs and the meaning of logical constants.Göran Sundholm - 1983 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (2):151 - 172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • logicism, intuitionism, and formalism - What has become of them?Sten Lindstr©œm, Erik Palmgren, Krister Segerberg & Viggo Stoltenberg-Hansen (eds.) - 2008 - Berlin, Germany: Springer.
    The period in the foundations of mathematics that started in 1879 with the publication of Frege's Begriffsschrift and ended in 1931 with Gödel's Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I can reasonably be called the classical period. It saw the development of three major foundational programmes: the logicism of Frege, Russell and Whitehead, the intuitionism of Brouwer, and Hilbert's formalist and proof-theoretic programme. In this period, there were also lively exchanges between the various schools culminating in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)A proof-theoretical analysis of semiconstructive intermediate theories.Mauro Ferrari & Camillo Fiorentini - 2003 - Studia Logica 73 (1):21 - 49.
    In the 80's Pierangelo Miglioli, starting from motivations in the framework of Abstract Data Types and Program Synthesis, introduced semiconstructive theories, a family of large subsystems of classical theories that guarantee the computability of functions and predicates represented by suitable formulas. In general, the above computability results are guaranteed by algorithms based on a recursive enumeration of the theorems of the whole system. In this paper we present a family of semiconstructive systems, we call uniformly semiconstructive, that provide computational procedures (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paradox and Potential Infinity.Charles McCarty - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (1):195-219.
    We describe a variety of sets internal to models of intuitionistic set theory that (1) manifest some of the crucial behaviors of potentially infinite sets as described in the foundational literature going back to Aristotle, and (2) provide models for systems of predicative arithmetic. We close with a brief discussion of Church’s Thesis for predicative arithmetic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Natural factors of the Medvedev lattice capturing IPC.Rutger Kuyper - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (7):865-879.
    Skvortsova showed that there is a factor of the Medvedev lattice which captures intuitionistic propositional logic (IPC). However, her factor is unnatural in the sense that it is constructed in an ad hoc manner. We present a more natural example of such a factor. We also show that the theory of every non-trivial factor of the Medvedev lattice is contained in Jankov’s logic, the deductive closure of IPC plus the weak law of the excluded middle $${\neg p \vee \neg \neg (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On Paradoxes in Normal Form.Mattia Petrolo & Paolo Pistone - 2019 - Topoi 38 (3):605-617.
    A proof-theoretic test for paradoxicality was famously proposed by Tennant: a paradox must yield a closed derivation of absurdity with no normal form. Drawing on the remark that all derivations of a given proposition can be transformed into derivations in normal form of a logically equivalent proposition, we investigate the possibility of paradoxes in normal form. We compare paradoxes à la Tennant and paradoxes in normal form from the viewpoint of the computational interpretation of proofs and from the viewpoint of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Topologies and free constructions.Anna Bucalo & Giuseppe Rosolini - 2013 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 22 (3):327-346.
    The standard presentation of topological spaces relies heavily on (naïve) set theory: a topology consists of a set of subsets of a set (of points). And many of the high-level tools of set theory are required to achieve just the basic results about topological spaces. Concentrating on the mathematical structures, category theory offers the possibility to look synthetically at the structure of continuous transformations between topological spaces addressing specifically how the fundamental notions of point and open come about. As a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Possibilities, models, and intuitionistic logic: Ian Rumfitt’s The boundary stones of thought.Stewart Shapiro - 2019 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (7):812-825.
    ABSTRACTAIan Rumfitt's new book presents a distinctive and intriguing philosophy of logic, one that ultimately settles on classical logic as the uniquely correct one–or at least rebuts some prominent arguments against classical logic. The purpose of this note is to evaluate Rumfitt's perspective by focusing on some themes that have occupied me for some time: the role and importance of model theory and, in particular, the place of counter-arguments in establishing invalidity, higher-order logic, and the logical pluralism/relativism articulated in my (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Context of Inference.Curtis Franks - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (4):365-395.
    There is an ambiguity in the concept of deductive validity that went unnoticed until the middle of the twentieth century. Sometimes an inference rule is called valid because its conclusion is a theorem whenever its premises are. But often something different is meant: The rule's conclusion follows from its premises even in the presence of other assumptions. In many logical environments, these two definitions pick out the same rules. But other environments are context-sensitive, and in these environments the second notion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophy of mathematics and computer science.Kazimierz Trzęsicki - 2010 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 22 (35).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kripke Models, Distributive Lattices, and Medvedev Degrees.Sebastiaan A. Terwijn - 2007 - Studia Logica 85 (3):319-332.
    We define a variant of the standard Kripke semantics for intuitionistic logic, motivated by the connection between constructive logic and the Medvedev lattice. We show that while the new semantics is still complete, it gives a simple and direct correspondence between Kripke models and algebraic structures such as factors of the Medvedev lattice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Notes on Constructive Negation.Grigori Mints - 2006 - Synthese 148 (3):701-717.
    We put together several observations on constructive negation. First, Russell anticipated intuitionistic logic by clearly distinguishing propositional principles implying the law of the excluded middle from remaining valid principles. He stated what was later called Peirce’s law. This is important in connection with the method used later by Heyting for developing his axiomatization of intuitionistic logic. Second, a work by Dragalin and his students provides easy embeddings of classical arithmetic and analysis into intuitionistic negationless systems. In the last section, we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark