Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Logic Reduced To (Proof-Theoretical) Bare Bones.Jaroslav Peregrin - 2015 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 24 (2):193-209.
    What is a minimal proof-theoretical foundation of logic? Two different ways to answer this question may appear to offer themselves: reduce the whole of logic either to the relation of inference, or else to the property of incompatibility. The first way would involve defining logical operators in terms of the algebraic properties of the relation of inference—with conjunction $$\hbox {A}\wedge \hbox {B}$$ A ∧ B as the infimum of A and B, negation $$\lnot \hbox {A}$$ ¬ A as the minimal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Reality of Existence and Identity.Ian Hacking - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (4):613 - 632.
    “The confusion of a logical with a real predicate,” according to the Critique of Pure Reason, “is almost beyond correction”. Kant did not assert that existence is no predicate, but that it is only a “logical” one, and not a “real” one. Much the same thing has been said about identity, although Kant himself thought it is real and not logical. We have long lacked a rigorous criterion to distinguish real from logical predicates, and hence have not been able to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On Inversion Principles.Enrico Moriconi & Laura Tesconi - 2008 - History and Philosophy of Logic 29 (2):103-113.
    The idea of an ?inversion principle?, and the name itself, originated in the work of Paul Lorenzen in the 1950s, as a method to generate new admissible rules within a certain syntactic context. Some fifteen years later, the idea was taken up by Dag Prawitz to devise a strategy of normalization for natural deduction calculi (this being an analogue of Gentzen's cut-elimination theorem for sequent calculi). Later, Prawitz used the inversion principle again, attributing it with a semantic role. Still working (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Continuum, name and paradox.Vojtěch Kolman - 2010 - Synthese 175 (3):351 - 367.
    The article deals with Cantor's argument for the non-denumerability of reals somewhat in the spirit of Lakatos' logic of mathematical discovery. At the outset Cantor's proof is compared with some other famous proofs such as Dedekind's recursion theorem, showing that rather than usual proofs they are resolutions to do things differently. Based on this I argue that there are "ontologically" safer ways of developing the diagonal argument into a full-fledged theory of continuum, concluding eventually that famous semantic paradoxes based on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant’s Theory of Arithmetic: A Constructive Approach?Kristina Engelhard & Peter Mittelstaedt - 2008 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 39 (2):245-271.
    Kant's theory of arithmetic is not only a central element in his theoretical philosophy but also an important contribution to the philosophy of arithmetic as such. However, modern mathematics, especially non-Euclidean geometry, has placed much pressure on Kant's theory of mathematics. But objections against his theory of geometry do not necessarily correspond to arguments against his theory of arithmetic and algebra. The goal of this article is to show that at least some important details in Kant's theory of arithmetic can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reflecting rules: A note on generalizing the deduction theorem.Gillman Payette - 2015 - Journal of Applied Logic 13 (3):188-196.
    The purpose of this brief note is to prove a limitative theorem for a generalization of the deduction theorem. I discuss the relationship between the deduction theorem and rules of inference. Often when the deduction theorem is claimed to fail, particularly in the case of normal modal logics, it is the result of a confusion over what the deduction theorem is trying to show. The classic deduction theorem is trying to show that all so-called ‘derivable rules’ can be encoded into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dialogical Harmony: tonk, constructive type theory and rules for anonymous players.Juan Redmond & Shahid Rahman - unknown
    Recent literature on dialogical logic discusses the case of tonk and the notion harmony in the context of a rule-based theory of meaning. Now, since the publications of those papers, a dialogical version of constructive type theory has been developed. The aim of the present paper is to show that, from the dialogical point of view, the harmony of the CTT-rules is the consequence of a more fundamental level of meaning characterized by the independence of players. We hope that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Calculus of Higher-Level Rules, Propositional Quantification, and the Foundational Approach to Proof-Theoretic Harmony.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2014 - Studia Logica 102 (6):1185-1216.
    We present our calculus of higher-level rules, extended with propositional quantification within rules. This makes it possible to present general schemas for introduction and elimination rules for arbitrary propositional operators and to define what it means that introductions and eliminations are in harmony with each other. This definition does not presuppose any logical system, but is formulated in terms of rules themselves. We therefore speak of a foundational account of proof-theoretic harmony. With every set of introduction rules a canonical elimination (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (1 other version)Jak pojmenovat reálné číslo?Vojtěch Kolman - 2011 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 18 (3):283-301.
    The article deals with Cantor’s diagonal argument and its alleged philosophical consequences such as that there are more reals than integers and, hence, that some of the reals must be independent of language because the totality of words and sentences is always count-able. My claim is that the main flaw of the argument for the existence of non-nameable objects or truths lies in a very superficial understanding of what a name or representation actually is.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are the Laws of Quantum Logic Laws of Nature?Peter Mittelstaedt - 2012 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 43 (2):215-222.
    The main goal of quantum logic is the bottom-up reconstruction of quantum mechanics in Hilbert space. Here we discuss the question whether quantum logic is an empirical structure or a priori valid. There are good reasons for both possibilities. First, with respect to the possibility of a rational reconstruction of quantum mechanics, quantum logic follows a priori from quantum ontology and can thus not be considered as a law of nature. Second, since quantum logic allows for a reconstruction of quantum (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Symbolic Languages and Natural Structures a Mathematician’s Account of Empiricism.Hermann G. W. Burchard - 2005 - Foundations of Science 10 (2):153-245.
    The ancient dualism of a sensible and an intelligible world important in Neoplatonic and medieval philosophy, down to Descartes and Kant, would seem to be supplanted today by a scientific view of mind-in-nature. Here, we revive the old dualism in a modified form, and describe mind as a symbolic language, founded in linguistic recursive computation according to the Church-Turing thesis, constituting a world L that serves the human organism as a map of the Universe U. This methodological distinction of L (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Lógica clásica y esquizofrenia: por una semántica lúdica.Juan Redmond & Rodrigo Lopez-Orellana - 2018 - Revista de filosofía (Chile) 74:215-241.
    Resumen:En este artículo delineamos una propuesta para elaborar una lógica de las ficciones desde el enfoque lúdico del pragmatismo dialógico. En efecto, centrados en una de las críticas mayores al enfoque clásico de la lógica: la esquizofrenia estructural de su semántica (Lambert 2004: 142-143; 160), recorremos los compromisos ontológicos de las dos tradiciones mayores de la lógica (Aristóteles y Frege) para establecer sus posibilidades y límites en el análisis del discurso ficcional, y la superación desde una perspectiva lúdico pragmática.Palabras clave: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Almost structural completeness; an algebraic approach.Wojciech Dzik & Michał M. Stronkowski - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (7):525-556.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • (1 other version)Predicativity.Solomon Feferman - 2005 - In Stewart Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 590-624.
    What is predicativity? While the term suggests that there is a single idea involved, what the history will show is that there are a number of ideas of predicativity which may lead to different logical analyses, and I shall uncover these only gradually. A central question will then be what, if anything, unifies them. Though early discussions are often muddy on the concepts and their employment, in a number of important respects they set the stage for the further developments, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • (1 other version)Übersetzung von algorithmischen Formelsprachen in die Programmsprachen von Rechenmaschinen.H. Bottenbruch - 1958 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 4 (12-16):180-221.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Validity Concepts in Proof-theoretic Semantics.Peter Schroeder-Heister - 2006 - Synthese 148 (3):525-571.
    The standard approach to what I call “proof-theoretic semantics”, which is mainly due to Dummett and Prawitz, attempts to give a semantics of proofs by defining what counts as a valid proof. After a discussion of the general aims of proof-theoretic semantics, this paper investigates in detail various notions of proof-theoretic validity and offers certain improvements of the definitions given by Prawitz. Particular emphasis is placed on the relationship between semantic validity concepts and validity concepts used in normalization theory. It (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • Protowissenschaft Und RekonstruktionProtoscience and reconstruction.Dirk Hartmann - 1996 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 27 (1):55-69.
    Protoscience and Reconstruction. A central concept of the constructivist philosophy of science is the term 'protoscience'. From an orthodox point of view, protosciences are bound to give the so called 'measurement-theoretical Apriori' for a science. Protophysics for example defines the quantities 'length', 'time', and 'mass'. Thereby it yields some basic physical laws, which usually are regarded as "laws of nature", but in fact follow already from the definitions of the basic quantities. The attempt to establish other protodisciplines than protophysics is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The nets of reason.Johan van Benthem - 2012 - Argument and Computation 3 (2-3):83 - 86.
    Argument & Computation, Volume 3, Issue 2-3, Page 83-86, June–September 2012.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Hintikka’s Take on the Axiom of Choice and the Constructivist Challenge.Radmila Jovanović - 2013 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 2:135-150.
    In the present paper we confront Martin- Löf’s analysis of the axiom of choice with J. Hintikka’s standing on this axiom. Hintikka claims that his game theoretical semantics for Independence Friendly Logic justifies Zermelo’s axiom of choice in a first-order way perfectly acceptable for the constructivists. In fact, Martin- Löf’s results lead to the following considerations:Hintikka preferred version of the axiom of choice is indeed acceptable for the constructivists and its meaning does not involve higher order logic.However, the version acceptable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Context of Inference.Curtis Franks - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (4):365-395.
    There is an ambiguity in the concept of deductive validity that went unnoticed until the middle of the twentieth century. Sometimes an inference rule is called valid because its conclusion is a theorem whenever its premises are. But often something different is meant: The rule's conclusion follows from its premises even in the presence of other assumptions. In many logical environments, these two definitions pick out the same rules. But other environments are context-sensitive, and in these environments the second notion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Wahrheit, Wirklichkeit und Logik in der Sprache der Physik.Peter Mittelstaedt - 1983 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 14 (1):24-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the Proof-theoretic Foundation of General Definition Theory.Lars Hallnäs - 2006 - Synthese 148 (3):589-602.
    A general definition theory should serve as a foundation for the mathematical study of definitional structures. The central notion of such a theory is a precise explication of the intuitively given notion of a definitional structure. The purpose of this paper is to discuss the proof theory of partial inductive definitions as a foundation for this kind of a more general definition theory. Among the examples discussed is a suggestion for a more abstract definition of lambda-terms (derivations in natural deduction) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Dialogue foundations: A sceptical look: Wilfrid Hodges.Wilfrid Hodges - 2001 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 75 (1):17–32.
    During the last forty or so years it has become popular to offer explanations of logical notions in terms of games. There is no doubt that many people find games helpful for understanding various logical phenomena. But we ask whether anything is really 'explained' by these accounts, and we analyse Paul Lorenzen's dialogue foundations for constructive logic as an example. The conclusion is that the value of games lies in their ability to provide helpful metaphors and representations, rather than in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • General-Elimination Stability.Bruno Jacinto & Stephen Read - 2017 - Studia Logica 105 (2):361-405.
    General-elimination harmony articulates Gentzen’s idea that the elimination-rules are justified if they infer from an assertion no more than can already be inferred from the grounds for making it. Dummett described the rules as not only harmonious but stable if the E-rules allow one to infer no more and no less than the I-rules justify. Pfenning and Davies call the rules locally complete if the E-rules are strong enough to allow one to infer the original judgement. A method is given (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Logics and algebras for multiple players.Loes Olde Loohuis & Yde Venema - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (3):485-519.
    We study a generalization of the standard syntax and game-theoretic semantics of logic, which is based on a duality between two players, to a multiplayer setting. We define propositional and modal languages of multiplayer formulas, and provide them with a semantics involving a multiplayer game. Our focus is on the notion of equivalence between two formulas, which is defined by saying that two formulas are equivalent if under each valuation, the set of players with a winning strategy is the same (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Russian Text Ignored.H. A. [Russian Text Ignored] - 1958 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 4 (17-20):293-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A formalization of a nominalistic set theory.C. Chihara, Y. Lin & T. Schaffter - 1975 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 4 (2):155 - 169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rules for subatomic derivation.Bartosz Więckowski - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):219-236.
    In proof-theoretic semantics the meaning of an atomic sentence is usually determined by a set of derivations in an atomic system which contain that sentence as a conclusion (see, in particular, Prawitz, 1971, 1973). The paper critically discusses this standard approach and suggests an alternative account which proceeds in terms of subatomic introduction and elimination rules for atomic sentences. A simple subatomic normal form theorem by which this account of the semantics of atomic sentences and the terms from which they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Different Notions of Constructivity — their Ontology.Amitabha Ghose - 1978 - Dialectica 32 (3‐4):245-253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Steps Towards a Proof-Theoretical Semantics.Enrico Moriconi - 2012 - Topoi 31 (1):67-75.
    The aim of this paper is to reconsider several proposals that have been put forward in order to develop a Proof-Theoretical Semantics, from the by now classical neo-verificationist approach provided by D. Prawitz and M. Dummett in the Seventies, to an alternative, more recent approach mainly due to the work of P. Schroeder-Heister and L. Hallnäs, based on clausal definitions. Some other intermediate proposals are very briefly sketched. Particular attention will be given to the role played by the so-called Fundamental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Modal foundations of probability theory.Wulf Rehder - 1981 - Erkenntnis 16 (1):61 - 71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adventures of abstraction.Ignacio Angelelli - 2004 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 82 (1):11-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations