Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The least weakly compact cardinal can be unfoldable, weakly measurable and nearly $${\theta}$$ θ -supercompact.Brent Cody, Moti Gitik, Joel David Hamkins & Jason A. Schanker - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (5-6):491-510.
    We prove from suitable large cardinal hypotheses that the least weakly compact cardinal can be unfoldable, weakly measurable and even nearly θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\theta}$$\end{document}-supercompact, for any desired θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\theta}$$\end{document}. In addition, we prove several global results showing how the entire class of weakly compactcardinals, a proper class, can be made to coincide with the class of unfoldable cardinals, with the class of weakly measurable cardinals or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Global singularization and the failure of SCH.Radek Honzik - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (7):895-915.
    We say that κ is μ-hypermeasurable for a cardinal μ≥κ+ if there is an embedding j:V→M with critical point κ such that HV is included in M and j>μ. Such a j is called a witnessing embedding.Building on the results in [7], we will show that if V satisfies GCH and F is an Easton function from the regular cardinals into cardinals satisfying some mild restrictions, then there exists a cardinal-preserving forcing extension V* where F is realised on all V-regular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • More on the Least Strongly Compact Cardinal.Arthur W. Apter - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (3):427-430.
    We show that it is consistent, relative to a supercompact limit of supercompact cardinals, for the least strongly compact cardinal k to be both the least measurable cardinal and to be > 2k supercompact.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On löwenheim–skolem–tarski numbers for extensions of first order logic.Menachem Magidor & Jouko Väänänen - 2011 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 11 (1):87-113.
    We show that, assuming the consistency of a supercompact cardinal, the first inaccessible cardinal can satisfy a strong form of a Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski theorem for the equicardinality logic L, a logic introduced in [5] strictly between first order logic and second order logic. On the other hand we show that in the light of present day inner model technology, nothing short of a supercompact cardinal suffices for this result. In particular, we show that the Löwenheim–Skolem–Tarski theorem for the equicardinality logic at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Co-critical points of elementary embeddings.Michael Sheard - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):220-226.
    Probably the two most famous examples of elementary embeddings between inner models of set theory are the embeddings of the universe into an inner model given by a measurable cardinal and the embeddings of the constructible universeLinto itself given by 0#. In both of these examples, the “target model” is a subclass of the “ground model”. It is not hard to find examples of embeddings in which the target model is not a subclass of the ground model: ifis a generic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Indestructibility and the level-by-level agreement between strong compactness and supercompactness.Arthur W. Apter & Joel David Hamkins - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (2):820-840.
    Can a supercompact cardinal κ be Laver indestructible when there is a level-by-level agreement between strong compactness and supercompactness? In this article, we show that if there is a sufficiently large cardinal above κ, then no, it cannot. Conversely, if one weakens the requirement either by demanding less indestructibility, such as requiring only indestructibility by stratified posets, or less level-by-level agreement, such as requiring it only on measure one sets, then yes, it can.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Identity crises and strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter & James Cummings - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (4):1895-1910.
    Combining techniques of the first author and Shelah with ideas of Magidor, we show how to get a model in which, for fixed but arbitrary finite n, the first n strongly compact cardinals κ 1 ,..., κ n are so that κ i for i = 1,..., n is both the i th measurable cardinal and κ + i supercompact. This generalizes an unpublished theorem of Magidor and answers a question of Apter and Shelah.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Contributions to the Theory of Large Cardinals through the Method of Forcing.Alejandro Poveda - 2021 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 27 (2):221-222.
    The dissertation under comment is a contribution to the area of Set Theory concerned with the interactions between the method of Forcing and the so-called Large Cardinal axioms.The dissertation is divided into two thematic blocks. In Block I we analyze the large-cardinal hierarchy between the first supercompact cardinal and Vopěnka’s Principle. In turn, Block II is devoted to the investigation of some problems arising from Singular Cardinal Combinatorics.We commence Part I by investigating the Identity Crisis phenomenon in the region comprised (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strong Compactness, Square, Gch, and Woodin Cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-9.
    We show the consistency, relative to the appropriate supercompactness or strong compactness assumptions, of the existence of a non-supercompact strongly compact cardinal $\kappa _0$ (the least measurable cardinal) exhibiting properties which are impossible when $\kappa _0$ is supercompact. In particular, we construct models in which $\square _{\kappa ^+}$ holds for every inaccessible cardinal $\kappa $ except $\kappa _0$, GCH fails at every inaccessible cardinal except $\kappa _0$, and $\kappa _0$ is less than the least Woodin cardinal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The tree property at the successor of a singular limit of measurable cardinals.Mohammad Golshani - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (1-2):3-25.
    Assume \ is a singular limit of \ supercompact cardinals, where \ is a limit ordinal. We present two methods for arranging the tree property to hold at \ while making \ the successor of the limit of the first \ measurable cardinals. The first method is then used to get, from the same assumptions, the tree property at \ with the failure of SCH at \. This extends results of Neeman and Sinapova. The second method is also used to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • All uncountable cardinals in the Gitik model are almost Ramsey and carry Rowbottom filters.Arthur W. Apter, Ioanna M. Dimitriou & Peter Koepke - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (3):225-231.
    Using the analysis developed in our earlier paper, we show that every uncountable cardinal in Gitik's model of in which all uncountable cardinals are singular is almost Ramsey and is also a Rowbottom cardinal carrying a Rowbottom filter. We assume that the model of is constructed from a proper class of strongly compact cardinals, each of which is a limit of measurable cardinals. Our work consequently reduces the best previously known upper bound in consistency strength for the theory math formula (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Many Normal Measures.Shimon Garti - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (3):349-357.
    We characterize the situation of having at least $^{+}$-many normal ultrafilters on a measurable cardinal $\kappa$. We also show that if $\kappa$ is a compact cardinal, then $\kappa$ carries $^{+}$-many $\kappa$-complete ultrafilters, each of which extends the club filter on $\kappa$.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The wholeness axiom and Laver sequences.Paul Corazza - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 105 (1-3):157-260.
    In this paper we introduce the Wholeness Axiom , which asserts that there is a nontrivial elementary embedding from V to itself. We formalize the axiom in the language {∈, j } , adding to the usual axioms of ZFC all instances of Separation, but no instance of Replacement, for j -formulas, as well as axioms that ensure that j is a nontrivial elementary embedding from the universe to itself. We show that WA has consistency strength strictly between I 3 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Partial near supercompactness.Jason Aaron Schanker - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (2):67-85.
    A cardinal κ is nearly θ-supercompact if for every A⊆θ, there exists a transitive M⊨ZFC− closed under θ and j″θ∈N.2 This concept strictly refines the θ-supercompactness hierarchy as every θ-supercompact cardinal is nearly θ-supercompact, and every nearly 2θ<κ-supercompact cardinal κ is θ-supercompact. Moreover, if κ is a θ-supercompact cardinal for some θ such that θ<κ=θ, we can move to a forcing extension preserving all cardinals below θ++ where κ remains θ-supercompact but is not nearly θ+-supercompact. We will also show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Weakly measurable cardinals.Jason A. Schanker - 2011 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 57 (3):266-280.
    In this article, we introduce the notion of weakly measurable cardinal, a new large cardinal concept obtained by weakening the familiar concept of a measurable cardinal. Specifically, a cardinal κ is weakly measurable if for any collection equation image containing at most κ+ many subsets of κ, there exists a nonprincipal κ-complete filter on κ measuring all sets in equation image. Every measurable cardinal is weakly measurable, but a weakly measurable cardinal need not be measurable. Moreover, while the GCH cannot (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Tall cardinals.Joel D. Hamkins - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (1):68-86.
    A cardinal κ is tall if for every ordinal θ there is an embedding j: V → M with critical point κ such that j > θ and Mκ ⊆ M. Every strong cardinal is tall and every strongly compact cardinal is tall, but measurable cardinals are not necessarily tall. It is relatively consistent, however, that the least measurable cardinal is tall. Nevertheless, the existence of a tall cardinal is equiconsistent with the existence of a strong cardinal. Any tall cardinal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Universal partial indestructibility and strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (5):524-531.
    For any ordinal δ, let λδ be the least inaccessible cardinal above δ. We force and construct a model in which the least supercompact cardinal κ is indestructible under κ-directed closed forcing and in which every measurable cardinal δ < κ is < λδ strongly compact and has its < λδ strong compactness indestructible under δ-directed closed forcing of rank less than λδ. In this model, κ is also the least strongly compact cardinal. We also establish versions of this result (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Failure of GCH and the level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (6):587.
    We force and obtain three models in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds and in which, below the least supercompact cardinal, GCH fails unboundedly often. In two of these models, GCH fails on a set having measure 1 with respect to certain canonical measures. There are no restrictions in all of our models on the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Forcing the Least Measurable to Violate GCH.Arthur W. Apter - 1999 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 45 (4):551-560.
    Starting with a model for “GCH + k is k+ supercompact”, we force and construct a model for “k is the least measurable cardinal + 2k = K+”. This model has the property that forcing over it with Add preserves the fact k is the least measurable cardinal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Identity crises and strong compactness III: Woodin cardinals. [REVIEW]Arthur W. Apter & Grigor Sargsyan - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (3):307-322.
    We show that it is consistent, relative to n ∈ ω supercompact cardinals, for the strongly compact and measurable Woodin cardinals to coincide precisely. In particular, it is consistent for the first n strongly compact cardinals to be the first n measurable Woodin cardinals, with no cardinal above the n th strongly compact cardinal being measurable. In addition, we show that it is consistent, relative to a proper class of supercompact cardinals, for the strongly compact cardinals and the cardinals which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A new proof of a theorem of Magidor.Arthur W. Apter - 2000 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 39 (3):209-211.
    We give a new proof using iterated Prikry forcing of Magidor's theorem that it is consistent to assume that the least strongly compact cardinal is the least supercompact cardinal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Extended ultrapowers and the vopěnka-hrbáček theorem without choice.Mitchell Spector - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (2):592-607.
    We generalize the ultrapower in a way suitable for choiceless set theory. Given an ultrafilter, forcing is used to construct an extended ultrapower of the universe, designed so that the fundamental theorem of ultrapowers holds even in the absence of the axiom of choice. If, in addition, we assume DC, then an extended ultrapower of the universe by a countably complete ultrafilter must be well-founded. As an application, we prove the Vopěnka-Hrbáček theorem from ZF + DC only (the proof of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the ordering of certain large cardinals.Carl F. Morgenstern - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (4):563-565.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Measurability and degrees of strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (2):249-254.
    We prove, relative to suitable hypotheses, that it is consistent for there to be unboundedly many measurable cardinals each of which possesses a large degree of strong compactness, and that it is consistent to assume that the least measurable is partially strongly compact and that the second measurable is strongly compact. These results partially answer questions of Magidor on the relationship of strong compactness to measurability.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Some results concerning strongly compact cardinals.Yoshihiro Abe - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (4):874-880.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Restrictions of Ultrafilters From Generic Extensions to Ground Models.Moti Gitik & Eyal Kaplan - 2023 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 88 (1):169-190.
    Let P be a forcing notion and $G\subseteq P$ its generic subset. Suppose that we have in $V[G]$ a $\kappa{-}$ complete ultrafilter1,2W over $\kappa $. Set $U=W\cap V$.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Indestructibility when the first two measurable cardinals are strongly compact.Arthur W. Apter - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (1):214-227.
    We prove two theorems concerning indestructibility properties of the first two strongly compact cardinals when these cardinals are in addition the first two measurable cardinals. Starting from two supercompact cardinals $\kappa _1 < \kappa _2$, we force and construct a model in which $\kappa _1$ and $\kappa _2$ are both the first two strongly compact and first two measurable cardinals, $\kappa _1$ ’s strong compactness is fully indestructible, and $\kappa _2$ ’s strong compactness is indestructible under $\mathrm {Add}$ for any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Woodin for strong compactness cardinals.Stamatis Dimopoulos - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):301-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Killing the $GCH$ everywhere with a single real.Sy-David Friedman & Mohammad Golshani - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (3):803-823.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Supercompactness and level by level equivalence are compatible with indestructibility for strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (3-4):155-163.
    It is known that if $\kappa < \lambda$ are such that κ is indestructibly supercompact and λ is 2λ supercompact, then level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness fails. We prove a theorem which points towards this result being best possible. Specifically, we show that relative to the existence of a supercompact cardinal, there is a model for level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness containing a supercompact cardinal κ in which κ’s strong compactness is indestructible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Diamond, square, and level by level equivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (3):387-395.
    We force and construct a model in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds, along with certain additional combinatorial properties. In particular, in this model, ♦ δ holds for every regular uncountable cardinal δ, and below the least supercompact cardinal κ, □ δ holds on a stationary subset of κ. There are no restrictions in our model on the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Indestructible strong compactness but not supercompactness.Arthur W. Apter, Moti Gitik & Grigor Sargsyan - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (9):1237-1242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Level by level inequivalence beyond measurability.Arthur W. Apter - 2011 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 50 (7-8):707-712.
    We construct models containing exactly one supercompact cardinal in which level by level inequivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds. In each model, above the supercompact cardinal, there are finitely many strongly compact cardinals, and the strongly compact and measurable cardinals precisely coincide.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Inner models with large cardinal features usually obtained by forcing.Arthur W. Apter, Victoria Gitman & Joel David Hamkins - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (3-4):257-283.
    We construct a variety of inner models exhibiting features usually obtained by forcing over universes with large cardinals. For example, if there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is an inner model with a Laver indestructible supercompact cardinal. If there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is an inner model with a supercompact cardinal κ for which 2κ = κ+, another for which 2κ = κ++ and another in which the least strongly compact cardinal is supercompact. If there is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Semistationary and stationary reflection.Hiroshi Sakai - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (1):181-192.
    We study the relationship between the semistationary reflection principle and stationary reflection principles. We show that for all regular cardinals Λ ≥ ω₂ the semistationary reflection principle in the space [Λ](1) implies that every stationary subset of $E_{\omega}^{\lambda}\coloneq \{\alpha \in \lambda \,|\,{\rm cf}(\alpha)=\omega \}$ reflects. We also show that for all cardinals Λ ≥ ω₃ the semistationary reflection principle in [Λ](1) does not imply the stationary reflection principle in [Λ](1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Strong Compactness and Stationary Sets.John Krueger - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):767 - 777.
    We construct a model in which there is a strongly compact cardinal κ such that the set $S(\kappa,\kappa ^{+})=\{a\in P_{\kappa}\kappa ^{-}\colon o,t(a)=(a\cap \kappa)^{+}\})$ is non-stationary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Closed and unbounded classes and the härtig quantifier model.Philip D. Welch - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (2):564-584.
    We show that assuming modest large cardinals, there is a definable class of ordinals, closed and unbounded beneath every uncountable cardinal, so that for any closed and unbounded subclasses $P, Q, {\langle L[P],\in,P \rangle }$ and ${\langle L[Q],\in,Q \rangle }$ possess the same reals, satisfy the Generalised Continuum Hypothesis, and moreover are elementarily equivalent. Examples of such P are Card, the class of uncountable cardinals, I the uniform indiscernibles, or for any n the class $C^{n}{=_{{\operatorname {df}}}}\{ \lambda \, | \, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The lottery preparation.Joel David Hamkins - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 101 (2-3):103-146.
    The lottery preparation, a new general kind of Laver preparation, works uniformly with supercompact cardinals, strongly compact cardinals, strong cardinals, measurable cardinals, or what have you. And like the Laver preparation, the lottery preparation makes these cardinals indestructible by various kinds of further forcing. A supercompact cardinal κ, for example, becomes fully indestructible by <κ-directed closed forcing; a strong cardinal κ becomes indestructible by κ-strategically closed forcing; and a strongly compact cardinal κ becomes indestructible by, among others, the forcing to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Level by level equivalence and strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2004 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 50 (1):51.
    We force and construct models in which there are non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals which aren't measurable limits of strongly compact cardinals and in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds non-trivially except at strongly compact cardinals. In these models, every measurable cardinal κ which isn't either strongly compact or a witness to a certain phenomenon first discovered by Menas is such that for every regular cardinal λ > κ, κ is λ strongly compact iff κ is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the indestructibility aspects of identity crisis.Grigor Sargsyan - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (6):493-513.
    We investigate the indestructibility properties of strongly compact cardinals in universes where strong compactness suffers from identity crisis. We construct an iterative poset that can be used to establish Kimchi–Magidor theorem from (in The independence between the concepts of compactness and supercompactness, circulated manuscript), i.e., that the first n strongly compact cardinals can be the first n measurable cardinals. As an application, we show that the first n strongly compact cardinals can be the first n measurable cardinals while the strong (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Radin forcing and its iterations.John Krueger - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (3-4):223-252.
    We provide an exposition of supercompact Radin forcing and present several methods for iterating Radin forcing.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Abstract logic and set theory. II. large cardinals.Jouko Väänänen - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):335-346.
    The following problem is studied: How large and how small can the Löwenheim and Hanf numbers of unbounded logics be in relation to the most common large cardinals? The main result is that the Löwenheim number of the logic with the Härtig-quantifier can be consistently put in between any two of the first weakly inaccessible, the first weakly Mahlo, the first weakly compact, the first Ramsey, the first measurable and the first supercompact cardinals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Exactly controlling the non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter & Joel David Hamkins - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (2):669-688.
    We summarize the known methods of producing a non-supercompact strongly compact cardinal and describe some new variants. Our Main Theorem shows how to apply these methods to many cardinals simultaneously and exactly control which cardinals are supercompact and which are only strongly compact in a forcing extension. Depending upon the method, the surviving non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals can be strong cardinals, have trivial Mitchell rank or even contain a club disjoint from the set of measurable cardinals. These results improve and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Some structural results concerning supercompact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1919-1927.
    We show how the forcing of [5] can be iterated so as to get a model containing supercompact cardinals in which every measurable cardinal δ is δ + supercompact. We then apply this iteration to prove three additional theorems concerning the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The least measurable can be strongly compact and indestructible.Arthur W. Apter & Moti Gitik - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (4):1404-1412.
    We show the consistency, relative to a supercompact cardinal, of the least measurable cardinal being both strongly compact and fully Laver indestructible. We also show the consistency, relative to a supercompact cardinal, of the least strongly compact cardinal being somewhat supercompact yet not completely supercompact and having both its strong compactness and degree of supercompactness fully Laver indestructible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A note on tall cardinals and level by level equivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (1-2):128-132.
    Starting from a model “κ is supercompact” + “No cardinal is supercompact up to a measurable cardinal”, we force and construct a model such that “κ is supercompact” + “No cardinal is supercompact up to a measurable cardinal” + “δ is measurable iff δ is tall” in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds. This extends and generalizes both [, Theorem 1] and the results of.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Patterns of compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 89 (2-3):101-115.
    We show relative to strong hypotheses that patterns of compact cardinals in the universe, where a compact cardinal is one which is either strongly compact or supercompact, can be virtually arbitrary. Specifically, we prove if V “ZFC + Ω is the least inaccessible limit of measurable limits of supercompact cardinals + ƒ : Ω → 2 is a function”, then there is a partial ordering P V so that for , There is a proper class of compact cardinals + If (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • A Characterization of Generalized Příkrý Sequences.Gunter Fuchs - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (8):935-971.
    A generalization of Příkrý's forcing is analyzed which adjoins to a model of ZFC a set of order type at most ω below each member of a discrete set of measurable cardinals. A characterization of generalized Příkrý generic sequences reminiscent of Mathias' criterion for Příkrý genericity is provided, together with a maximality theorem which states that a generalized Příkrý sequence almost contains every other one lying in the same extension.This forcing can be used to falsify the covering lemma for a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Nonsplitting subset of κ.Moti Gitik - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (4):881-894.
    Assuming the existence of a supercompact cardinal, we construct a model of ZFC + ). Answering a question of Uri Abraham [A], [A-S], we prove that adding a real to the world always makes P ℵ 1 - V stationary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Normal measures on a tall cardinal.Arthur W. Apter & James Cummings - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):178-204.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation