Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The consistency strength of projective absoluteness.Kai Hauser - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 74 (3):245-295.
    It is proved that in the absence of proper class inner models with Woodin cardinals, for each n ε {1,…,ω}, ∑3 + n1 absoluteness implies there are n strong cardinals in K (where this denotes a suitably defined global version of the core model for one Woodin cardinal as exposed by Steel. Combined with a forcing argument of Woodin, this establishes that the consistency strength of ∑3 + n1 absoluteness is exactly that of n strong cardinals so that in particular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The covering lemma up to a Woodin cardinal.W. J. Mitchell, E. Schimmerling & J. R. Steel - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 84 (2):219-255.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Inner models in the region of a Woodin limit of Woodin cardinals.Itay Neeman - 2002 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 116 (1-3):67-155.
    We extend the construction of Mitchell and Steel to produce iterable fine structure models which may contain Woodin limits of Woodin cardinals, and more. The precise level reached is that of a cardinal which is both a Woodin cardinal and a limit of cardinals strong past it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Strong Cardinals and Sets of Reals in Lω1.Ralf-Dieter Schindler - 1999 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 45 (3):361-369.
    We generalize results of [3] and [1] to hyperprojective sets of reals, viz. to more than finitely many strong cardinals being involved. We show, for example, that if every set of reals in Lω is weakly homogeneously Souslin, then there is an inner model with an inaccessible limit of strong cardinals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Equiconsistencies at subcompact cardinals.Itay Neeman & John Steel - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (1-2):207-238.
    We present equiconsistency results at the level of subcompact cardinals. Assuming SBHδ, a special case of the Strategic Branches Hypothesis, we prove that if δ is a Woodin cardinal and both □ and □δ fail, then δ is subcompact in a class inner model. If in addition □ fails, we prove that δ is Π12\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\Pi_1^2}$$\end{document} subcompact in a class inner model. These results are optimal, and lead to equiconsistencies. As a corollary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Weak Ultrafilter Axiom.W. Hugh Woodin - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (1-2):319-351.
    The main theorem is that the Ultrafilter Axiom of Woodin :115–37, 2011) must fail at all cardinals where the Axiom I0 holds, in all non-strategic extender models subject only to fairly general requirements on the non-strategic extender model.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Boolean-Valued Second-Order Logic.Daisuke Ikegami & Jouko Väänänen - 2015 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 56 (1):167-190.
    In so-called full second-order logic, the second-order variables range over all subsets and relations of the domain in question. In so-called Henkin second-order logic, every model is endowed with a set of subsets and relations which will serve as the range of the second-order variables. In our Boolean-valued second-order logic, the second-order variables range over all Boolean-valued subsets and relations on the domain. We show that under large cardinal assumptions Boolean-valued second-order logic is more robust than full second-order logic. Its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Comparison of fine structural mice via coarse iteration.F. Schlutzenberg & J. R. Steel - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (5-6):539-559.
    Let M\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathcal{M}}$$\end{document} be a fine structural mouse. Let D\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathbb{D}}$$\end{document} be a fully backgrounded L[E]\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${L[\mathbb{E}]}$$\end{document}-construction computed inside an iterable coarse premouse S. We describe a process comparing M\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathcal{M}}$$\end{document} with D\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathbb{D}}$$\end{document}, through forming iteration trees on M\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Π12 Wadge degrees.Greg Hjorth - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 77 (1):53-74.
    Suppose that any two Π12 sets are comparable in the sense of Wadge degrees. Then every real has a dagger. This argument proceeds by using the Dodd-Jensen core model theory to show that x ε ωω along with, say, “0† implies the existence of a Π12 norm of length u2. As a result of more recent work by John Steel, the same argument will extend to show that the Wadge comparability of all Π12 sets implies Π12 determinacy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Strong cardinals in the core model.Kai Hauser & Greg Hjorth - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 83 (2):165-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • How to win some simple iteration games.Alessandro Andretta & John Steel - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 83 (2):103-164.
    We introduce two new iteration games: the game , which is a strengthening of the weak iteration game, and the game , which is somewhat stronger than but weaker than the full iteration game of length ω1. For a countable M elementarily embeddable in some Vη, with two players I and II, we can show that II wins and that I does not win.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Counterexamples to the Unique and Cofinal Branches Hypotheses.Itay Neeman & John Steel - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (3):977 - 988.
    We produce counterexamples to the unique and cofinal branches hypotheses, assuming (slightly less than) the existence of a cardinal which is strong past a Woodin cardinal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Characterizing all models in infinite cardinalities.Lauri Keskinen - 2013 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 164 (3):230-250.
    Fix a cardinal κ. We can ask the question: what kind of a logic L is needed to characterize all models of cardinality κ up to isomorphism by their L-theories? In other words: for which logics L it is true that if any models A and B of cardinality κ satisfy the same L-theory then they are isomorphic?It is always possible to characterize models of cardinality κ by their Lκ+,κ+-theories, but we are interested in finding a “small” logic L, i.e., (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Inner models and large cardinals.Ronald Jensen - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (4):393-407.
    In this paper, we sketch the development of two important themes of modern set theory, both of which can be regarded as growing out of work of Kurt Gödel. We begin with a review of some basic concepts and conventions of set theory.§0. The ordinal numbers were Georg Cantor's deepest contribution to mathematics. After the natural numbers 0, 1, …, n, … comes the first infinite ordinal number ω, followed by ω + 1, ω + 2, …, ω + ω, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Combinatorial principles in the core model for one Woodin cardinal.Ernest Schimmerling - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 74 (2):153-201.
    We study the fine structure of the core model for one Woodin cardinal, building of the work of Mitchell and Steel on inner models of the form . We generalize to some combinatorial principles that were shown by Jensen to hold in L. We show that satisfies the statement: “□κ holds whenever κ the least measurable cardinal λ of order λ++”. We introduce a hierarchy of combinatorial principles □κ, λ for 1 λ κ such that □κ□κ, 1 □κ, λ □κ, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Mouse sets.Mitch Rudominer - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 87 (1):1-100.
    In this paper we explore a connection between descriptive set theory and inner model theory. From descriptive set theory, we will take a countable, definable set of reals, A. We will then show that , where is a canonical model from inner model theory. In technical terms, is a “mouse”. Consequently, we say that A is a mouse set. For a concrete example of the type of set A we are working with, let ODnω1 be the set of reals which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations