Switch to: References

Citations of:

Thought's Ego in Augustine and Descartes

Ithaca: Cornell University Press (1992)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The 'Meditational' Genre of Descartes' Meditations.Joshtrom Isaac Kureethadam - 1970 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 13 (1):51-68.
    In this paper, I reflect on Descartes' employment of the meditational genre in the weaving of the text of the Meditations. In the first part, the possible influences behind Descartes' choice of the meditational genre are examined. The second part of the paper attempts to spell out the significance of Descartes' use of the meditational form. The claim advanced here is that Descartes adopted this unique genre ultimately to further his radical philosophical project of a subject-centred theory of knowledge and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Descartes and Hume on I-thoughts.Luca Forgione - 2018 - Thémata: Revista de Filosofía 57:211-228.
    Self-consciousness can be understood as the ability to think I-thou-ghts which can be described as thoughts about oneself ‘as oneself’. Self-consciousness possesses two specific correlated features: the first regards the fact that it is grounded on a first-person perspective, whereas the second concerns the fact that it should be considered a consciousness of the self as subject rather than a consciousness of the self as object. The aim of this paper is to analyse a few considerations about Descartes and Hume’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Loving God in and through the self: Trinitarian love in St. Augustine.Matthew Drever - 2017 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 78 (1-2):7-22.
    ABSTRACTAnders Nygren argues that Augustine’s adherence to a Platonist notion of eros undermines both his own and a wider Christian account of agape. On Nygren’s reading, eros, which is self-fulfilling love that originates in the soul’s movement toward God, stands in contradistinction to agape, which is self-denying love that originates in God and condescends to us through the sacrifice of Christ. While it is true that Platonism plays an important role for Augustine, he comes to interpret love through a lens (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In dialogue with Augustine’s Soliloquia. Interpreting and recovering a theory of illumination.Anthony Dupont & Matthew W. Knotts - 2013 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 74 (5):432-465.
    The task of this article is a two-fold approach to Augustine’s theory of knowledge, often called that of ‘divine illumination’, with particular attention to one of its seminal sources, his Soliloquia. The first approach is historical- and text-critical; we consider the text of the Soliloquia, its meaning and significance, the questions to which Augustine was implicitly responding at the time, and especially how this work broaches themes which are revisited and further developed in Augustine’s later works. In the second part, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Successful is Naturalism?Georg Gasser (ed.) - 2007 - Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.
    The aim of the present volume is to draw the balance of naturalism's success so far.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Walter chatton.Rondo Keele & Jenny Pelletier - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Augustine’s Master Argument for the Incorporeality of the Mind.Tamer Nawar - 2022 - Philosophical Quarterly 72 (2):422-440.
    In De Trinitate 10, Augustine offers an argument that seemingly proceeds from certain premises about self-knowledge to the conclusion that the mind is incorporeal. Although the argument has sometimes been compared to later Cartesian arguments, it has received relatively little philosophical attention. In this paper, I offer a detailed analysis and original interpretation of Augustine's argument and argue that it is not vulnerable to some of the main objections which have been raised against it. I go on to argue that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Augustine on testimony.Peter King & Nathan Ballantyne - 2009 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 39 (2):pp. 195-214.
    Philosophical work on testimony has flourished in recent years. Testimony roughly involves a source affirming or stating something in an attempt to transfer information to one or more persons. It is often said that the topic of testimony has been neglected throughout most of the history of philosophy, aside from contributions by David Hume (1711–1776) and Thomas Reid (1710–1796).1 True as this may be, Hume and Reid aren’t the only ones who deserve a tip of the hat for recognizing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Ontology Down-to-Earth.L. R. Baker - 2015 - The Monist 98 (2):145-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Naturalism and the Idea of Nature.Lynne Rudder Baker - 2017 - Philosophy 92 (3):333-349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Self-knowledge in Aristotle.Frank A. Lewis - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):39-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Retrospective necessity and the first person.Yujian Zheng - 2021 - Philosophical Forum 52 (3):245-261.
    The Philosophical Forum, Volume 52, Issue 3, Page 245-261, Fall 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on the Individuality of Self.Juha Sihvola - 2008 - In Pauliina Remes & Juha Sihvola (eds.), Ancient philosophy of the self. London: Springer. pp. 125--137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations