Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Handbook of philosophy of management.Cristina Neesham & Steven Segal (eds.) - 2019
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Three laws of qualia: what neurology tells us about the biological functions of consciousness.Vilayanur S. Ramachandran & William Hirstein - 1997 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 (5-6):429-457.
    Neurological syndromes in which consciousness seems to malfunction, such as temporal lobe epilepsy, visual scotomas, Charles Bonnet syndrome, and synesthesia offer valuable clues about the normal functions of consciousness and ‘qualia’. An investigation into these syndromes reveals, we argue, that qualia are different from other brain states in that they possess three functional characteristics, which we state in the form of ‘three laws of qualia’. First, they are irrevocable: I cannot simply decide to start seeing the sunset as green, or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Uncertainty and objectivity in clinical decision making: a clinical case in emergency medicine.Eivind Engebretsen, Kristin Heggen, Sietse Wieringa & Trisha Greenhalgh - 2016 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 19 (4):595-603.
    The evidence-based practice and evidence-based medicine movements have promoted standardization through guideline development methodologies based on systematic reviews and meta-analyses of best available research. EBM has challenged clinicians to question their reliance on practical reasoning and clinical judgement. In this paper, we argue that the protagonists of EBM position their mission as reducing uncertainty through the use of standardized methods for knowledge evaluation and use. With this drive towards uniformity, standardization and control comes a suspicion towards intuition, creativity and uncertainty (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What can Recent Replication Failures tell us about the Theoretical Commitments of Psychology?Stan Klein - 2014 - Theory and Psychology 24:326-338.
    I suggest that the recent, highly visible, and often heated debate over failures to replicate the results in the social sciences reveals more than the need for greater attention to the pragmatics and value of empirical falsification. It also is a symptom of a serious issue -- the underdeveloped state of theory in many areas of psychology. While I focus on the phenomenon of “social priming” -- since it figures centrally in current debate -- it is not the only area (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • An ecological theory of learning: Good goal, poor strategy.Sara J. Shettleworth - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):160-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Principles of learning and the ecological style of inquiry.Thomas R. Alley & Robert E. Shaw - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):139-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Self-experimentation as a source of new ideas: Ten examples about sleep, mood, health, and weight.Seth Roberts - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (2):227-262.
    Little is known about how to generate plausible new scientific ideas. So it is noteworthy that 12 years of self-experimentation led to the discovery of several surprising cause-effect relationships and suggested a new theory of weight control, an unusually high rate of new ideas. The cause-effect relationships were: (1) Seeing faces in the morning on television decreased mood in the evening (>10 hrs later) and improved mood the next day (>24 hrs later), yet had no detectable effect before that (0–10 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Resurrecting logical probability.James Franklin - 2001 - Erkenntnis 55 (2):277-305.
    The logical interpretation of probability, or "objective Bayesianism'' – the theory that (some) probabilities are strictly logical degrees of partial implication – is defended. The main argument against it is that it requires the assignment of prior probabilities, and that any attempt to determine them by symmetry via a "principle of insufficient reason" inevitably leads to paradox. Three replies are advanced: that priors are imprecise or of little weight, so that disagreement about them does not matter, within limits; that it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Universality, Truth, and Popperian Simplicity.Iñaki Xavier Larrauri Pertierra - manuscript
    Popper's account of science is an endeavour in establishing the relationship between universality and truth. The idea is that the more an empirical law is universal, by precluding certain realities from obtaining in an evidentially falsifiable way, the more the law is supported by instances of its predictions being evidentially verified. The logical structure of this dynamic is captured by Popper's notion of 'corroboration'. However, this notion is suspect, for, depending on one's interpretation of evidential givenness, the relation between a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An ecological approach to a theory of learning.Timothy D. Johnston - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):162-173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The relevance of phylogenetics to the study of behavioral diversity.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):144-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the transdisciplinary nature of the epistemology of discovery.Morris L. Shames - 1991 - Zygon 26 (3):343-357.
    Despite the by now historical tendency to demarcate scientific epistemology sharply from virtually all others, especially theological “epistemology,” it has recently been recognized that both enterprises share a great deal in common, at least as far as the epistemology of discovery is implicated. Such a claim is founded upon a psychological analysis of figuration, where, it is argued, metaphor plays a crucial role in the mediation of discovery, in the domains of science and religion alike. Thus, although the conventionally conceived (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The ecology of learning: The right answer to the wrong question.Barry Schwartz - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):159-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptive modification of behavior: Processing information from the environment.Wolfgang M. Schleidt - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):158-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Biological approaches to the study of learning: Does Johnston provide a new alternative?Robert A. Hinde - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):146-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Galileo and Copernican Astronomy: A Scientific World View Defined.Clive Morphet - 1986 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 6 (5):429-502.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “The Scientific Method” as Myth and Ideal.Brian A. Woodcock - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (10):2069-2093.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A fourth approach to the study of learning: Are “processes” really necessary?John C. Malone - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):151-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • On the what and how of learning.R. C. Gonzalez & Matthew Yarczower - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):145-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On accounting for one kind of difference in terms of another kind of difference.John L. Gedye - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (3):353-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teaching philosophy of science to scientists: why, what and how.Till Grüne-Yanoff - 2014 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 4 (1):115-134.
    This paper provides arguments to philosophers, scientists, administrators and students for why science students should be instructed in a mandatory, custom-designed, interdisciplinary course in the philosophy of science. The argument begins by diagnosing that most science students are taught only conventional methodology: a fixed set of methods whose justification is rarely addressed. It proceeds by identifying seven benefits that scientists incur from going beyond these conventions and from acquiring abilities to analyse and evaluate justifications of scientific methods. It concludes that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Karl Popper and the 'the problem of induction': A fresh look at the logic of testing scientific theories. [REVIEW]I. Grattan-Guinness - 2004 - Erkenntnis 60 (1):107-120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • T. rex, the crater of doom, and the nature of scientific discovery.Anton E. Lawson - 2004 - Science & Education 13 (3):155-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Learning theory in its niche.Howard Rachlin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):155-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The nature of learning explanations.John Garcia - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):143-144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • General process theory, ecology, and animal-human continuity: A cognitive perspective.Janet L. Lachman & Roy Lachman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):149-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Ecology and learning.Alan C. Kamil - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Contrasting approaches to a theory of learning.Timothy D. Johnston - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):125-139.
    The general process view of learning, which guided research into learning for the first half of this century, has come under attack in recent years from several quarters. One form of criticism has come from proponents of the so-called biological boundaries approach to learning. These theorists have presented a variety of data showing that supposedly general laws of learning may in fact be limited in their applicability to different species and learning tasks, and they argue that the limitations are drawn (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   287 citations  
  • Informal Logic and Informal Consequence.Danilo Suster - 2011 - In Majda Trobok, Nenad Miščević & Berislav Žarnić (eds.), Between Logic and Reality: Modeling Inference, Action and Understanding. Dordrecht and New York: Springer. pp. 101--120.
    What is informal logic, is it ``logic" at all? Main contemporary approaches are briefly presented and critically commented. If the notion of consequence is at the heart of logic, does it make sense to speak about ``informal" consequence? A valid inference is truth preserving, if the premises are true, so is the conclusion. According to Prawitz two further conditions must also be satisfied in the case of classical logical consequence: (i) it is because of the logical form of the sentences (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Clinical intuition versus statistics: Different modes of tacit knowledge in clinical epidemiology and evidence-based medicine.Hillel D. Braude - 2009 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 30 (3):181-198.
    Despite its phenomenal success since its inception in the early nineteen-nineties, the evidence-based medicine movement has not succeeded in shaking off an epistemological critique derived from the experiential or tacit dimensions of clinical reasoning about particular individuals. This critique claims that the evidence-based medicine model does not take account of tacit knowing as developed by the philosopher Michael Polanyi. However, the epistemology of evidence-based medicine is premised on the elimination of the tacit dimension from clinical judgment. This is demonstrated through (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • A funny thing happened on the way to comparative psychology.James W. Kalat - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):147-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Useful concepts for predictive ecology.Robert Henry Peters - 1980 - Synthese 43 (2):257 - 269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Can scientists be objective?Malcolm Williams - 2006 - Social Epistemology 20 (2):163 – 180.
    Objectivity and value freedom have often been conflated in the philosophical and sociological literature. While value freedom construed as an absence of social and moral values in scientific work has been discredited, defenders of value freedom bracket off methodological values or practices from social and moral ones. In this paper I will first show how values exist along a continuum and argue that science is and should be value based. One of these values is necessarily objectivity for science to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Wrecked Vessel: The Effects of Gnosticism, Nominalism and the Protestant Reformation in the Semiotic Scaffolding of Modern Scientific Consciousness.Wendy Wheeler - 2015 - Biosemiotics 8 (2):305-324.
    This essay discusses the semiotic scaffolding of modern science, the roots of which lie in the Protestant Reformation and the latter’s repudiation of the “semiotics of nature” upon which medieval theology depended. Taking the fourteenth-century battles between realism and nominalism as the semiotic scaffolding of the Reformation which was subsequently built on nominalist principles, and the Reformation as what made possible the development of early modern science, this essay argues that nominalism, Protestantism, and early modern science were all infected by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge-based systems and issues of integration: A commercial perspective. [REVIEW]Karl M. Wiig - 1988 - AI and Society 2 (3):209-233.
    Commercial applications of knowledge-based systems are changing from an embryonic to a growth business. Knowledge is classified by levels and types to differentiate various knowledge-based systems. Applications are categorized by size, generic types, and degree of intelligence to establish a framework for discussion of progress and implications. A few significant commercial applications are identified and perspectives and implications of these and other systems are discussed. Perspectives relate to development paths, delivery modes, types of integration, and resource requirements. Discussion includes organizational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Linking the biological functions and the mechanisms of learning: Uses and abuses.Patrick Bateson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):142-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Known general principles of learning cannot be ignored.Sam Revusky - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):156-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An ecological approach toward a unified theory of learning.William R. Charlesworth - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):142-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A theory of learning - not even déjà vu.George W. Barlow & Stephen E. Glickman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):141-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Discussing learning: The quandary of substance.Jack P. Hailman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):146-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The philosophy of everyday knowledge.Stefan Björklund - 1993 - Theoria 59 (1-3):28-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is an ecological approach radical enough?H. C. Plotkin & F. J. Odling-Smee - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):154-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Explaining diversity and searching for general processes: Isn't there a middle ground?Paul Rozin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):157-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Missing variables in studies of animal learning.Wally Welker - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):161-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A functional view of learning.Lewis Petrinovich - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):153-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning theory: Behavioral artifacts or general principles?John A. Nevin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Species differences and principles of learning: Informed generality.A. W. Logue - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):150-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Organized skepticism, naïve methodism, and other -isms.Jay A. Labinger - 2006 - Foundations of Chemistry 8 (2):97-110.
    The Science Wars have pitted defenders of science against those accused of attacking it with the weapons of constructivism and relativism. I argue that this defensive stance is in large part a consequence of two other -isms, organized skepticism and naïve methodism, that play a significant, if mostly unconscious, role in how scientists tend to think about science, and suggest that increased awareness of these -isms may help dissipate the perceptions of hostility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ecological approach to learning.John Kruse & Edward Reed - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):148-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is unsaying polite?Berislav Žarnić - 2011 - In Majda Trobok, Nenad Miščević & Berislav Žarnić (eds.), Between Logic and Reality: Modeling Inference, Action and Understanding. Dordrecht and New York: Springer. pp. 201--224.
    This paper is divided in five sections. Section 11.1 sketches the history of the distinction between speech act with negative content and negated speech act, and gives a general dynamic interpretation for negated speech act. “Downdate semantics” for AGM contraction is introduced in Section 11.2. Relying on semantically interpreted contraction, Section 11.3 develops the dynamic semantics for constative and directive speech acts, and their external negations. The expressive completeness for the formal variants of natural language utterances, none of which is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation