Switch to: References

Citations of:

A Cock for Asclepius

Classical Quarterly 43 (1):96-111 (1993)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. In and Out of Character: Socratic Mimēsis.Mateo Duque - 2020 - Dissertation, Cuny Graduate Center
    In the "Republic," Plato has Socrates attack poetry’s use of mimēsis, often translated as ‘imitation’ or ‘representation.’ Various scholars (e.g. Blondell 2002; Frank 2018; Halliwell 2009; K. Morgan 2004) have noticed the tension between Socrates’ theory critical of mimēsis and Plato’s literary practice of speaking through various characters in his dialogues. However, none of these scholars have addressed that it is not only Plato the writer who uses mimēsis but also his own character, Socrates. At crucial moments in several dialogues, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Socrates’ Tomb in Antisthenes’ Kyrsas and its Relationship with Plato’s Phaedo.Menahem Luz - 2022 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 1176 (2):163-177.
    Socrates’ burial is dismissed as philosophically irrelevant in Phaedo 115c-e although it had previously been discussed by Plato’s older contemporaries. In Antisthenes’ Kyrsas dialogue describes a visit to Socrates’ tomb by a lover of Socrates who receives protreptic advice in a dream sequence while sleeping over Socrates’ grave. The dialogue is a metaphysical explanation of how Socrates’ spiritual message was continued after death. Plato underplays this metaphorical imagery by lampooning Antisthenes philosophy and his work (Phd. 81b-82e) and subsequently precludes him (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Сова і півень як символи філософування.Vadym Menzhulin - 2021 - Наукові Записки Наукма. Філософія Та Релігієзнавство 6:3-13.
    Based on the assumption that “philosophy, as the thought of the world, does not appear until reality has completed its formative process,” Georg Hegel compared it with the ancient symbol of wisdom: the owl of Minerva. This analogy is well known and has not caused many debates. Much less known is the comparison of philosophy with another bird, the rooster, proposed by Henry Thoreau. The main purpose of the article is to show that the latter analogy also has a deep (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on the Nature and Politics of Medicine.Samuel H. Baker - 2021 - Apeiron 54 (4):441-449.
    According to Aristotle, the medical art aims at health, which is a virtue of the body, and does so in an unlimited way. Consequently, medicine does not determine the extent to which health should be pursued, and “mental health” falls under medicine only via pros hen predication. Because medicine is inherently oriented to its end, it produces health in accordance with its nature and disease contrary to its nature—even when disease is good for the patient. Aristotle’s politician understands that this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • “Le debemos un gallo a Asclepio”. El canto político del cisne socrático.Esteban Bieda - 2020 - Daimon: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 80:125-138.
    Mucho se ha escrito acerca del significado de las últimas palabras de Sócrates en el Fedón: “Critón, debemos un gallo a Asclepio. Pues bien, ¡páguenselo! Y no se descuiden…”. En el presente trabajo nos proponemos retomar el enigma de la deuda con Asclepio a fin de rescatar cierto matiz político presente en él. Para ello, tras reseñar brevemente las principales interpretaciones que se han dado en el último siglo, nos detendremos en la concepción socrática del nacimiento y de la vida (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O exemplo de Sócrates.Olímpio Pimenta - 2019 - Discurso 49 (2).
    Um tópico de interesse permanente em relação a Sócrates é a determinação dos melhores termos para o entendimento da articulação entre sua vida e sua prática filosófica. O presente artigo busca ensaiar uma discussão introdutória desta questão. Nesse sentido, parte-se de uma restituição, em largos traços, do testemunho das três principais fontes diretas, avança-se daí até algumas formulações atuais centradas no tema do exame para, por último, considerar a matéria à luz da morte de Sócrates e dos desdobramentos que seu (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Annotated Bibliography on Plato's Phaedo.David Ebrey - 2017 - Oxford Bibliographies.
    8000 Word annotated bibliography on the Phaedo, with roughly 70 entries. Note that the subscription version is a bit easier to navigate. The hyperlinks work in this pdf, but you can not as easily jump to the different sections.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Duša poetická a duša filozofická. K Platónovmu dialógu Faidón.Jaroslav Cepko - 2014 - Pro-Fil 14 (2):19.
    Článok je pokusom o interpretáciu Platónovho dialógu Faidón vo svetle prvých Sókratových slov, ktoré v ňom zaznievajú. Sókratova krátka úvaha o vzťahu príjemného a nepríjemného je vzápätí vsadená do kontextu konfrontácie filozofického a básnického typu explanácie. Zaujímavé je, že Sókratov komentár k snu, ktorý ho kedysi vyzval k praktizovaniu múzického umenia, neprezentuje oba prístupy ako navzájom sa vylučujúce, ale skôr ako komplementárne. V tejto perspektíve je možné čítať Faidóna ako náčrt „vysokej“ filozofie oddelených ideí, a zároveň ako výzvu o jej (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The Manumission of Socrates.Deborah Kamen - 2013 - Classical Antiquity 32 (1):78-100.
    This article argues we can better interpret key aspects of Plato's Phaedo, including Socrates' cryptic final words, if we read the dialogue against the background of Greek manumission. I first discuss modes of manumission in ancient Greece, showing that the frequent participation of healing gods (Apollo, Asklepios, and Sarapis) reveals a conception of manumission as “healing.” I next examine Plato's use of manumission and slavery as metaphors, arguing that Plato uses the language of slavery in two main ways: like real (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)Cleombrotus of Ambracia: interpretations of a suicide from Callimachus to Agathias.G. D. Williams - 1995 - Classical Quarterly 45 (01):154-.
    At Phaedo 59b Echecrates asks Phaedo who was present on the day when Socrates drank the hemlock in prison. Various Athenians are named , then various foreigners , but when Echecrates subsequently asks if two other foreigners, Aristippus and Cleombrotus, were present, Phaedo replies that they were said to be in Aegina . After this fleeting reference to Cleombrotus, Plato does not mention him again in the Phaedo or any other dialogue; and yet in later antiquity a certain Cleombrotus of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Socrates’ Burial in Plato and Euclides.Menahem Luz - 2022 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 16 (1):1-14.
    In Phaedo 115c-e Socrates scornfully rebukes Crito for enquiring how Socrates should be buried for Crito had not been persuaded by the previous arguments that burying Socrates’ body is not equal to burying Socrates. A parallel account is found in Aelian and Diogenes Laertius where Apollodorus is rebuked for attempting to persuade Socrates that he should be bothered how his remains would be clothed when laid out. Several scholars have suggested this should not be considered a copy of Plato but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)The Manumission of Socrates.Alex Dressler, Miguel Herrero De Jäuregui, Deborah Kamen, Leslie Kurke, Michael Mordine & Craig A. Williams - 2013 - Classical Antiquity 32 (1):78-100.
    This article argues we can better interpret key aspects of Plato's Phaedo, including Socrates' cryptic final words, if we read the dialogue against the background of Greek manumission. I first discuss modes of manumission in ancient Greece, showing that the frequent participation of healing gods (Apollo, Asklepios, and Sarapis) reveals a conception of manumission as “healing.” I next examine Plato's use of manumission and slavery as metaphors, arguing that Plato uses the language of slavery in two main ways: like real (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Socrates' last words: another look at an ancient riddle.J. Crooks - 1998 - Classical Quarterly 48 (01):117-.
    Socrates' last words are a microcosm of the riddle his character poses to the philosophical reader. Are they sincere or ironic? Do they represent an afterthought prompted by a belated sense of familial responsibility or a death–bed epiphany? Are we to determine their reference in relation to the surface logic of the Phaedo or take them as the sign of a concealed discursive depth? In what follows, I will argue that the answer to these questions depends upon acknowledgement and clarification (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Filosofia como forma de vida: variações sobre o tema a partir de Nietzsche e Sócrates.Olímpio Pimenta - 2020 - Cadernos Nietzsche 41 (2):63-83.
    Resumo Busca-se, a partir do exame dos compromissos existenciais implicados pela prática filosófica dos dois pensadores, estipular uma série de convergências entre ambos. Porque tal associação parece improvável, se se tem em vista o combate dado por Nietzsche a formulações substantivas do repertório filosófico tradicional talvez autorizadas por Sócrates, importará oferecer ao final um balanço da reflexão também quanto a isso.We aim, starting from the examination of the existencial commitments implied by both thinkers’ philosophical practice, to define a series of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Satyrica and the Gospels in the Second Century.Robyn Faith Walsh - 2020 - Classical Quarterly 70 (1):356-367.
    TheSatyricahas long been associated with a Neronian courtier named Petronius, mentioned by Tacitus in hisAnnals. As such, the text is usually dated to the mid first centuryc.e.This view is so established that certain scholars have suggested it is ‘little short of perverse not to accept the general consensus and read theSatyricaas a Neronian text of the mid-60sad’. In recent years, however, there has been a groundswell of support for re-evaluating this long-held position. Laird, after comparing the ‘form and content’ of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark