Switch to: References

Citations of:

Wittgensteinian Fideism

Philosophy 42 (161):191-209 (1967)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Eradicating Theocracy Philosophically.Pouya Lotfi Yazdi - manuscript
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bibliography.[author unknown] - 2007 - In Guy Kahane, Edward Kanterian & Oskari Kuusela (eds.), Wittgenstein and His Interpreters. Blackwell. pp. 320–344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Faith and Hinge Epistemology in Calvin’s Institutes.Nicholas Smith - forthcoming - Philosophia Reformata:1-26.
    In mainstream analytic epistemology, Reformed theology has made its presence prominently felt in Reformed epistemology, the view of religious belief according to which religious beliefs can be properly basic and warranted when formed by the proper functioning of the sensus divinitatis, an inborn capacity or faculty for belief in God that can be prompted to generate certain religious beliefs when presented with things (e.g., certain majestic aspects of creation). A major competitor to Reformed epistemology is Wittgensteinian quasi-fideism, a position drawn (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and the Cognitive Science of Religion: Interpreting Human Nature and the Mind.Robert Vinten (ed.) - 2023 - London: Bloomsbury Academic.
    Advancing our understanding of one of the most influential 20th-century philosophers, Robert Vinten brings together an international line up of scholars to consider the relevance of Ludwig Wittgenstein's ideas to the cognitive science of religion. Wittgenstein's claims ranged from the rejection of the idea that psychology is a 'young science' in comparison to physics to challenges to scientistic and intellectualist accounts of religion in the work of past anthropologists. Chapters explore whether these remarks about psychology and religion undermine the frameworks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • De la certitude religieuse : Wittgenstein sur la corde raide.Elise Marrou - 2011 - ThéoRèmes 1 (1).
    Le penseur religieux honnête est comme un funambule. Il progresse, semble-t-il, presque comme s'il marchait dans l'air. Son terrain est le plus mince qui se puisse imaginer. Et pourtant, il est réellement possible d'y marcher [Wittgenstein 1984] La difficulté immédiate et massive qui assaille le lecteur des notes que Wittgenstein a consacrées à la croyance religieuse est qu'elles offrent une toute autre appréhension de la certitude que celle à laquelle il nous avait accoutumé. Il s'y dessine...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hadot's later Wittgenstein: A critique.Michael Hymers - 2024 - Philosophical Investigations 47 (2):178-203.
    Pierre Hadot is best known as a historian of ancient philosophy and for advocating the relevance of ancient thinking for contemporary lives. What is less well known is that he was one of the first French philosophers to take a serious interest in the work of Wittgenstein, publishing between 1959 and 1962 two essays on the Tractatus and two on the Philosophical Investigations, since republished as Wittgenstein et les limites de langage (Paris: J. Vrin, 2010). Only two of these essays (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The rhetoric of grammar: Understanding Wittgenstein's method.William E. Barnett - 1990 - Metaphilosophy 21 (1-2):43-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Significance of Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Religious Belief.Jan Wawrzyniak - 2021 - Philosophia 49 (4):1767-1804.
    This article aims to show that Wittgenstein’s remarks on religious belief and religious statements can be understood in modest philosophical terms, consistent with the thought that they are neither intended as serving to justify or undermine religious beliefs, nor as the expression of any theorizing about the nature of religious belief or the meaning of religious language. Instead, their philosophical significance is held to consist in their functioning to remind us of what we already know about the latter: such things (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The expression of wonderment.Sophia Vasalou - 2007 - Philosophical Investigations 30 (2):138–155.
    In this paper, I consider certain remarks raised by Wittgenstein in his Lecture on Ethics in connection with the effability of absolute value. My focus is on the expressions we use to talk about the experience of wonderment at the existence of the world, which he dismisses as nonsensical owing to the way they deviate from the conditions of ordinary usage (specifically, to wonder at something, one must be able to imagine its contrary). I suggest that the concept of imagination (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Acknowledging a hidden God: A theological critique of Stanley Cavell on scepticism.Judith E. Tonning - 2007 - Heythrop Journal 48 (3):384–405.
    In his early work, the philosopher Stanley Cavell offers a sustained engagement with the threat of epistemological scepticism, shaped by the intuition that although (as the late Wittgenstein shows) ordinary language use is the practice within which alone meaning is possible (and which can thus not be further analysed or rationalised), it is also a basic human inclination to wish to escape the limitations of the ‘ordinary’. This, for Cavell, is the root of scepticism. Scepticism, on this view, thus appears (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • After Religion? Reflections on Nielsen's Wittgenstein.Béla Szabados - 2004 - Dialogue 43 (4):747-770.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Registers of the religious: The Terence H. McLaughlin lecture 2010.Paul Standish - 2012 - Ethics and Education 7 (2):185-197.
    Alasdair MacIntyre's landmark book After Virtue, first published in 1981, begins with sobering words, the resonance of which has, in the three decades since then, been felt by many. We live in a wo...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Religion and the contextualization of criteria.John J. Shepherd - 1976 - Sophia 15 (1):1-10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Religious language.Michael Scott - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (6):505-515.
    This study reviews some of the principal themes in contemporary work on religious language. Unlike other recent surveys, the most pressing issues about religious language are addressed from the perspective of the philosophy of language; different positions taken on these issues by philosophers of religion and theologians are considered. Topics that are covered include: the subject matter of religious discourse, reductionism and subjectivism, expressivism, the nature of religious metaphor, religious fictionalism and truth in religious discourse. The study also looks at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Religious Language. [REVIEW]Michael Scott - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (6):505-515.
    This study reviews some of the principal themes in contemporary work on religious language. Unlike other recent surveys, the most pressing issues about religious language are addressed from the perspective of the philosophy of language; different positions taken on these issues by philosophers of religion and theologians are considered. Topics that are covered include: the subject matter of religious discourse, reductionism and subjectivism, expressivism, the nature of religious metaphor, religious fictionalism and truth in religious discourse. The study also looks at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Quasi-fideism and epistemic relativism.Duncan Pritchard - forthcoming - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy.
    Quasi-fideism accounts for the rationality of religious belief by embracing the idea that a subject’s most fundamental religious commitments are essentially arational. It departs from standard forms of fideism, however, by contending that this feature of religious commitment does not set it apart from belief in general. Indeed, the quasi-fideist maintains, in keeping with the Wittgensteinian hinge epistemology that underlies the view, that it is in the nature of belief in general (i.e. religious or otherwise) that it presupposes essentially arational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Quasi-Fideism and Religious Conviction.Duncan Pritchard - 2018 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (3):51-66.
    It is argued that standard accounts of the epistemology of religious commitmentfail to be properly sensitive to certain important features of the nature of religious conviction. Once one takes these features of religious conviction seriously, then it becomes clear that we are not to conceive of the epistemology of religious conviction along completely rational lines.But the moral to extract from this is not fideism, or even a more moderate proposal that casts the epistemic standing of basic religious beliefs along nonrational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Quasi-Fideism and Sceptical Fideism.Duncan Pritchard - 2021 - Manuscrito 44 (4):3-30.
    My interest is in the relationship between the contemporary account of the epistemology of religious belief, known as quasi-fideism, and the sceptical fideism that has been so important, historically, in motivating fideistic ideas. I argue that we can profitably construe quasi-fideism along sceptical fideist lines, in that it is a proposal that is naturally understood as both arising within the context of a sceptical investigation and as exhibiting core features that it shares with Pyrrhonian scepticism. Moreover, I suggest that sceptical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Faith and Reason.Duncan Pritchard - 2017 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 81:101-118.
    A novel account of the rationality of religious belief is offered, called quasi-fideism. According to this proposal, we are neither to think of religious belief as completely immune to rational evaluation nor are we to deny that it involves fundamental commitments which are arational. Moreover, a parity argument is presented to the effect that religious belief is no different from ordinary rational belief in presupposing such fundamental arational commitments. This proposal is shown to be rooted in Wittgenstein's remarks on hinge (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Analysis and theology.William L. Power - 1978 - Sophia 17 (2):16-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein, Religious “Passion,” and Fundamentalism.Bob Plant - 2013 - Journal of Religious Ethics 41 (2):280-309.
    Notwithstanding his own spiritual inadequacies, Wittgenstein has a profound respect for those capable of living a genuinely religious life; namely, those whose “passionate,” “loving” faith demands unconditional existential commitment. In contrast, he disapproves of those who see religious belief as hypothetical, reasonable, or dependent on empirical evidence. Drawing primarily on Culture and Value, “Lectures on Religious Belief,” and On Certainty, in this essay I defend two claims: (1) that there is an unresolved tension between Wittgenstein's later descriptive-therapeutic approach and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Religion, Relativism, and Wittgenstein’s Naturalism.Bob Plant - 2011 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19 (2):177-209.
    Wittgenstein’s remarks on religious and magical practices are often thought to harbour troubling fideistic and relativistic views. Unsurprisingly, commentators are generally resistant to the idea that religious belief constitutes a ‘language‐game’ governed by its own peculiar ‘rules’, and is thereby insulated from the critical assessment of non‐participants. Indeed, on this fideist‐relativist reading, it is unclear how mutual understanding between believers and non‐believers (even between different sorts of believers) would be possible. In this paper I do three things: (i) show why (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Remarks on Béla Szabados's “After Religion? Reflections on Nielsen's Wittgenstein”.Kai Nielsen - 2004 - Dialogue 43 (4):771-796.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Islamic Wittgensteinian Fideism?Edward Ryan Moad - 2022 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 18 (2):(SI4)5-28.
    This paper examines recent deployments of Wittgenstein’s thought, by Mustafa (2018) and Asad (2020), in defense of the Islamic “traditionalism” of Ibn Taymiyyah and the Hanbali school. I will briefly summarize the key features of Wittgenstein’s thought crucial to this, and then examine their ramifications. I argue that Wittgenstein’s position actually undermines any claim to interpretive authority, whether of the “rationalist” or salafi “traditionalist” sort. Secondly, the approach to religious language most commonly associated with Wittgenstein—so-called “Wittgensteinian Fideism” may pose bigger (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Was wittgenstein a fideist? two views.Ken McGovern & Béla Szabados - 2002 - Sophia 41 (2):41-54.
    Kai Nielsen and Felicity McCutcheon have each in their own way taken issue with the received view that Wittgenstein’s remarks on religious language are to be construed as a form of “fideism”. They each provide sharply divergent views on Wittgenstein’s remarks on the meaning of religious language and, indeed, the importance of religion itself. These differences, however, serve to bring into relief both Wittgenstein’s recognition of the genuinely descriptive nature of ordinary religious discourse and his underlying political sensitivity. The paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • God, Scepticism and Modernity Kai Nielsen Collection Philosophica Ottawa: University of Ottawa Press, 1989, iii + 252 pp. [REVIEW]John King-Farlow - 1995 - Dialogue 34 (1):196-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rationality and problem- solving.John Kekes - 1977 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 7 (4):351-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Rethinking fideism through the lens of Wittgenstein’s engineering outlook.Brad J. Kallenberg - 2012 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 71 (1):55-73.
    Careful readers of Wittgenstein tend to overlook the significance his engineering education had for his philosophy; this despite Georg von Wright’s stern admonition that “the two most important facts to remember about Wittgenstein were, firstly, that he was Viennese, and, secondly, that he was an engineer.” Such oversight is particularly tempting for those of us who come to philosophy late, having first been schooled in math and science, because our education tricks us into thinking we understand engineering by extension. But (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Recent trends and future prospects in epistemology.John Kekes - 1977 - Metaphilosophy 8 (2-3):87-107.
    Three basic problems in contemporary epistemology are discussed. The first is the conflict between foundationalists and fallibilists. The second is the problem of scepticism. The third is the question of what sort of considerations are relevant to justification. The recent literature is surveyed and some original contributions are offered.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What if there were a religious "form of life"?James R. Hamilton - 1979 - Philosophical Investigations 2 (3):1-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and the genteel tradition.Reza Hosseini - 2019 - South African Journal of Philosophy 38 (3):287-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The modern invention of “science‐and‐religion”: What follows?Peter Harrison - 2016 - Zygon 51 (3):742-757.
    I am grateful to the four reviewers of The Territories of Science and Religion for their careful and insightful readings of the book, and their kind words about it. They all got the central arguments pretty much right, and thus any critical comments are not the result of fundamental misunderstandings. While there are some common themes in the assessments, each reviewer, happily, has offered a distinct perspective on the book. For this reason I will deal with their comments in turn, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Games, Families, the Public, and Religion.F. Gerald Downing - 1972 - Philosophy 47 (179):38 - 54.
    Wittgenstein's illustrative comparison of linguistic activities with games, his defence of a single term for items having no more than a ‘family resemblance’ and not even one common distinguishing feature, and his objections to any proposal seeming to imply an unshareably private language appear to have been accepted as interesting and important if not always as persuasive in English language philosophy. But these themes, and others introduced along with them are most often taken as separate items, belonging to distinct compartments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein on Understanding Religious Beliefs: Some Remarks against Incommensurability and Scepticism.Yuliya Fadeeva - 2020 - Wittgenstein-Studien 11 (1):53-78.
    Wittgenstein’s writings on religious and magical beliefs, especially the “Lectures on Religious Belief” and “Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough” are taken to imply semantic incommensurability and inaccessibility by the Wittgensteinian Fideism and, in part, the expressivist interpretation. According to these interpretations, religious and non-religious discourses are self-contained, closed, and not intertranslatable. Wittgenstein is taken to deny mutual understanding between believers and non-believers with respect to religious and magical discourse. I argue against such interpretations and support readings by Kusch, Schroeder, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On an unnoticed key to reality.A. A. Derksen - 1978 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 8 (3):209-225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The truth of religious narratives.Gary L. Comstock - 1993 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 34 (3):131 - 150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The epistemological foundations of practical reason.Mark Colby - 1999 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 42 (1):25 – 47.
    One consequence of the later Wittgenstein's influential critique of epistemological foundationalism has been to convince many contemporary philosophers that the ideal of universal and necessary cognitive grounds for moral or political norms is illusory. Recent neo-Wittgensteinian accounts of practical reason attempt to formulate a conception of a post-foundational politics in which a political ethos can be legitimate, rational or just even if its informing practices and cognitive standards lack foundational justification. Against these appropriations of Wittgenstein, I argue that his account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lived religion: rethinking human nature in a neoliberal age.Beverley Clack - 2018 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 79 (4):355-369.
    This article considers the relationship between philosophy of religion and an approach to the study of religion, which prioritises the experience of lived religion. Considering how individuals and communities live out their faith challenges some of the assumptions of analytic philosophers of religion regarding the position the philosopher should adopt when approaching the investigation of religion. If philosophy is understood principally as a means for analysing belief, it will have little space for an engagement with what it feels like to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Religious Hinges: Some Historical Precursors.Anna Boncompagni - 2022 - Topoi 41 (5):955-965.
    Recently, hinge epistemologists have applied Wittgenstein’s metaphor of hinges to religious belief. The most prominent proposal in this context is Pritchard’s “quasi-fideism”. This paper examines some historical precursors of the notion of religious hinges, with the aim of shedding more light on it. After outlining the framework of hinge epistemology and its application to religious belief, I briefly examine the views of Thomas Reid and John Henry Newman as acknowledged forerunners of this framework (or cognate views). Next, I turn to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The philosophy of religion: A programmatic overview.John Bishop - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 1 (5):506–534.
    It is argued that philosophy of religion should focus not only on the epistemic justifiability of holding religious beliefs but also on the moral justifiability of commitment to their truth in practical reasoning. If the truth of classical theism may turn out to be evidentially ambiguous, then pressure is placed on the moral evidentialist assumption that one is morally justified in taking a theistic truth-claim to be true only if one's total evidence sufficiently supports its truth. After investigating some contemporary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Paradox and Mystery in Theology.Bruce P. Baugus - 2013 - Heythrop Journal 54 (2):238-251.
    The question of paradox in Christian theology continues to attract attention in contemporary philosophical theology. Much of this attention understandably centers on the epistemological problems paradoxical claims pose for Christian faith. But even among those who conclude that certain points of Christian theology are paradoxical and that belief in paradoxical points of doctrine is epistemically supportable, concepts of the nature and function of paradox in Christian theology differ significantly. In this essay, after briefly noting the diversity of phenomena that count (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on the grounds of religious faith: A Kantian proposal.Hanne Appelqvist - 2018 - European Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):1026-1040.
    This paper argues that there is an important continuity between Wittgenstein's early remarks on religion and his later treatment of the theme as it appears in his lectures in the 1930s and in his personal diary notes at that time. This continuity pertains to 3 features. First, the early and later Wittgenstein share a critical stance on methodological naturalism, that is, the view that the method of philosophy is relevantly similar to that of the natural sciences. Importantly, religion figures as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fideism.Richard Amesbury - 2007 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Religious End of Metaphysics? Heidegger, Meillassoux and the Question of Fideism.Jussi Backman - 2016 - In Antonio Cimino & Gert-Jan van der Heiden (eds.), Rethinking Faith: Heidegger between Nietzsche and Wittgenstein. New York: Bloomsbury Academic. pp. 39-62.
    The paper analyzes Quentin Meillassoux’s conception of the fideistic approach to religious faith intrinsic to the “strong correlationism” that he considers pervasive in contemporary thought. Backman presents the basic elements of Meillassoux’s speculative materialism and especially the thesis according to which strong correlationism involves a “fideistic” approach to religiosity. In doing so, Backman critically examines Meillassoux’s notions of post-metaphysical faith, religious absolutes, and contemporary fanaticism, especially against the background of Heidegger’s philosophy. According to Backman, Meillassoux’s logical and conceptual critique of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Theodicy : a critique and a proposal.Bernard Charles Farr - unknown
    This thesis explores possibilities that arise from regarding theodicy as the activity of descriptive understanding of Christian belief and practice as found in the classical theistic framework. First, any theodicy as an activity is analysed in terms of the role of philosophy, the place of epistemology, the basis of theology, and the taking of an apologetic stance. It is then argued that traditional approaches to theodicy suffer from methodological weaknesses which derive from formulating theodicy in terms of unbelief, and from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark