Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Logique mathématique et philosophie des mathématiques.Yvon Gauthier - 1971 - Dialogue 10 (2):243-275.
    Pour le philosophe intéressé aux structures et aux fondements du savoir théorétique, à la constitution d'une « méta-théorétique «, θεωρíα., qui, mieux que les « Wissenschaftslehre » fichtéenne ou husserlienne et par-delà les débris de la métaphysique, veut dans une intention nouvelle faire la synthèse du « théorétique », la logique mathématique se révèle un objet privilégié.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nonsense logics and their algebraic properties.Victor K. Finn & Revaz Grigolia - 1993 - Theoria 59 (1-3):207-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • In the shadow of giants: The work of mario pieri in the foundations of mathematics.Elena Anne Marchisotto - 1995 - History and Philosophy of Logic 16 (1):107-119.
    (1995). In the shadow of giants: The work of mario pieri in the foundations of mathematics. History and Philosophy of Logic: Vol. 16, No. 1, pp. 107-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Lewis Carroll's Formal Logic.Francine Abeles - 2005 - History and Philosophy of Logic 26 (1):33-46.
    Charles L. Dodgson's reputation as a significant figure in nineteenth-century logic was firmly established when the philosopher and historian of philosophy William Warren Bartley, III published Dodgson's ?lost? book of logic, Part II of Symbolic Logic, in 1977. Bartley's commentary and annotations confirm that Dodgson was a superb technical innovator. In this paper, I closely examine Dodgson's methods and their evolution in the two parts of Symbolic Logic to clarify and justify Bartley's claims. Then, using more recent publications and unpublished (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Platonism, phenomenology, and interderivability.Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock - 2010 - In Mirja Hartimo (ed.), Phenomenology and mathematics. London: Springer. pp. 23--46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intensionality and paradoxes in ramsey’s ‘the foundations of mathematics’.Dustin Tucker - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):1-25.
    In , Frank Ramsey separates paradoxes into two groups, now taken to be the logical and the semantical. But he also revises the logical system developed in Whitehead and Russellthe intensional paradoxess interest in these problems seriously, then the intensional paradoxes deserve more widespread attention than they have historically received.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reflections on the revolution at Stanford.F. A. Muller - 2011 - Synthese 183 (1):87-114.
    We inquire into the question whether the Aristotelean or classical \emph{ideal} of science has been realised by the Model Revolution, initiated at Stanford University during the 1950ies and spread all around the world of philosophy of science --- \emph{salute} P.\ Suppes. The guiding principle of the Model Revolution is: \emph{a scientific theory is a set of structures in the domain of discourse of axiomatic set-theory}, characterised by a set-theoretical predicate. We expound some critical reflections on the Model Revolution; the conclusions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The classical model of science: A millennia-old model of scientific rationality.Willem R. de Jong & Arianna Betti - 2010 - Synthese 174 (2):185-203.
    Throughout more than two millennia philosophers adhered massively to ideal standards of scientific rationality going back ultimately to Aristotle’s Analytica posteriora . These standards got progressively shaped by and adapted to new scientific needs and tendencies. Nevertheless, a core of conditions capturing the fundamentals of what a proper science should look like remained remarkably constant all along. Call this cluster of conditions the Classical Model of Science . In this paper we will do two things. First of all, we will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Adventures of abstraction.Ignacio Angelelli - 2004 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 82 (1):11-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Category theory and concrete universals.David P. Ellerman - 1988 - Erkenntnis 28 (3):409 - 429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Uniform Gentzen systems.Raymond M. Smullyan - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (4):549-559.
    Generally speaking, it appears correct to say that in a formulation of first order logic in which a large number of connectives are taken as primitive which allows us to have our cake and eat it too.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Trees and nest structures.Raymond M. Smullyan - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (3):303-321.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Equivalence between semantics for intuitionism. I.E. G. K. López-Escobar - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):773-780.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A modern elaboration of the ramified theory of types.Twan Laan & Rob Nederpelt - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (2-3):243 - 278.
    The paper first formalizes the ramified type theory as (informally) described in the Principia Mathematica [32]. This formalization is close to the ideas of the Principia, but also meets contemporary requirements on formality and accuracy, and therefore is a new supply to the known literature on the Principia (like [25], [19], [6] and [7]).As an alternative, notions from the ramified type theory are expressed in a lambda calculus style. This situates the type system of Russell and Whitehead in a modern (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Model existence theorems for modal and intuitionistic logics.Melvin Fitting - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (4):613-627.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • An intuitionistically plausible interpretation of intuitionistic logic.H. C. M. de Swart - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (4):564-578.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Systems of substitutional semantics.Daniel Bonevac - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (4):631-656.
    I investigate substitutional interpretations of quantifiers that count existential sentences true just in case they have true instances in a parametric extension of the language. I devise a semantics meeting four criteria: (1) it accounts adequately for natural language quantification; (2) it provides an account of justification in abstract sciences; (3) it constitutes a continuous semantics for natural and formal languages; and (4) it is purely substitutional, containing no appeal to referential interpretations. The prospects for a purely substitutional theory of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logics in scientific discovery.Atocha Aliseda - 2004 - Foundations of Science 9 (3):339-363.
    In this paper I argue for a place for logic inscientific methodology, at the same level asthat of computational and historicalapproaches. While it is well known that a awhole generation of philosophers dismissedLogical Positivism (not just for the logicthough), there are at least two reasons toreconsider logical approaches in the philosophyof science. On the one hand, the presentsituation in logical research has gone farbeyond the formal developments that deductivelogic reached last century, and new researchincludes the formalization of several othertypes of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations