Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Metric spaces and the axiom of choice.Omar De la Cruz, Eric Hall, Paul Howard, Kyriakos Keremedis & Jean E. Rubin - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (5):455-466.
    We study conditions for a topological space to be metrizable, properties of metrizable spaces, and the role the axiom of choice plays in these matters.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Unions and the axiom of choice.Omar De la Cruz, Eric J. Hall, Paul Howard, Kyriakos Keremedis & Jean E. Rubin - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (6):652-665.
    We study statements about countable and well-ordered unions and their relation to each other and to countable and well-ordered forms of the axiom of choice. Using WO as an abbreviation for “well-orderable”, here are two typical results: The assertion that every WO family of countable sets has a WO union does not imply that every countable family of WO sets has a WO union; the axiom of choice for WO families of WO sets does not imply that the countable union (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Finiteness classes arising from Ramsey-theoretic statements in set theory without choice.Joshua Brot, Mengyang Cao & David Fernández-Bretón - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (6):102961.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Dependent choice, properness, and generic absoluteness.David Asperó & Asaf Karagila - forthcoming - Review of Symbolic Logic:1-25.
    We show that Dependent Choice is a sufficient choice principle for developing the basic theory of proper forcing, and for deriving generic absoluteness for the Chang model in the presence of large cardinals, even with respect to $\mathsf {DC}$ -preserving symmetric submodels of forcing extensions. Hence, $\mathsf {ZF}+\mathsf {DC}$ not only provides the right framework for developing classical analysis, but is also the right base theory over which to safeguard truth in analysis from the independence phenomenon in the presence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Relations between cardinalities of the finite sequences and the finite subsets of a set.Navin Aksornthong & Pimpen Vejjajiva - 2018 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 64 (6):529-534.
    We write and for the cardinalities of the set of finite sequences and the set of finite subsets, respectively, of a set which is of cardinality. With the axiom of choice (), for every infinite cardinal but, without, any relationship between and for an arbitrary infinite cardinal cannot be proved. In this paper, we give conditions that make and comparable for an infinite cardinal. Among our results, we show that, if we assume the axiom of choice for sets of finite (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • MA(ℵ0) restricted to complete Boolean algebras and choice.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2021 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 67 (4):420-431.
    It is a long standing open problem whether or not the Axiom of Countable Choice implies the fragment of Martin's Axiom either in or in. In this direction, we provide a partial answer by establishing that the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem in conjunction with the Countable Union Theorem does not imply restricted to complete Boolean algebras in. Furthermore, we prove that the latter (formally) weaker form of and the Δ‐system Lemma are independent of each other in.We also answer open questions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Łoś's theorem and the axiom of choice.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2019 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 65 (3):280-292.
    In set theory without the Axiom of Choice (), we investigate the problem of the placement of Łoś's Theorem () in the hierarchy of weak choice principles, and answer several open questions from the book Consequences of the Axiom of Choice by Howard and Rubin, as well as an open question by Brunner. We prove a number of results summarised in § 3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the minimal cover property and certain notions of finite.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2018 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 57 (5-6):665-686.
    In set theory without the axiom of choice, we investigate the deductive strength of the principle “every topological space with the minimal cover property is compact”, and its relationship with certain notions of finite as well as with properties of linearly ordered sets and partially ordered sets.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Almost Disjoint and Mad Families in Vector Spaces and Choice Principles.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (3):1093-1110.
    In set theory without the Axiom of Choice ( $\mathsf {AC}$ ), we investigate the open problem of the deductive strength of statements which concern the existence of almost disjoint and maximal almost disjoint (MAD) families of infinite-dimensional subspaces of a given infinite-dimensional vector space, as well as the extension of almost disjoint families in infinite-dimensional vector spaces to MAD families.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A note on the deductive strength of the Nielsen‐Schreier theorem.Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2018 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 64 (3):173-177.
    We show that the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem () does not imply the Nielsen‐Schreier Theorem () in, thus strengthening the result of Kleppmann from “Nielsen‐Schreier and the Axiom of Choice” that the (strictly weaker than ) Ordering Principle () does not imply in. We also show that is false in Mostowski's Linearly Ordered Model of. The above two results also settle the corresponding open problems from Howard and Rubin's “Consequences of the Axiom of Choice”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The dense linear ordering principle.David Pincus - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):438-456.
    Let DO denote the principle: Every infinite set has a dense linear ordering. DO is compared to other ordering principles such as O, the Linear Ordering principle, KW, the Kinna-Wagner Principle, and PI, the Prime Ideal Theorem, in ZF, Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory without AC, the Axiom of Choice. The main result is: Theorem. $AC \Longrightarrow KW \Longrightarrow DO \Longrightarrow O$ , and none of the implications is reversible in ZF + PI. The first and third implications and their irreversibilities were (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adding dependent choice.David Pincus - 1977 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 11 (1):105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • On Hausdorff operators in ZF$\mathsf {ZF}$.Kyriakos Keremedis & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 2023 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 69 (3):347-369.
    A Hausdorff space is called effectively Hausdorff if there exists a function F—called a Hausdorff operator—such that, for every with,, where U and V are disjoint open neighborhoods of x and y, respectively. Among other results, we establish the following in, i.e., in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the Axiom of Choice (): is equivalent to “For every set X, the Cantor cube is effectively Hausdorff”. This enhances the result of Howard, Keremedis, Rubin and Rubin [13] that is equivalent to “Hausdorff (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Independent families and some notions of finiteness.Eric Hall & Kyriakos Keremedis - 2023 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 62 (5):689-701.
    In \(\textbf{ZF}\), the well-known Fichtenholz–Kantorovich–Hausdorff theorem concerning the existence of independent families of _X_ of size \(|{\mathcal {P}} (X)|\) is equivalent to the following portion of the equally well-known Hewitt–Marczewski–Pondiczery theorem concerning the density of product spaces: “The product \({\textbf{2}}^{{\mathcal {P}}(X)}\) has a dense subset of size |_X_|”. However, the latter statement turns out to be strictly weaker than \(\textbf{AC}\) while the full Hewitt–Marczewski–Pondiczery theorem is equivalent to \(\textbf{AC}\). We study the relative strengths in \(\textbf{ZF}\) between the statement “_X_ has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hindman’s theorem in the hierarchy of choice principles.David Fernández-Bretón - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 24 (1).
    In the context of [Formula: see text], we analyze a version of Hindman’s finite unions theorem on infinite sets, which normally requires the Axiom of Choice to be proved. We establish the implication relations between this statement and various classical weak choice principles, thus precisely locating the strength of the statement as a weak form of the [Formula: see text].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark