Switch to: References

Citations of:

Science and Ethics

New York: Cambridge University Press (2006)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Meaning Matters: The Biosemiotic Basis of Bioethics.Jonathan Beever - 2012 - Biosemiotics 5 (2):181-191.
    If the central problem in philosophical ethics is determining and defining the scope of moral value, our normative ethical theories must be able to explain on what basis and to what extent entities have value. The scientific foundation of contemporary biosemiotic theory grounds a theory of moral value capable of addressing this problem. Namely, it suggests that what is morally relevant is semiosis. Within this framework, semiosis is a morally relevant and natural property of all living things thereby offering us (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From epistemology to policy: reorienting philosophy courses for science students.Mark Thomas Young - 2022 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 (2):1-14.
    Philosophy of science has traditionally focused on the epistemological dimensions of scientific practice at the expense of the ethical and political questions scientists encounter when addressing questions of policy in advisory contexts. In this article, I will explore how an exclusive focus on epistemology and theoretical reason can function to reinforce common, yet flawed assumptions concerning the role of scientific knowledge in policy decision making when reproduced in philosophy courses for science students. In order to address this concern, I will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Quantified Animal: Precision Livestock Farming and the Ethical Implications of Objectification.Ynte K. van Dam, Peter H. Feindt, Bernice Bovenkerk & Jacqueline M. Bos - 2018 - Food Ethics 2 (1):77-92.
    Precision livestock farming (PLF) is the management of livestock using the principles and technology of process engineering. Key to PLF is the dense monitoring of variegated parameters, including animal growth, output of produce (e.g. milk, eggs), diseases, animal behaviour, and the physical environment (e.g. thermal micro-environment, ammonia emissions). While its proponents consider PLF a win-win strategy that combines production efficiency with sustainability goals and animal welfare, critics emphasise, inter alia, the potential interruption of human-animal relationships. This paper discusses the notion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The opposite of human enhancement: Nanotechnology and the blind chicken problem. [REVIEW]Paul B. Thompson - 2008 - NanoEthics 2 (3):305-316.
    Nanotechnologies that have been linked to the possibility of enhancing cognitive capabilities of human beings might also be deployed to reduce or eliminate such capabilities in non-human vertebrate animals. A surprisingly large literature on the ethics of such disenhancement has been developed in response to the suggestion that it would be an ethically defensible response to animal suffering both in medical experimentation and in industrial livestock production. However, review of this literature illustrates the difficulty of formulating a coherent ethical debate. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • To Each Technology Its Own Ethics: The Problem of Ethical Proliferation.Henrik Skaug Sætra & John Danaher - 2022 - Philosophy and Technology 35 (4):1-26.
    Ethics plays a key role in the normative analysis of the impacts of technology. We know that computers in general and the processing of data, the use of artificial intelligence, and the combination of computers and/or artificial intelligence with robotics are all associated with ethically relevant implications for individuals, groups, and society. In this article, we argue that while all technologies are ethically relevant, there is no need to create a separate ‘ethics of X’ or ‘X ethics’ for each and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Inseparability of Science and Ethics in Animal Welfare.Bernard E. Rollin - 2015 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 28 (4):759-765.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Of mice and men.Bernard E. Rollin - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (5):55 – 57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Genetic engineering and the sacred.Bernard E. Rollin - 2005 - Zygon 40 (4):939-952.
    Genetic engineering of life forms could well have a profound effect upon our sense of the sacred. Integrating the experience of the sacred as George Bataille does, we can characterize it as a phenomenological encounter with prelinguistic, noncategoreal experience. This view of the sacred is similar to Friedrich Nietzsche's Dionysian experience or Rudolf Otto's mysterium tremendum and diminishes one's sense of self. It seems similar to the eighteenth‐century aesthetic categorization of “the sublime.” Despite the dominant rational approach to religiosity in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Animal Pain: What It is and Why It Matters. [REVIEW]Bernard E. Rollin - 2011 - The Journal of Ethics 15 (4):425-437.
    The basis of having a direct moral obligation to an entity is that what we do to that entity matters to it. The ability to experience pain is a sufficient condition for a being to be morally considerable. But the ability to feel pain is not a necessary condition for moral considerability. Organisms could have possibly evolved so as to be motivated to flee danger or injury or to eat or drink not by pain, but by “pangs of pleasure” that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Dying Animal.Jessica Pierce - 2013 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 10 (4):469-478.
    The study of animal death is poised to blossom into an exciting new interdisciplinary field—and one with profound relevance for bioethics. Areas of interest include the biology and evolution of death-related behavior in nonhuman animals, as well as human social, psychological, cultural, and moral attitudes toward and practices related to animal death. In this paper, I offer a brief overview of what we know about death-related behavior in animals. I will then sketch some of the bioethical implications of this emerging (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Pluralist Theory of Ethics Programs Orientations and Ideologies: An Empirical Study Anchored in Requisite Variety.Joé T. Martineau, Kevin J. Johnson & Thierry C. Pauchant - 2017 - Journal of Business Ethics 142 (4):791-815.
    We propose, in this article, a pluralistic theory of ethics programs orientations, empirically derived from the statistical analysis of responses to an ad hoc questionnaire on organizational ethics practices. The results of our research identify six different orientations to ethics programs, corresponding to as many types of organizational ethics practices. This model goes beyond the traditional opposition between a compliance orientation, focused on the regulation of behavior and the detection of deviance, and a values-based orientation, which is said to be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Can Journal Editors Police Animal Welfare? Three Es for Three Rs in Scientific Journals.Ana Marusic - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12):66-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Normality and naturalness: A comparison of the meanings of concepts used within veterinary medicine and human medicine. [REVIEW]Henrik Lerner & Bjørn Hofmann - 2011 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 32 (6):403-412.
    This article analyses the different connotations of “normality” and “being natural,” bringing together the theoretical discussion from both human medicine and veterinary medicine. We show how the interpretations of the concepts in the different areas could be mutually fruitful. It appears that the conceptions of “natural” are more elaborate in veterinary medicine, and can be of value to human medicine. In particular they can nuance and correct conceptions of nature in human medicine that may be too idealistic. Correspondingly, the wide (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ethical mouse: Be not like icarus.Robert R. Lavieri - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (5):57 – 58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Genetics and Society—Educating Scientifically Literate Citizens: Introduction to the Thematic Issue.Kostas Kampourakis, Thomas A. C. Reydon, George P. Patrinos & Bruno J. Strasser - 2014 - Science & Education 23 (2):251-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Telos and the Ethics of Animal Farming.Jes Lynning Harfeld - 2013 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 26 (3):691-709.
    The concept of animal welfare in confinement agriculture—and an ethical theory based upon this concept—necessitates an idea of what kind of being it is that fares well and what “well” is for this being. This double-question is at the heart of understanding and adequately defining welfare as qualitatively embedded in the experiencing subject. The notion of telos derives (philosophically) from Aristotle and is a way of accounting for the good life of an animal from the unique speciesness of the animal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • 'Knows' Entails Truth.Michael Hannon - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Research 38:349-366.
    It is almost universally presumed that knowledge is factive: in order to know that p it must be the case that p is true. This idea is often justified by appealing to knowledge ascriptions and related linguistic phenomena; i.e., an utterance of the form ‘S knows that p, but not-p’ sounds contradictory. In a recent article, Allan Hazlett argues that our ordinary concept of knowledge is not factive. From this it seems to follow that epistemologists cannot appeal to ordinary language (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Moving beyond the welfare standard of psychological well-being for nonhuman primates: the case of chimpanzees.John P. Gluck - 2014 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 35 (2):105-116.
    Since 1985, the US Animal Welfare Act and Public Health Service policy have required that researchers using nonhuman primates in biomedical and behavioral research develop a plan “for a physical environment adequate to promote the psychological well-being of primates.” In pursuing this charge, housing attributes such as social companionship, opportunities to express species-typical behavior, suitable space for expanded locomotor activity, and nonstressful relationships with laboratory personnel are dimensions that have dominated the discussion. Regulators were careful not to direct a specific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientific Autonomy and the 3Rs.Bernard E. Rollin - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12):62-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Instilling Fairness in Animal Research.Bernard E. Rollin - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (10):43-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Books received. [REVIEW]W. Dekkers - 2006 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 9 (3):397-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Underdetermined Interests: Scientific 'Goods' and Animal Welfare.Chris Degeling & Jane Johnson - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12):64-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The role of ethical reflection and dialogue in conceptualising animal welfare.Simon Coghlan - 2022 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 35 (3):1-17.
    This paper argues that ethical reflection and dialogue can assist in understanding what animal welfare is. Questions about animal welfare’s nature are thorny and contested. Responding to an essay by Donald Bruckner, the paper acknowledges that animal welfare is a type of normative value distinct from ethical value and that the methodology for determining prudential value is not simply reducible to ethical thought. However, it contends that connections between ethics and understanding wellbeing are closer than we might expect. The paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Taking Responsibility for Cloning: Discourses of Care and Knowledge in Biotechnological Approaches to Nonhuman Life.Jessica L. W. Carey - 2015 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 28 (3):589-599.
    This article examines the practice of animal cloning in relation to discourses of care and responsibility, in particular a common cultural interpretation of care theorized by Michel Foucault. This interpretation figures care as a “pastoral” relation premised in essential differences between carers and objects of care, and its interspecies implications are increasingly drawing the attention of theorists in animal studies. This article argues that, perhaps despite appearances, animal welfare in the form of pastoral care and abstract conceptualizations of animals that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Graphic Novel Raises Ethical Issues: Laika.Lisa Brown - 2008 - Society and Animals 16 (3):293-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Use of Animal Models in Behavioural Neuroscience Research.B. Bovenkerk & F. Kaldewaij - unknown
    Animal models are used in experiments in the behavioural neurosciences that aim to contribute to the prevention and treatment of cognitive and affective disorders in human beings, such as anxiety and depression. Ironically, those animals that are likely to be the best models for psychopathology are also likely to be considered the ones that are most morally problematic to use, if it seems probable that (and if indeed they are initially selected as models because) they have experiences that are similar (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fish Welfare in Aquaculture: Explicating the Chain of Interactions Between Science and Ethics. [REVIEW]Bernice Bovenkerk & Franck L. B. Meijboom - 2013 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 26 (1):41-61.
    Aquaculture is the fastest growing animal-production sector in the world. This leads to the question how we should guarantee fish welfare. Implementing welfare standards presupposes that we know how to weigh, define, and measure welfare. While at first glance these seem empirical questions, they cannot be answered without ethical reflection. Normative assumptions are made when weighing, defining, and measuring welfare. Moreover, the focus on welfare presupposes that welfare is a morally important concept. This in turn presupposes that we can define (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Animal Rights and the Duty to Harm: When to be a Harm Causing Deontologist.C. E. Abbate - 2020 - Zeitschrift Für Ethik Und Moralphilosophie 3 (1):5-26.
    An adequate theory of rights ought to forbid the harming of animals to promote trivial interests of humans, as is often done in the animal-user industries. But what should the rights view say about situations in which harming some animals is necessary to prevent intolerable injustices to other animals? I develop an account of respectful treatment on which, under certain conditions, it’s justified to intentionally harm some individuals to prevent serious harm to others. This can be compatible with recognizing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Animal Ethics.Cheryl Abbate - 2022 - In Routledge Handbook of Animal Welfare. pp. 353-365.
    What do we owe to non-human animals? How should we respond to the many injustices they face? Answering these questions requires philosophical attention to complicated questions about moral reasoning, moral status, and ethical theory. This first part of this chapter provides an overview of what both good and bad moral reasoning look like in the context of discussions about animal ethics. The second part of this chapter provides an overview of competing approaches to moral status, including anthropocentric, rationality, and sentio-centric (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Animal Rights and the Duty to Harm: When to be a Harm Causing Deontologist.C. E. Abbate - 2020 - Journal for Ethics and Moral Philosophy 3 (1):5-26.
    An adequate theory of rights ought to forbid the harming of animals (human or nonhuman) to promote trivial interests of humans, as is often done in the animal-user industries. But what should the rights view say about situations in which harming some animals is necessary to prevent intolerable injustices to other animals? I develop an account of respectful treatment on which, under certain conditions, it’s justified to intentionally harm some individuals to prevent serious harm to others. This can be compatible (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Husbandry to industry: Animal Agriculture, Ethics and Public Policy.Jes Harfeld - 2010 - Between the Species 13 (10):9.
    The industrialisation of agriculture has led to considerable alterations at both the technological and economical levels of animal farming. Several animal welfare issues of modern animal agriculture – e.g. stress and stereotypical behaviour – can be traced back to the industrialised intensification of housing and numbers of animals in production. Although these welfare issues dictate ethical criticism, it is the claim of this article that such direct welfare issues are only the forefront of a greater systemic ethical problem inherent to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ethics of livestock farming? : who cares?H. G. J. Gremmen - unknown
    'Concerns about livestock farming mainly focus on animal welfare. Societal groups address livestock farmers on their duty of care because more and more animals are kept in increasingly intensive systems. Most farmers, as caring farmers, are willing to take various measures to improve the welfare of their animals. However, not all solutions to animal welfare problems are seen as a welfare improvement or give rise to other welfare concerns. How will farmers be able to perform their duty of care?'.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A moral Operating System of livestock farming.Bart Gremmen - 2017 - Pragmatism Today 8 (2):41-51.
    Societal views about livestock production systems in Europe are changing dramatically in a negative direction. Based on the tradition of pragmatism in applied philosophy I develop a Moral Operating System of animal production systems in cooperating a plurality of ethical views. This moral operating system of animal production systems consists of two interactive, dynamic parts: an internal professional care ethics combined with an emergent ethics in life sciences enabling change by responsible innovation, and external ethical boundary conditions based on societal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Review of Science and Ethics. [REVIEW]Gregory L. Bock - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark