Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Visions of the Self in Late Medieval Christianity: Some Cross-Disciplinary Reflections: Sarah Coakley.Sarah Coakley - 1992 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 32:89-103.
    In a volume devoted to philosophy, religion and the spiritual life, I would like to focus the later part of my essay on a comparison of two Christian spiritual writings of the fourteenth century, the anonymous Cloud of Unknowing in the West, and the Triads of Gregory Palamas in the Byzantine East. Their examples, for reasons which I shall explain, seem to me rich with implications for some of our current philosophical and theological aporias on the nature of the self. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theory in psychology: A review essay of Andre Kukla's methods of theoretical psychology. [REVIEW]Huib Looren de Jong, Sacha Bem & Maurice Schouten - 2004 - Philosophical Psychology 17 (2):275 – 295.
    This review essay critically discusses Andre Kukla's Methods of theoretical psychology. It is argued that Kukla mistakenly tries to build his case for theorizing in psychology as a separate discipline on a dubious distinction between theory and observation. He then argues that the demise of empiricism implies a return of some form of rationalism, which entails an autonomous role for theorizing in psychology. Having shown how this theory-observation dichotomy goes back to traditional and largely abandoned ideas in epistemology, an alternative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • First-person Folk Psychology: Mindreading or Mindshaping?Leon De Bruin - 2016 - Studia Philosophica Estonica 9 (1):170-183.
    Proponents of mindshaping argue that third-person folk psychology is not primarily about "reading" mental states for the purpose of behavior prediction and explanation. Instead, they claim that third-person folk psychology is first and foremost a regulative practice -- one that "shapes" mental states in accordance with the norms of a shared folk psychological framework. This paper investigates to what extent the core assumptions behind the mindshaping hypothesis are compatible with an account of first-person folk psychology that is based on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What is Humane Philosophy and Why is it At Risk?John Cottingham - 2009 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 65:233-255.
    Let me begin with what may seem a very minor point, but one which I think reveals something about how many philosophers today conceive of their subject. During the past few decades, there has been an increasing tendency for references in philosophy books and articles to be formatted in the ‘author and date’ style (‘see Fodor (1996)’, ‘see Smith (2001)’.) A neat and economical reference system, you may think; and it certainly saves space, albeit inconveniencing readers by forcing them to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Naturalism, science and the supernatural.Steve Clarke - 2009 - Sophia 48 (2):127-142.
    There is overwhelming agreement amongst naturalists that a naturalistic ontology should not allow for the possibility of supernatural entities. I argue, against this prevailing consensus, that naturalists have no proper basis to oppose the existence of supernatural entities. Naturalism is characterized, following Leiter and Rea, as a position which involves a primary commitment to scientific methodology and it is argued that any naturalistic ontological commitments must be compatible with this primary commitment. It is further argued that properly applied scientific method (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Descartes' Debt to Augustine.Stephen R. L. Clark - 1992 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 32:73-88.
    Jonathan Edwards identified the central act of faith as ‘the cordial consent of beings to Being in general’, which is to say to God. That equation, of Being, Truth and God, is rarely taken seriously in analytical circles. My argument will be that this is to neglect the real context of a great deal of past philosophy, particularly the very Cartesian arguments from which so many undergraduate courses begin. All too many students issue from such courses immunized against enthusiasm, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constructing an understanding of mind: The development of children's social understanding within social interaction.Jeremy I. M. Carpendale & Charlie Lewis - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (1):79-96.
    Theories of children's developing understanding of mind tend to emphasize either individualistic processes of theory formation, maturation, or introspection, or the process of enculturation. However, such theories must be able to account for the accumulating evidence of the role of social interaction in the development of social understanding. We propose an alternative account, according to which the development of children's social understanding occurs within triadic interaction involving the child's experience of the world as well as communicative interaction with others about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Idealism and Greek Philosophy: What Descartes Saw and Berkeley Missed.Miles F. Burnyeat - 1982 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 13:19-50.
    It is a standing temptation for philosophers to find anticipations of their own views in the great thinkers of the past, but few have been so bold in the search for precursors, and so utterly mistaken, as Berkeley when he claimed Plato and Aristotle as allies to his immaterialist idealism. InSiris: A Chain of Philosophical Reflexions and Inquiries Concerning the Virtues of Tar-Water, which Berkeley published in his old age in 1744, he reviews the leading philosophies of antiquity and finds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Epistemological Behaviorism, Nonconceptual Content, and the Given.Matthew Burstein - 2010 - Contemporary Pragmatism 7 (1):168-89.
    Debates about nonconceptual content impact many philosophical disciplines, including philosophy of mind, epistemology, and philosophy of language. However, arguments made by many philosophers from within the pragmatist tradition, including Quine, Sellars, Davidson, Rorty, and Putnam, undercut the very role such content purportedly plays. I explore how specifically Sellarsian arguments against the Given and Rortian defenses of “epistemological behaviorism” undermine standard conceptions of nonconceptual content. Subsequently, I show that the standard objections to epistemological behaviorism inadequately attend to the essentially social and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Editorial Review: Kant and Contemporary Epistemology.Graham Bird - 1997 - Kantian Review 1:1-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy of Education for the Public Good: Five challenges and an agenda.Gert Biesta - 2012 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 44 (6):581-593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • A Social Representations Approach To The Communication Between Different Spheres: An Analysis Of The Impacts Of Two Discursive Formats.Susana Batel & Paula Castro - 2009 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 39 (4):415-433.
    This paper discusses the potential of the notions of reification and consensualization as developed by the theory of social representations as analytical tools for addressing the communication between the lay and scientific spheres. Social Representations Theory started by offering an over-sharp distinction between the reified and the consensual universes of which science and common sense, respectively, were presented as paradigmatic. This paper, however, suggests that the notions of consensual and reified can be considered as describing two distinct communicative formats: reification (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Metaphilosophical Dualism.Ross Barham - 2011 - Essays in Philosophy 12 (2):273-291.
    There exist two equally prominent, though seemingly divergent metaphilosophical viewpoints. One takes philosophy to be an essentially revolutionary process. The other sees philosophy as a constructive, collaborative enterprise that seeks increased rigor and consensus. Recent debate in the philosophy of language regarding the relationship of particular languages to the general capacity for language reveals an illuminating structural analogy with these divergent metaphilosophical trends. While neither debate is settled herein, regardless of their eventual determinations, it is concluded that there is little (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Take Painkillers?David Bain - 2019 - Noûs 53 (2):462-490.
    Accounts of the nature of unpleasant pain have proliferated over the past decade, but there has been little systematic investigation of which of them can accommodate its badness. This paper is such a study. In its sights are two targets: those who deny the non-instrumental disvalue of pain's unpleasantness; and those who allow it but deny that it can be accommodated by the view—advanced by me and others—that unpleasant pains are interoceptive experiences with evaluative content. Against the former, I argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • An approach to D. Davidson’s “Radical Interpretation” theory.Inês Araújo - 2009 - Filosofia Unisinos 10 (3):302-316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Using 'Foundation'as Inculturation Hermeneutic in a World Church: Did Rahner Validate Lonergan?Cyril Orji - 2013 - Heythrop Journal 54 (2):287-300.
    Lonergan writes both of a foundation for human knowing as well as of a functional specialty he termed ‘foundations’. Neither of these is the same as ‘foundation’ as the term is used by nonfoundationalists. Lack of clarity and differentiation regarding what is meant by ‘foundationalism’ sometimes informs the perception that Lonergan is a foundationalist. The burden of this essay is to show that Lonergan's philosophical and theological thought, as well as his use of the term ‘foundations’, fall awkwardly, if at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Points of view: Kant on perspectival knowledge.Michela Massimi - 2018 - Synthese 198 (S13):3279-3296.
    The aim of this paper is to cast new light on an important and often overlooked notion of perspectival knowledge arising from Kant. In addition to a traditional notion of perspectival knowledge as "knowledge from a vantage point", a second novel notion — "knowledge towards a vantage point" —is here introduced. The origin and rationale of perspectival knowledge 2 are traced back to Kant's so-called transcendental illusion. The legacy of the Kantian notion of perspectival knowledge 2 for contemporary discussions on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Pragmatic a Priori Knowledge: A Pragmatic Approach to the Nature and Object of What Can Be Known Independently of Experience.Lauri Järvilehto - 2011 - Jyväskylä University Printing House.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reflections on iconicity, representation, and resemblance: Peirce's theory of signs, Goodman on resemblance, and modern philosophies of language and mind.Randall R. Dipert - 1996 - Synthese 106 (3):373 - 397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Is a Post-philosophical Sociology Possible? Insights from Norbert Elias’s Sociology of Knowledge.Philip Walsh - 2014 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44 (2):179-200.
    This article investigates the status of Norbert Elias’s conception of the sociology of knowledge as the means to provide a new epistemological security for sociology. The author of the article argues that this translates into an effective critique of the underlaboring model of the relationship between philosophy and the social sciences, which is consistent with Elias’s attempt to consolidate his own sociological theory. Nevertheless, the author argues that Elias’s sociology of knowledge runs into problems in its attempt to evade the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Priority of literature to Philosophy in Richard Rorty.محمد اصغری - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations 13 (28):207-219.
    In this article, I try to defend the thesis that imagination against reason, moral progress through imagination not the reason, the emergence of literary culture after philosophical culture from Hegel onwards, contingency of language, the usefulness of literature (poetry, novels and stories, etc.) in enhancing empathy with one another and ultimately reducing philosophy to poetry in Richard Rorty's writings point to one thing: the priority of literature to philosophy. The literary or post-physical culture that Rorty defends is opposed to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From critique of ideology to politics: Habermas on Bildung.Asger Sørensen - 2015 - Ethics and Education 10 (2):252-270.
    Considering the German idea of Bildung, I argue that it is a central concern of Habermas. First, he criticized the idea of being educated as a sign of innate abilities, emphasizing instead the significance of the social conditions of the upbringing. Subsequently, inspired by Adorno, he performed an analysis of Bildung, based on critique of ideology, in The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere. The basic critique is that Bildung is too tightly connected to societal dominance, but still the ideal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shadow and shade: The ethopoietics of enlightenment.Mick Smith - 2003 - Ethics, Place and Environment 6 (2):117 – 130.
    Modern Western thought and culture have envisaged their task in terms of a metaphorics, a metaphysics and a technics of 'enlightenment'. However, the ethical and environmental implications of this determination to dispel all shadows have become increasingly pernicious as modernity both extends and alters the conceptualization and employment of (a now artificial) light as a tool of discovery and control. Drawing on the work of Foucault and Benjamin amongst others, this paper seeks to illustrate, through a critical ethopoietics, the 'speculative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Learning from experience.Richard Smith - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 21 (1):37–46.
    Richard Smith; Learning from Experience, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 21, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 37–46, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9752.1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Towards a general theory on the existence of typically nati onal philosophies: the Portuguese, the Austrian, the Italian, and other cases reviewed.Henrique Jales Ribeiro - 2012 - Revista Filosófica de Coimbra 21 (41):199-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • In the face of relativism: Stephen Toulminsʼs latest views on rhetoric and argumentation.Henrique Jales Ribeiro - 2015 - Revista Filosófica de Coimbra 24 (47):95-110.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Filosofia, ciência e retórica: a viragem retórica do século XX aos nossos dias.Henrique Jales Ribeiro - 2015 - Revista Filosófica de Coimbra 24 (48):335-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Romantic ignorance.Anthony Reynolds - 2005 - Angelaki 10 (3):15 – 25.
    To view a work knowingly gives understanding but not hope Rorty, "The Necessity of Inspired Reading" I cannot count one. I know not the first letter of the alphabet. Thoreau, Walden.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to Make Your Relationship Work? Aesthetic Relations with Technology.Jeannette Pols - 2017 - Foundations of Science 22 (2):421-424.
    Discussing the workings of technology in care as aesthetic rather than as ethical or epistemological interventions focusses on how technologies engage in and change relations between those involved. Such an aesthetic study opens up a repertoire to address values that are abundant in care, but are as yet hardly theorized. Kamphof studies the problem that sensor technology reveals things about the elderly patients without the patients being aware of this. I suggest improvement of these relations may be considered in aesthetic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conceptual Validity in a Nontheoretical Human Science.Donald E. Polkinghorne - 1986 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 17 (2):129-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Can Philosophy be a Rigorous Science?Herman Philipse - 2009 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 65:155-176.
    It is difficult to imagine that a Royal Institute of Physics would organize an annual lecture series on the theme ‘conceptions of physics’. Similarly, it is quite improbable that a Royal Institute of Astronomy would even contemplate inviting speakers for a lecture series called ‘conceptions of astronomy’. What, then, is so special about philosophy that the theme of this lecture series does not appear to be altogether outlandish? Is it, perhaps, that philosophy is the reflective discipline par excellence, so that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and post‐analytic philosophy of education: Rorty or Lyotard?Michael Peters - 1997 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 29 (2):1-32.
    I was thinking about my philosophical work and saying to myself: ‘I destroy, I destroy, I destroy…’Context: The ‘linguistic turn’ of Western philosophy ; and correlatively, the decline of universalist discourses. The weariness with regard to ‘theory’, and the miserable slackening that goes along with it. The time has come to philosophize.…there is no danger of philosophy's ‘coming to an end’. Religion did not come to an end in the Enlightenment, nor painting in Impressionism. Even if the period from Plato (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Satire, Swift and the deconstruction of the public intellectual.Michael A. Peters - 2022 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 54 (7):849-856.
    It is intended that a large Academy be erected, capable of containing nine thousand seven hundred forty and three persons, which, by modest computation, is reckoned to be pretty near the current nu...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Looks as powers.Philip Pettit - 2003 - Philosophical Issues 13 (1):221-52.
    Although they may differ on the reason why, many philosophers hold that it is a priori that an object is red if and only if it is such as to look red to normal observers in normal conditions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Der Charakter der Mathematik zwischen Philosophie und Wissenschaft.Michael Otte - 1989 - Philosophica 43:79-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can there be progress in philosophy?Kai Nielsen - 1987 - Metaphilosophy 18 (1):1–30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The practice of philosophy.Isaac Nevo - 1997 - European Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):74–82.
    Words and Life (= WL) is a bulky collection of 29 essays, edited and introduced by James Conant. Pragmatism: An Open Question (= P) is a much thinner collection, dedicated to Conant, of just three lectures. Taken together, the two books constitute an argument for pragmatism as a viable option in contemporary philosophy, and a new (pragmatic) basis for what remains viable in the philosophical and political ideals of the Enlightenment. As in a previous collection of essays (Putnam 1990), Conant’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Defining Objectivity in Realist Terms: Objectivity as a Second-Order ‘Bridging’ Concept Part II: Bridging to Praxis.Jamie Morgan & Wendy Olsen - 2008 - Journal of Critical Realism 7 (1):107-132.
    Our aim is to explore and develop notions of objectivity that are useful and appropriate for critical realist empirical research. In Part I, we provided an initial definition that introduced the idea that objectivity is a value that must be chosen but that its significance is rooted in a series of other epistemological and ontological matters. We also addressed why it is worthwhile in realist terms to develop the notion of objectivity, and began to develop a revision of the concept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophical Writing: Prefacing as professing.Rob McCormack - 2008 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 40 (7):832-855.
    If you do not wish to construe philosophical discourse as simply a discourse of cognition, a theoretical discourse; if you think it is also a practical, ethical discourse: how should you write? How should you frame the ethos, the authority of your discourse? This article re‐presents an extended preface I wrote and rewrote obsessively over a period of nearly two years in an effort to forge a voice and mode of address adequate to my sense of philosophical discourse as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein on Rules: implications for authority and discipline in education.James D. Marshall - 1985 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 19 (1):3-11.
    James D Marshall; Wittgenstein on Rules: implications for authority and discipline in education, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 19, Issue 1, 30 May.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Examination of practices of ignorance conducive to democracy based on Rancièrian thought and Rortian pragmatism.Lev Marder - 2016 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 42 (8):797-814.
    Theorists, who broadly subscribe to Claude Lefort’s characterization of democracy as the dissolution of the markers of certainty, disagree over the proper enactment of democracy. In this article, I consider the possibility of narrowing the gap by attending to the ignorance advocated by each of the two approaches – the disruptive radical route Jacques Rancière describes and the reformist approach of Richard Rorty. I highlight the attributes and shortcomings of the positive link between practices of ignorance and democracy in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • McDowell, scepticism, and the 'veil of perception'.David Macarthur - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2):175-190.
    McDowell has argued that external world scepticism is a pressing problem only in so far as we accept, on the basis of the argument from illusion, the claim that perceiving that p and hallucinating that p involve a highest common factor.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On the Non‐discursive Nature of Competence.Gerard Lum - 2004 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 36 (5):485-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Image Politics: The Monotheistic Prohibition of Images and its Afterlife in Political Aesthetics.Gertrud Koch - 2013 - Critical Horizons 14 (3):341-354.
    This essay focuses on the ongoing references made to the ban on graven images for the foundation of political aesthetics. In this tradition the image itself plays a significant role in the creation of a dichotomy in which the image becomes either “icon” or false appearance. The image in this tradition is a powerful agent and gains as such performative power. From the Bible to Kant and German idealism to Adorno and Deleuze, the prohibition of the image signals its power (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • De-idealizing Disagreement, Rethinking Relativism.Katherina Kinzel & Martin Kusch - 2018 - Humana Mente 26 (1):40-71.
    Relativism is often motivated in terms of certain types of disagreement. In this paper, we survey the philosophical debates over two such types: faultless disagreement in the case of gustatory conflict, and fundamental disagreement in the case of epistemic conflict. Each of the two discussions makes use of a implicit conception of judgement: brute judgement in the case of faultless disagreement, and rule-governed judgement in the case of fundamental disagreement. We show that the prevalent accounts work with unreasonably high levels (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Sustainability and the 'Struggle for Existence': The Critical Role of Metaphor in Society's Metabolism.Tim Jackson - 2003 - Environmental Values 12 (3):289 - 316.
    This paper presents a historical examination of the influence of the Darwinian metaphor 'the struggle for existence' on a variety of scientific theories which inform our current understanding of the prospects for sustainable development. The first part of the paper traces the use of the metaphor of struggle through two distinct avenues of thought relevant to the search for sustainable development. One of these avenues leads to the biophysical critique of conventional development popularised by 'ecological economists' such as Georgescu-Roegen and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hegel's Critique of Foundationalism in the 'Doctrine of Essence'.Stephen Houlgate - 1999 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 44:25-45.
    It is a commonplace among certain recent philosophers that there is no such thing as the essence of anything. Nietzsche, for example, asserts that things have no essence of their own, because they are nothing but ceaselessly changing ways of acting on, and reacting to, other things. Wittgenstein, famously, rejects the idea that there is an essence to language and thought – at least if we mean by that some a priori logical structure underlying our everyday utterances. Finally, Richard Rorty (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hegel's Critique of Foundationalism in the “Doctrine of Essence”.Stephen Houlgate - 1999 - Hegel Bulletin 20 (1-2):18-34.
    It is a commonplace among certain recent philosophers that there is no such thing as theessenceof anything. Nietzsche, for example, asserts that things have no essence of their own, because they are nothing but ceaselessly changing ways of acting on, and reacting to, other things. Wittgenstein, famously, rejects the idea that there is an essence to language and thought — at least if we mean by that somea priorilogical structure underlying our everyday utterances. Finally, Richard Rorty urges that we “abandon (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What makes practice educational?Pádraig Hogan - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 24 (1):15–27.
    Pádraig Hogan; What Makes Practice Educational?, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 24, Issue 1, 30 May 2006, Pages 15–26, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Solidarity, objectivity, and the human form of life: Wittgenstein vs. Rorty.Greg Hill - 1997 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 11 (4):555-580.
    Reason, objectivity, and human nature are now suspect ideas. Among postmodern thinkers, Richard Rorty has advanced an especially forceful critique of these notions. Drawing partly on Wittgenstein's philosophy of language, Rorty contends that objectivity is no more than a metaphysical name for intersubjective agreement, and that “human nature” is an empty category, there being nothing beneath history and culture. Wittgenstein himself, however, recognized within the world's many civilizations “the common behavior of mankind,” without which Rorty's ethnocentric “solidarity” would be inconceivable. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations