Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Elements of Mathematical Logic

Synthese 8 (8):430-431 (1950)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought.John Corcoran - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (4):261-288.
    Prior Analytics by the Greek philosopher Aristotle and Laws of Thought by the English mathematician George Boole are the two most important surviving original logical works from before the advent of modern logic. This article has a single goal: to compare Aristotle's system with the system that Boole constructed over twenty-two centuries later intending to extend and perfect what Aristotle had started. This comparison merits an article itself. Accordingly, this article does not discuss many other historically and philosophically important aspects (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • (1 other version)Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of thought.John Corcoran - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic. 24 (4):261-288.
    Prior Analytics by the Greek philosopher Aristotle (384 – 322 BCE) and Laws of Thought by the English mathematician George Boole (1815 – 1864) are the two most important surviving original logical works from before the advent of modern logic. This article has a single goal: to compare Aristotle’s system with the system that Boole constructed over twenty-two centuries later intending to extend and perfect what Aristotle had started. This comparison merits an article itself. Accordingly, this article does not discuss (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Schemata: The concept of schema in the history of logic.John Corcoran - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (2):219-240.
    The syllogistic figures and moods can be taken to be argument schemata as can the rules of the Stoic propositional logic. Sentence schemata have been used in axiomatizations of logic only since the landmark 1927 von Neumann paper [31]. Modern philosophers know the role of schemata in explications of the semantic conception of truth through Tarski’s 1933 Convention T [42]. Mathematical logicians recognize the role of schemata in first-order number theory where Peano’s second-order Induction Axiom is approximated by Herbrand’s Induction-Axiom (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • (1 other version)Mechanical intelligence and Godelian Arguments.Vincenzo Fano - 2014 - Epistemologia 2:207-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the necessary philosophical premises of the Goedelian arguments.Fano Vincenzo & Graziani Pierluigi - unknown
    Lucas-Penrose type arguments have been the focus of many papers in the literature. In the present paper we attempt to evaluate the consequences of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems for the philosophy of the mind. We argue that the best answer to this question was given by Gödel already in 1951 when he realized that either our intellectual capability is not representable by a Turing Machine, or we can never know with mathematical certainty what such a machine is. But his considerations became (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The autonomy of probability theory (notes on Kolmogorov, rényi, and popper).Hugues Leblanc - 1989 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40 (2):167-181.
    Kolmogorov's account in his [1933] of an absolute probability space presupposes given a Boolean algebra, and so does Rényi's account in his [1955] and [1964] of a relative probability space. Anxious to prove probability theory ‘autonomous’. Popper supplied in his [1955] and [1957] accounts of probability spaces of which Boolean algebras are not and [1957] accounts of probability spaces of which fields are not prerequisites but byproducts instead.1 I review the accounts in question, showing how Popper's issue from and how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Towards a Historical Notion of ‘Turing—the Father of Computer Science’.Edgar G. Daylight - 2015 - History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (3):205-228.
    In the popular imagination, the relevance of Turing's theoretical ideas to people producing actual machines was significant and appreciated by everybody involved in computing from the moment he published his 1936 paper ‘On Computable Numbers’. Careful historians are aware that this popular conception is deeply misleading. We know from previous work by Campbell-Kelly, Aspray, Akera, Olley, Priestley, Daylight, Mounier-Kuhn, Haigh, and others that several computing pioneers, including Aiken, Eckert, Mauchly, and Zuse, did not depend on Turing's 1936 universal-machine concept. Furthermore, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Herbrand semantics, the potential infinite, and ontology-free logic.Theodore Hailperin - 1992 - History and Philosophy of Logic 13 (1):69-90.
    This paper investigates the ontological presuppositions of quantifier logic. It is seen that the actual infinite, although present in the usual completeness proofs, is not needed for a proper semantic foundation. Additionally, quantifier logic can be given an adequate formulation in which neither the notion of individual nor that of a predicate appears.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the Mathematical Foundations of Syntactic Structures.Geoffrey K. Pullum - 2011 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 20 (3):277-296.
    Chomsky’s highly influential Syntactic Structures ( SS ) has been much praised its originality, explicitness, and relevance for subsequent cognitive science. Such claims are greatly overstated. SS contains no proof that English is beyond the power of finite state description (it is not clear that Chomsky ever gave a sound mathematical argument for that claim). The approach advocated by SS springs directly out of the work of the mathematical logician Emil Post on formalizing proof, but few linguists are aware of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)On post's canonical systems.Raymond M. Smullyan - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (1):55-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Programs, grammars and arguments: A personal view of some connections between computation, language and logic.J. Lambek - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (3):312-328.
    As an undergraduate I was taught to multiply two numbers with the help of log tables, using the formulaHaving graduated to teach calculus to Engineers, I learned that log tables were to be replaced by slide rules. It was then that Imade the fateful decision that there was no need for me to learn how to use this tedious device, as I could always rely on the students to perform the necessary computations. In the course of time, slide rules were (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How are Concepts of Infinity Acquired?Kazimierz Trzęsicki - 2015 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 40 (1):179-217.
    Concepts of infinity have been subjects of dispute since antiquity. The main problems of this paper are: is the mind able to acquire a concept of infinity? and: how are concepts of infinity acquired? The aim of this paper is neither to say what the meanings of the word “infinity” are nor what infinity is and whether it exists. However, those questions will be mentioned, but only in necessary extent.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An interpretation of logical formulas.Jean A. Phillips - 1959 - Theoria 25 (3):158-172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Strict implication, deducibility and the deduction theorem.Ruth Barcan Marcus - 1953 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (3):234-236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Algebraic semantics for modal logics I.E. J. Lemmon - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):46-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Deductive completeness.Kosta Došen - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (3):243-283.
    This is an exposition of Lambek's strengthening and generalization of the deduction theorem in categories related to intuitionistic propositional logic. Essential notions of category theory are introduced so as to yield a simple reformulation of Lambek's Functional Completeness Theorem, from which its main consequences can be readily drawn. The connections of the theorem with combinatory logic, and with modal and substructural logics, are briefly considered at the end.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • From Curry to Haskell.Felice Cardone - 2020 - Philosophy and Technology 34 (1):57-74.
    We expose some basic elements of a style of programming supported by functional languages like Haskell by relating them to a coherent set of notions and techniques from Curry’s work in combinatory logic and formal systems, and their algebraic and categorical interpretations. Our account takes the form of a commentary to a simple fragment of Haskell code attempting to isolate the conceptual sources of the linguistic abstractions involved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark