Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Penrose's Platonism.James Higginbotham - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):667-668.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Thought Experiments, Formalization, and Disagreement.Sören Häggqvist - 2019 - Topoi 38 (4):801-810.
    In the last decade, philosophers have offered a number of proposals concerning the logical form of hypothetical cases, or thought experiments, as these are used for purposes of testing philosophical claims. In this paper, I discuss what the desiderata for a formal proposal are. Employing a comparison with general philosophy of science, I suggest that one important desideratum is to highlight recurrent patterns of disagreement surrounding cases. I advocate a proposal in propositional modal logic which, I argue, better meets this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Preserving a combat commander’s moral agency: The Vincennes Incident as a Chinese Room.Patrick Chisan Hew - 2016 - Ethics and Information Technology 18 (3):227-235.
    We argue that a command and control system can undermine a commander’s moral agency if it causes him/her to process information in a purely syntactic manner, or if it precludes him/her from ascertaining the truth of that information. Our case is based on the resemblance between a commander’s circumstances and the protagonist in Searle’s Chinese Room, together with a careful reading of Aristotle’s notions of ‘compulsory’ and ‘ignorance’. We further substantiate our case by considering the Vincennes Incident, when the crew (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Joseph F. Rychlak, artificial intelligence and human reason: A teleological critique. [REVIEW]Marek Hetmański - 1999 - Minds and Machines 9 (3):421-424.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Machines and metaphors: Challenges for the detection, interpretation and production of metaphors by computer programs.Jacob Hesse - 2023 - Theoria 89 (5):607-624.
    Powerful transformer models based on neural networks such as GPT-4 have enabled huge progress in natural language processing. This paper identifies three challenges for computer programs dealing with metaphors. First, the phenomenon of Twice-Apt-Metaphors shows that metaphorical interpretations do not have to be triggered by syntactical, semantic or pragmatic tensions. The detection of these metaphors seems to involve a sense of aesthetic pleasure or a higher-order theory of mind, both of which are difficult to implement into computer programs. Second, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Searle's regimen for rediscovering the mind.Jeffrey Hershfield - 1997 - Dialogue 36 (2):361-374.
    Like Wittgenstein, John Searle believes that much of analytic philosophy—especially the philosophy of mind—is founded on confusion and falsehood. Unlike Wittgenstein, he does not consider this condition to be endemic to philosophy. As a result, Searle's dual goals in The Rediscovery of the Mind are to rid the philosophy of mind of the fundamental confusions that plague it, and to set the field on the path toward genuine progress. Thus, the book opens with a chapter entitled “What's Wrong with the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Penrose on What Scientists Know.Rubén Herce - 2016 - Foundations of Science 21 (4):679-694.
    This paper presents an analysis and critique of Roger Penrose’s epistemological, methodological, and ontological positions. The analysis is relevant not only because Penrose is an influential scientist, but also because of the particular traits of his thought. These traits are directly connected with his background and approach to science: ontological and epistemological realism, mathematical Platonism, emphasis on the continuities of science, epistemological inclusiveness and essential openness of science, the role of common sense, emphasis on the connection between science, ethics, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Non-locality of the phenomenon of consciousness according to Roger Penrose.Rubén Herce - 2016 - Dialogo 3 (2):127-134.
    Roger Penrose is known for his proposals, in collaboration with Stuart Hameroff, for quantum action in the brain. These proposals, which are still recent, have a prior, less known basis, which will be studied in the following work. First, the paper situates the framework from which a mathematical physicist like Penrose proposes to speak about consciousness. Then it shows how he understands the possible relationships between computation and consciousness and what criticism from other authors he endorses, to conclude by explaining (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Measuring universal intelligence: Towards an anytime intelligence test.José Hernández-Orallo & David L. Dowe - 2010 - Artificial Intelligence 174 (18):1508-1539.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Computer models solving intelligence test problems: Progress and implications.José Hernández-Orallo, Fernando Martínez-Plumed, Ute Schmid, Michael Siebers & David L. Dowe - 2016 - Artificial Intelligence 230 (C):74-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Creating in Our Own Image: Artificial Intelligence and the Image of God.Noreen Herzfeld - 2002 - Zygon 37 (2):303-316.
    There is remarkable convergence between twentieth‐century interpretations of the image of God (imago Dei), what it means for human beings to be created in God's image, and approaches toward creating in our own image in the field of artificial intelligence (AI). Both fields have viewed the intersection between God and humanity or humanity and computers in terms of either (1) a property or set of properties such as intelligence, (2) the functions we engage in or are capable of, or (3) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Species intelligence: Hazards of structural parallels.Robert W. Hendersen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):78-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chauvinism and science: Another reply to Shannon.Tracy B. Henley - 1990 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 20 (1):93–95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • But what is the substance of connectionist representation?James Hendler - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):496-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychopathology and the discontinuity of conscious experience.David R. Hemsley - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):683-684.
    It is accepted that “primary awareness” may emerge from the integration of two classes of information. It is unclear, however, why this cannot take place within the comparator rather than in conjunction with feedback to the perceptual systems. The model has plausibility in relation to the continuity of conscious experience in the normal waking state and may be extended to encompass certain aspects of the “sense of self” which are frequently disrupted in psychotic patients.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the mind in the brain in contemporary computational neuroscience?Meir Hemmo & Orly Shenker - 2023 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 100 (C):64-80.
    According to contemporary computational neuroscience the mental is associated with computations implemented in the brain. We analyze in physical terms based on recent results in the foundations of statistical mechanics two well-known (independent) problems that arise for this approach: the problem of multiple-computations and the problem of multiple-realization. We show that within the computational theory of the mind the two problems are insoluble by the physics of the brain. We further show that attempts to solve the problems by the interactions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence: John Preston and Mark Bishop, eds., Views into the Chinese Room: New Essays on Searle and Artificial Intelligence, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2002, xvi + 410, ISBN 0-19-925277-7. [REVIEW]Reese M. Heitner - 2005 - Minds and Machines 15 (1):97-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unraveling introspection.John Heil - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):49-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionality and the explanation of behavior.John Heil - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):146-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Virtual symposium on virtual mind.Patrick Hayes, Stevan Harnad, Donald Perlis & Ned Block - 1992 - Minds and Machines 2 (3):217-238.
    When certain formal symbol systems (e.g., computer programs) are implemented as dynamic physical symbol systems (e.g., when they are run on a computer) their activity can be interpreted at higher levels (e.g., binary code can be interpreted as LISP, LISP code can be interpreted as English, and English can be interpreted as a meaningful conversation). These higher levels of interpretability are called "virtual" systems. If such a virtual system is interpretable as if it had a mind, is such a "virtual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Do Personality Features Influence Our Intuitions of the Mind-Body Problem? A Pilot Study.Marek Havlík, Karolína Mladá, Iveta Fajnerová & Jiří Horáček - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The sense of thinking.Larry Hauser - 1993 - Minds and Machines 3 (1):21-29.
    It will be found that the great majority, given the premiss that thought is not distinct from corporeal motion, take a much more rational line and maintain that thought is the same in the brutes as in us, since they observe all sorts of corporeal motions in them, just as in us. And they will add that the difference, which is merely one of degree, does not imply any essential difference; from this they will be quite justified in concluding that, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Searle's Chinese Box: Debunking the Chinese Room Argument. [REVIEW]Larry Hauser - 1997 - Minds and Machines 7 (2):199-226.
    John Searle's Chinese room argument is perhaps the most influential andwidely cited argument against artificial intelligence (AI). Understood astargeting AI proper – claims that computers can think or do think– Searle's argument, despite its rhetorical flash, is logically andscientifically a dud. Advertised as effective against AI proper, theargument, in its main outlines, is an ignoratio elenchi. It musterspersuasive force fallaciously by indirection fostered by equivocaldeployment of the phrase "strong AI" and reinforced by equivocation on thephrase "causal powers" (at least) equal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is stiffness the mainspring of posture and movement?Z. Hasan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):756-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Why the Self Does Not Extend.Keith Raymond Harris - 2022 - Erkenntnis 87 (6):2645-2659.
    The defensibility of the extended mind thesis (EMT) is often thought to hinge on the possibility of extended selves. I argue that the self cannot extend and consider the ramifications of this finding, especially for EMT. After an overview of EMT and the supposed cruciality of the extended self to the defensibility of the former thesis, I outline several lines of argument in support of the possibility of extended selves. Each line of argument appeals to a different account of diachronic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Whose (Extended) Mind Is It, Anyway?Keith Harris - 2019 - Erkenntnis 86 (6):1599-1613.
    Presentations of the extended mind thesis are often ambiguous between two versions of that thesis. According to the first, the extension of mind consists in the supervenience base of human individuals’ mental states extending beyond the skull and into artifacts in the outside world. According to a second interpretation, human individuals sometimes participate in broader cognitive systems that are themselves the subjects of extended mental states. This ambiguity, I suggest, contributes to several of the most serious criticisms of the extended (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What is the intentional stance?Gilbert Harman - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):515.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the nature of programs, simulations, and organisms.R. J. Harvey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):741-742.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Other bodies, other minds: A machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem. [REVIEW]Stevan Harnad - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (1):43-54.
    Explaining the mind by building machines with minds runs into the other-minds problem: How can we tell whether any body other than our own has a mind when the only way to know is by being the other body? In practice we all use some form of Turing Test: If it can do everything a body with a mind can do such that we can't tell them apart, we have no basis for doubting it has a mind. But what is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Knowledge and the relativity of information.Gilbert Harman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):72-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Intentionality: Some distinctions.Gilbert Harman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):607-608.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is pain overt behavior?Gilbert Harman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):61-61.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Henry Holland on the hypothesis of duality of mind.Lauren Julius Harris - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):732.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Group minds as extended minds.Keith Raymond Harris - 2020 - Philosophical Explorations 23 (3):1-17.
    Despite clear overlap between the study of extended minds and the study of group minds, these research programs have largely been carried out independently. Moreover, whereas proponents of the extended mind thesis straightforwardly advocate the view that there are, literally, extended mental states, proponents of the group mind thesis tend to be more circumspect. Even those who advocate for some version of the thesis that groups are the subjects of mental states often concede that this thesis is true only in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Force and stiffness: Further considerations.Nigel Harvey & Kerry Greer - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):547-548.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • First-person current.Paul L. Harris - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):48-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Computation is just interpretable symbol manipulation; cognition isn't.Stevan Harnad - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (4):379-90.
    Computation is interpretable symbol manipulation. Symbols are objects that are manipulated on the basis of rules operating only on theirshapes, which are arbitrary in relation to what they can be interpreted as meaning. Even if one accepts the Church/Turing Thesis that computation is unique, universal and very near omnipotent, not everything is a computer, because not everything can be given a systematic interpretation; and certainly everything can''t be givenevery systematic interpretation. But even after computers and computation have been successfully distinguished (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Codes, communication and cognition.Stevan Harnad - 2019 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 42.
    Brette criticizes the notion of neural coding because it seems to entail that neural signals need to “decoded” by or for some receiver in the head. If that were so, then neural coding would indeed be homuncular, requiring an entity to decipher the code. But I think Brette's plea to think instead in terms of complex, interactive causal throughput is preaching to the converted. Turing has already shown the way. In any case, the metaphor of neural coding has little to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A too simple view of population genetics.Daniel L. Hartl - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):13-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What connectionist models learn: Learning and representation in connectionist networks.Stephen José Hanson & David J. Burr - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):471-489.
    Connectionist models provide a promising alternative to the traditional computational approach that has for several decades dominated cognitive science and artificial intelligence, although the nature of connectionist models and their relation to symbol processing remains controversial. Connectionist models can be characterized by three general computational features: distinct layers of interconnected units, recursive rules for updating the strengths of the connections during learning, and “simple” homogeneous computing elements. Using just these three features one can construct surprisingly elegant and powerful models of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • On the obvious treatment of connectionism.Stephen José Hanson - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):38-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning and representation: Tensions at the interface.Steven José Hanson - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):511-518.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intencionalidad sin naturalismo biológico.Ivar Hannikainen - 2011 - Revista de Filosofía (Madrid) 36 (1):139-153.
    The Chinese Room argument is a variant of Turing’s test which enables Searle to defend his biological naturalism, according to which computation is neither sufficient nor constitutive of the mind. In this paper, I examine both strands of his anticomputationalist stance, argue that computation is constitutive of natural language understanding and suggest a path toward the physicalist reduction of intentionality for propositional speech acts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From mimetic to mythic culture: Stimulus equivalence effects and prelinguistic cognition.P. J. Hampson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):763-763.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Artificial consciousness and the consciousness-attention dissociation.Harry Haroutioun Haladjian & Carlos Montemayor - 2016 - Consciousness and Cognition 45:210-225.
    Artificial Intelligence is at a turning point, with a substantial increase in projects aiming to implement sophisticated forms of human intelligence in machines. This research attempts to model specific forms of intelligence through brute-force search heuristics and also reproduce features of human perception and cognition, including emotions. Such goals have implications for artificial consciousness, with some arguing that it will be achievable once we overcome short-term engineering challenges. We believe, however, that phenomenal consciousness cannot be implemented in machines. This becomes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The “culturgen”: Science or science fiction?C. R. Hallpike - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):12-13.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mythos and logos.John Halverson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):762-762.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Moral Responsibility of Robots and Hybrid Agents.Raul Hakli & Pekka Mäkelä - 2019 - The Monist 102 (2):259-275.
    We study whether robots can satisfy the conditions of an agent fit to be held morally responsible, with a focus on autonomy and self-control. An analogy between robots and human groups enables us to modify arguments concerning collective responsibility for studying questions of robot responsibility. We employ Mele’s history-sensitive account of autonomy and responsibility to argue that even if robots were to have all the capacities required of moral agency, their history would deprive them from autonomy in a responsibility-undermining way. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • A Default‐Oriented Theory of Procedural Semantics.Robert F. Hadley - 1989 - Cognitive Science 13 (1):107-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Expose hidden assumptions in network theory.Karl Haberlandt - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):495-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations