Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The contents of consciousness: A neuropsychological conjecture.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):659-76.
    Drawing on previous models of anxiety, intermediate memory, the positive symptoms of schizophrenia, and goal-directed behaviour, a neuropsychological hypothesis is proposed for the generation of the contents of consciousness. It is suggested that these correspond to the outputs of a comparator that, on a moment-by-moment basis, compares the current state of the organism's perceptual world with a predicted state. An outline is given of the information-processing functions of the comparator system and of the neural systems which mediate them. The hypothesis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Guilty consciousness.George Graham - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):255-256.
    Should we distinguish between access and phenomenal consciousness? Block says yes and that various pathologies of consciousness support and clarify the distinction. The commentary charge that the distinction is neither supported nor clarified by the clinical data. It recommends an alternative reading of the data and urges Block to clarify the distinction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • From selves to systems: on the intrapersonal and intraneural dynamics of decision making.James Grayot - 2019 - Journal of Economic Methodology 26 (3):208-227.
    ABSTRACTNew trends in behavioral decision research see researchers attempting to integrate multiple-self models of behavioral economics with dual-process and dual-system theories of cognitive psych...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Enhanced probing of attentional bias: The independence of anxiety-linked selectivity in attentional engagement with and disengagement from negative information.Ben Grafton & Colin MacLeod - 2014 - Cognition and Emotion 28 (7):1287-1302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Dual Process Theories in Behavioral Economics and Neuroeconomics: a Critical Review.James D. Grayot - 2020 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 11 (1):105-136.
    Despite their popularity, dual process accounts of human reasoning and decision-making have come under intense scrutiny in recent years. Cognitive scientists and philosophers alike have come to question the theoretical foundations of the ‘standard view’ of dual process theory and have challenged the validity and relevance of evidence in support of it. Moreover, attempts to modify and refine dual process theory in light of these challenges have generated additional concerns about its applicability and refutability as a scientific theory. With these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Consciousness and its (dis)contents.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):703-722.
    The first claim in the target article was that there is as yet no transparent, causal account of the relations between consciousness and brain-and-behaviour. That claim remains firm. The second claim was that the contents of consciousness consist, psychologically, of the outputs of a comparator system; the third consisted of a description of the brain mechanisms proposed to instantiate the comparator. In order to defend these claims against criticism, it has been necessary to clarify the distinction between consciousness-as-such and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Visual attention to features by associative learning.Davood G. Gozli, Joshua B. Moskowitz & Jay Pratt - 2014 - Cognition 133 (2):488-501.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The possible futility of neuropsychology.Yonatan Goshen-Gottstein - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):448-449.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transitions in concept acquisition: Using the hand to read the mind.Susan Goldin-Meadow, Martha Wagner Alibali & R. Breckinridge Church - 1993 - Psychological Review 100 (2):279-297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • The Education of Perception.Robert L. Goldstone, David H. Landy & Ji Y. Son - 2010 - Topics in Cognitive Science 2 (2):265-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Statistical rationality.Richard M. Golden - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):35-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Reuniting perception and conception.Robert L. Goldstone & Lawrence W. Barsalou - 1998 - Cognition 65 (2-3):231-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • A Transcranial Stimulation Intervention to Support Flow State Induction.Joshua Gold & Joseph Ciorciari - 2019 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 13:461259.
    Background: Flow states are considered a positive, subjective experience during an optimal balance between skills and task demands. Previously, experimentally induced flow experiences have relied solely on adaptive tasks. Objective: To investigate whether cathodal transcranial direct current stimulation (tDCS) over the left dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (DLPFC) area and anodal tDCS over the right parietal cortex area during video game play will promote an increased experience of flow states. Methods: Two studies had participants play Tetris or first-person shooter (FPS) video games (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are rules and instances subserved by separate systems?Robert L. Goldstone & John K. Kruschke - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):405-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A cognitive theory without inductive learning.Lev Goldfarb - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):446-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Fodor's holism.Clark Glymour - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):15-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Modularity: Contextual interactions and the tractability of nonmodular systems.Sam Glucksberg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):14-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • More in the early selection process than the attentional-trace mechanism?Marie-Hélène Giard - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):240-241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Are Acquired Search-Guiding Context Memories Resistant to Updating?Thomas Geyer, Werner Seitz, Artyom Zinchenko, Hermann J. Müller & Markus Conci - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Looking for goal-relevant objects in our various environments is one of the most ubiquitous tasks the human visual system has to accomplish. Visual search is guided by a number of separable selective-attention mechanisms that can be categorized as bottom-up driven – guidance by salient physical properties of the current stimuli – or top-down controlled – guidance by observers' “online” knowledge of search-critical object properties. In addition, observers' expectations based on past experience also play also a significant role in goal-directed visual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Seeing through the eyes of anxious individuals: An investigation of anxiety-related interpretations of emotional expressions.Claudia Gebhardt & Kristin Mitte - 2014 - Cognition and Emotion 28 (8):1367-1381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The centrality of modules.Howard Gardner - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):12-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Memory with and without recollective experience.John M. Gardiner - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):678-679.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Must we solve the binding problem in neural hardware?James W. Garson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):459-460.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Executive Functions and the Improvement of Thinking Abilities: The Intervention in Reading Comprehension.Juan A. García-Madruga, Isabel Gómez-Veiga & José Ó Vila - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The effects of learning two languages on levels of metalinguistic awareness.Sylvia Joseph Galambos & Susan Goldin-Meadow - 1990 - Cognition 34 (1):1-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A modular sense of place?C. R. Gallistel & Ken Cheng - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):11-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anosognosia, denial of illness and the right hemisphere dominance for emotions: Some historical and clinical notes.Guido Gainotti - 2018 - Consciousness and Cognition 58:44-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Choice models and realistic ontologies: three challenges to neuro-psychological modellers.Roberto Fumagalli - 2016 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 6 (1):145-164.
    Choice modellers are frequently criticized for failing to provide accurate representations of the neuro-psychological substrates of decisions. Several authors maintain that recent neuro-psychological findings enable choice modellers to overcome this alleged shortcoming. Some advocate a realistic interpretation of neuro-psychological models of choice, according to which these models posit sub-personal entities with specific neuro-psychological counterparts and characterize those entities accurately. In this article, I articulate and defend three complementary arguments to demonstrate that, contrary to emerging consensus, even the best available neuro-psychological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Skill and motor control: intelligence all the way down.Ellen Fridland - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (6):1-22.
    When reflecting on the nature of skilled action, it is easy to fall into familiar dichotomies such that one construes the flexibility and intelligence of skill at the level of intentional states while characterizing the automatic motor processes that constitute motor skill execution as learned but fixed, invariant, bottom-up, brute-causal responses. In this essay, I will argue that this picture of skilled, automatic, motor processes is overly simplistic. Specifically, I will argue that an adequate account of the learned motor routines (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Mental structure in the psychoses: The only hope for a neuropsychology of schizophrenia.Chris Frith - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):447-448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Unified theories of cognition good strategy?Nico H. Frijda & Jan Elshout - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):445-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness is for other people.Chris Frith - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):682-683.
    Gray has expanded his account of schizophrenia to explain consciousness as well. His theory explains neither phenomenon adequately because he treats individual minds in isolation. The primary function of consciousness is to permit high level interactions with other conscious beings. The key symptoms of schizophrenia reflect a failure of this mechanism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Automatically minded.Ellen Fridland - 2017 - Synthese 194 (11).
    It is not rare in philosophy and psychology to see theorists fall into dichotomous thinking about mental phenomena. On one side of the dichotomy there are processes that I will label “unintelligent.” These processes are thought to be unconscious, implicit, automatic, unintentional, involuntary, procedural, and non-cognitive. On the other side, there are “intelligent” processes that are conscious, explicit, controlled, intentional, voluntary, declarative, and cognitive. Often, if a process or behavior is characterized by one of the features from either of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Dynamic systems and the “subsymbolic level”.Walter J. Freeman - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):33-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Deconstruction of neural data yields biologically implausible periodic oscillations.Walter J. Freeman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):458-459.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Connectionism and the study of language.R. Freidin - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dual-Process and Dual-System Theories of Reasoning.Keith Frankish - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (10):914-926.
    Dual-process theories hold that there are two distinct processing modes available for many cognitive tasks: one that is fast, automatic and non-conscious, and another that is slow, controlled and conscious. Typically, cognitive biases are attributed to type 1 processes, which are held to be heuristic or associative, and logical responses to type 2 processes, which are characterised as rule-based or analytical. Dual-system theories go further and assign these two types of process to two separate reasoning systems, System 1 and System (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Selective Processing of Threatening Words in Anxiety: The Role of Awareness.Elaine Fox - 1996 - Cognition and Emotion 10 (5):449-480.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • An operational definition of conscious awareness must be responsible to subjective experience.Carol A. Fowler - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):33-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Dream processing.David Foulkes - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):678-678.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On seeking the mythical fountain of consciousness.Jeffrey Foss - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):682-682.
    Because consciousness has an organizational, or functional, center, Gray supposes that there must be a corresponding physical center in the brain. He proposes further that since this center generates consciousness, ablating it would eliminate consciousness, while leaving behavior intact. But the center of consciousness is simply the product of the functional linkages among sensory input, memory, inner speech, and so on, and behavior.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Special purpose computation: All is not one.K. I. Forster - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):9-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Finding the right tools for the task: An intelligent approach to the study of intelligence.Martin E. Ford - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (2):291-292.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Long-term memory-based control of attention in multi-step tasks requires working memory: evidence from domain-specific interference.Rebecca M. Foerster, Elena Carbone & Werner X. Schneider - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Module or muddle?Janet Dean Fodor - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):7-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Precis of the modularity of mind.Jerry A. Fodor - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):1-42.
    The Modularity of Mind proposes an alternative to the or view of cognitive architecture that has dominated several decades of cognitive science. Whereas interactionism stresses the continuity of perceptual and cognitive processes, modularity theory argues for their distinctness. It is argued, in particular, that the apparent plausibility of New Look theorizing derives from the failure to distinguish between the (correct) claim that perceptual processes are inferential and the (dubious) claim that they are unencapsidated, that is, that they are arbitrarily sensitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   276 citations  
  • Reply module.Jerry A. Fodor - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):33-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The modularity of consciousness.Owen Flanagan - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (3):446-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowing and knowing you know: Better methods or better models?Ira Fischler - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):32-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consistent attending versus consistent responding in visual search: Task versus component consistency in automatic processing development.Arthur D. Fisk & Walter Schneider - 1984 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 22 (4):330-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation