Switch to: References

Citations of:

Mathematical Logic

Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3):376-376 (2001)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. (1 other version)A Note on the Interpolation Theorem in First Order Logic.George Weaver - 1982 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 28 (14-18):215-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • (1 other version)An Application of Rank‐Forcing to ω 1 ‐Categoricity.H. Peter Tuschik - 1980 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 26 (14-18):237-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Logic in the 1930s: Type Theory and Model Theory.Georg Schiemer & Erich H. Reck - 2013 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 19 (4):433-472.
    In historical discussions of twentieth-century logic, it is typically assumed that model theory emerged within the tradition that adopted first-order logic as the standard framework. Work within the type-theoretic tradition, in the style ofPrincipia Mathematica, tends to be downplayed or ignored in this connection. Indeed, the shift from type theory to first-order logic is sometimes seen as involving a radical break that first made possible the rise of modern model theory. While comparing several early attempts to develop the semantics of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Abstraction Reconceived.J. P. Studd - 2016 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 67 (2):579-615.
    Neologicists have sought to ground mathematical knowledge in abstraction. One especially obstinate problem for this account is the bad company problem. The leading neologicist strategy for resolving this problem is to attempt to sift the good abstraction principles from the bad. This response faces a dilemma: the system of ‘good’ abstraction principles either falls foul of the Scylla of inconsistency or the Charybdis of being unable to recover a modest portion of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with its intended generality. This article (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Um panorama da teoria aristotélica do silogismo categórico.Evandro Luís Gomes & Itala Maria L. D'Ottaviano - 2010 - CLE E-Prints 10 (4):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Morita Equivalence.Thomas William Barrett & Hans Halvorson - 2016 - Review of Symbolic Logic 9 (3):556-582.
    Logicians and philosophers of science have proposed various formal criteria for theoretical equivalence. In this paper, we examine two such proposals: definitional equivalence and categorical equivalence. In order to show precisely how these two well-known criteria are related to one another, we investigate an intermediate criterion called Morita equivalence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • (1 other version)Iterations of satisfaction classes and models of peano arithmetic.Roman Murawski - 1992 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 38 (1):59-84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Fixed points and diagonal method.Maurizio Negri - 1990 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 36 (4):319-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Some results on bounded truth-table degrees.Angel V. Ditchev - 1990 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 36 (3):263-271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)The hilbert type axiomatization of some three-valued propositional logic.Andrzej Zbrzezny - 1990 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 36 (5):415-421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Elimination of Quantifiers on Łukasiewicz Logics.Néstor G. Martínez - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (1):15-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Elimination of Quantifiers on Łukasiewicz Logics.Néstor G. Martínez - 1989 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 35 (1):15-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)A Free‐Variable Theory of Primitive Recursive Arithmetic.Daniel G. Schwartz - 1987 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 33 (2):147-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Untersuchungen zur Friedmanschen Theorie der Prädikate.Martin Kühnrich - 1986 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 32 (1-5):29-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Classes Closed Under Substructures and Direct Limits.Paul C. Eklof - 1977 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 23 (27-30):427-430.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The Inequivalence of Two Well-Known Notions of Randomness for Binary Sequences.Thomas Herzog & James C. Owings - 1976 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 22 (1):385-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Elimination of Cardinality Quantifiers.H. P. Tuschik - 1982 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 28 (4‐7):75-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Criteria of Empirical Significance: Foundations, Relations, Applications.Sebastian Lutz - 2012 - Dissertation, Utrecht University
    This dissertation consists of three parts. Part I is a defense of an artificial language methodology in philosophy and a historical and systematic defense of the logical empiricists' application of an artificial language methodology to scientific theories. These defenses provide a justification for the presumptions of a host of criteria of empirical significance, which I analyze, compare, and develop in part II. On the basis of this analysis, in part III I use a variety of criteria to evaluate the scientific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • An Intensional Type Theory: Motivation and Cut-Elimination.Paul C. Gilmore - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):383-400.
    By the theory TT is meant the higher order predicate logic with the following recursively defined types: 1 is the type of individuals and [] is the type of the truth values: [$\tau_l$,..., $\tau_n$] is the type of the predicates with arguments of the types $\tau_l$,..., $\tau_n$. The theory ITT described in this paper is an intensional version of TT. The types of ITT are the same as the types of TT, but the membership of the type 1 of individuals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Formalization, primitive concepts, and purity: Formalization, primitive concepts, and purity.John T. Baldwin - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):87-128.
    We emphasize the role of the choice of vocabulary in formalization of a mathematical area and remark that this is a particular preoccupation of logicians. We use this framework to discuss Kennedy’s notion of ‘formalism freeness’ in the context of various schools in model theory. Then we clarify some of the mathematical issues in recent discussions of purity in the proof of the Desargues proposition. We note that the conclusion of ‘spatial content’ from the Desargues proposition involves arguments which are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • (1 other version)Generalizations of Kochen and Specker's theorem and the effectiveness of Gleason's theorem.Itamar Pitowsky - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35 (2):177-194.
    Kochen and Specker’s theorem can be seen as a consequence of Gleason’s theorem and logical compactness. Similar compactness arguments lead to stronger results about finite sets of rays in Hilbert space, which we also prove by a direct construction. Finally, we demonstrate that Gleason’s theorem itself has a constructive proof, based on a generic, finite, effectively generated set of rays, on which every quantum state can be approximated. r 2003 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theory evolution and reference kinematics.Bernhard Lauth - 1991 - Synthese 88 (3):279 - 307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intensionality and the gödel theorems.David D. Auerbach - 1985 - Philosophical Studies 48 (3):337--51.
    Philosophers of language have drawn on metamathematical results in varied ways. Extensionalist philosophers have been particularly impressed with two, not unrelated, facts: the existence, due to Frege/Tarski, of a certain sort of semantics, and the seeming absence of intensional contexts from mathematical discourse. The philosophical import of these facts is at best murky. Extensionalists will emphasize the success and clarity of the model theoretic semantics; others will emphasize the relative poverty of the mathematical idiom; still others will question the aptness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Ramsey eliminability and the testability of scientific theories.Herbert A. Simon & Guy J. Groen - 1973 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24 (4):367-380.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Existentially closed structures.H. Simmons - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (2):293-310.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Why Popper's basic statements are not falsifiable. some paradoxes in Popper's “logic of scientific discovery”.Gerhard Schurz & Georg J. W. Dorn - 1988 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 19 (1):124-143.
    ENGLISH ABSTRACT: Basic statements play a central role in Popper's "The Logic of Scientific Discovery", since they permit a distinction between empirical and non-empirical theories. A theory is empirical iff it consists of falsifiable statements, and statements (of any kind) are falsifiable iff they are inconsistent with at least one basic statement. Popper obviously presupposes that basic statements are themselves empirical and hence falsifiable; at any rate, he claims several times that they are falsifiable. In this paper we prove that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ordinals connected with formal theories for transfinitely iterated inductive definitions.W. Pohlers - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (2):161-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Russell’s Notion of Scope.Saul A. Kripke - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):1005-1037.
    Despite the renown of ‘On Denoting’, much criticism has ignored or misconstrued Russell's treatment of scope, particularly in intensional, but also in extensional contexts. This has been rectified by more recent commentators, yet it remains largely unnoticed that the examples Russell gives of scope distinctions are questionable or inconsistent with his own philosophy. Nevertheless, Russell is right: scope does matter in intensional contexts. In Principia Mathematica, Russell proves a metatheorem to the effect that the scope of a single occurrence of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • The perfect set theorem and definable wellorderings of the continuum.Alexander S. Kechris - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (4):630-634.
    Let Γ be a collection of relations on the reals and let M be a set of reals. We call M a perfect set basis for Γ if every set in Γ with parameters from M which is not totally included in M contains a perfect subset with code in M. A simple elementary proof is given of the following result (assuming mild regularity conditions on Γ and M): If M is a perfect set basis for Γ, the field of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Uniform Upper Bounds on Ideals of Turing Degrees.Harold T. Hodes - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (3):601-612.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Abstract Beth Definability in Institutions.Marius Petria & Răzvan Diaconescu - 2006 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (3):1002 - 1028.
    This paper studies definability within the theory of institutions, a version of abstract model theory that emerged in computing science studies of software specification and semantics. We generalise the concept of definability to arbitrary logics, formalised as institutions, and we develop three general definability results. One generalises the classical Beth theorem by relying on the interpolation properties of the institution. Another relies on a meta Birkhoff axiomatizability property of the institution and constitutes a source for many new actual definability results, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Functional interpretation and inductive definitions.Jeremy Avigad & Henry Towsner - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (4):1100-1120.
    Extending Gödel's Dialectica interpretation, we provide a functional interpretation of classical theories of positive arithmetic inductive definitions, reducing them to theories of finite-type functionals defined using transfinite recursion on well-founded trees.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Issues in the foundations of science, I: Languages, structures, and models.Newton C. A. da Costa, Décio Krause & Otávio Bueno - unknown
    In this first paper of a series of works on the foundations of science, we examine the significance of logical and mathematical frameworks used in foundational studies. In particular, we emphasize the distinction between the order of a language and the order of a structure to prevent confusing models of scientific theories with first-order structures, and which are studied in standard model theory. All of us are, of course, bound to make abuses of language even in putatively precise contexts. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Carnap’s Problem, Definability and Compositionality.Pedro del Valle-Inclán - forthcoming - Journal of Philosophical Logic:1-26.
    In his Formalization of Logic (1943) Carnap pointed out that there are non-normal interpretations of classical logic: non-standard interpretations of the connectives and quantifiers that are consistent with the classical consequence relation of a language. Different ways around the problem have been proposed. In a recent paper, Bonnay and Westerståhl argue that the key to a solution is imposing restrictions on the type of interpretation we take into account. More precisely, they claim that if we restrict attention to interpretations that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Steps Towards a Minimalist Account of Numbers.Thomas Schindler - 2021 - Mind 131 (523):863-891.
    This paper outlines an account of numbers based on the numerical equivalence schema, which consists of all sentences of the form ‘#x.Fx=n if and only if ∃nx Fx’, where # is the number-of operator and ∃n is defined in standard Russellian fashion. In the first part of the paper, I point out some analogies between the NES and the T-schema for truth. In light of these analogies, I formulate a minimalist account of numbers, based on the NES, which strongly parallels (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Against Fregean Quantification.Bryan Pickel & Brian Rabern - 2023 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 9 (37):971-1007.
    There are two dominant approaches to quantification: the Fregean and the Tarskian. While the Tarskian approach is standard and familiar, deep conceptual objections have been pressed against its employment of variables as genuine syntactic and semantic units. Because they do not explicitly rely on variables, Fregean approaches are held to avoid these worries. The apparent result is that the Fregean can deliver something that the Tarskian is unable to, namely a compositional semantic treatment of quantification centered on truth and reference. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • D avid B ostock . Philosophy of mathematics: An introduction.James Robert Brown - 2010 - Philosophia Mathematica 18 (1):127-129.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Ontological Import of Adding Proper Classes.Alfredo Roque Freire & Rodrigo de Alvarenga Freire - 2019 - Manuscrito 42 (2):85-112.
    In this article, we analyse the ontological import of adding classes to set theories. We assume that this increment is well represented by going from ZF system to NBG. We thus consider the standard techniques of reducing one system to the other. Novak proved that from a model of ZF we can build a model of NBG (and vice versa), while Shoenfield have shown that from a proof in NBG of a set-sentence we can generate a proof in ZF of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quantification and Paradox.Edward Ferrier - 2018 - Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst
    I argue that absolutism, the view that absolutely unrestricted quantification is possible, is to blame for both the paradoxes that arise in naive set theory and variants of these paradoxes that arise in plural logic and in semantics. The solution is restrictivism, the view that absolutely unrestricted quantification is not possible. -/- It is generally thought that absolutism is true and that restrictivism is not only false, but inexpressible. As a result, the paradoxes are blamed, not on illicit quantification, but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mathematics and Its Applications, A Transcendental-Idealist Perspective.Jairo José da Silva - 2017 - Cham: Springer.
    This monograph offers a fresh perspective on the applicability of mathematics in science. It explores what mathematics must be so that its applications to the empirical world do not constitute a mystery. In the process, readers are presented with a new version of mathematical structuralism. The author details a philosophy of mathematics in which the problem of its applicability, particularly in physics, in all its forms can be explained and justified. Chapters cover: mathematics as a formal science, mathematical ontology: what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Models and theories I: The semantic view revisited.Chuang Liu - 1997 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 11 (2):147 – 164.
    The paper, as Part I of a two-part series, argues for a hybrid formulation of the semantic view of scientific theories. For stage-setting, it first reviews the elements of the model theory in mathematical logic (on whose foundation the semantic view rests), the syntactic and the semantic view, and the different notions of models used in the practice of science. The paper then argues for an integration of the notions into the semantic view, and thereby offers a hybrid semantic view, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)The philosophy of computer science.Raymond Turner - 2013 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Bounded Induction and Satisfaction Classes.Henryk Kotlarski - 1986 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 32 (31-34):531-544.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • A Methodology for Teaching Logic-Based Skills to Mathematics Students.Arnold Cusmariu - 2016 - Symposion: Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences 3 (3):259-292.
    Mathematics textbooks teach logical reasoning by example, a practice started by Euclid; while logic textbooks treat logic as a subject in its own right without practical application to mathematics. Stuck in the middle are students seeking mathematical proficiency and educators seeking to provide it. To assist them, the article explains in practical detail how to teach logic-based skills such as: making mathematical reasoning fully explicit; moving from step to step in a mathematical proof in logically correct ways; and checking to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Countable homogeneous relational structures and ℵ0-categorical theories.C. Ward Henson - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):494 - 500.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the theory of exponential fields.Bernd I. Dahn & Helmut Wolter - 1983 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 29 (9):465-480.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hyperdoctrines, Natural Deduction and the Beck Condition.Robert A. G. Seely - 1983 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 29 (10):505-542.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • New foundations for metascience.David Pearce & Veikko Rantala - 1983 - Synthese 56 (1):1 - 26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • (1 other version)Ein neuer “strukturtyp” Von logikbuch? [REVIEW]Ulrich Nortmann - 1987 - Erkenntnis 27 (1):113 - 145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The mathematical philosophy of Charles Parsons. [REVIEW]J. M. B. Moss - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (4):437-457.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark