Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Note on Gödel, Priest and Naïve Proof.Massimiliano Carrara - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1.
    In the 1951 Gibbs lecture, Gödel asserted his famous dichotomy, where the notion of informal proof is at work. G. Priest developed an argument, grounded on the notion of naïve proof, to the effect that Gödel’s first incompleteness theorem suggests the presence of dialetheias. In this paper, we adopt a plausible ideal notion of naïve proof, in agreement with Gödel’s conception, superseding the criticisms against the usual notion of naïve proof used by real working mathematicians. We explore the connection between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conditional Heresies.Fabrizio Cariani & Simon Goldstein - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (2):251-282.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Paradox and Logical Revision. A Short Introduction.Julien Murzi & Massimiliano Carrara - 2015 - Topoi 34 (1):7-14.
    Logical orthodoxy has it that classical first-order logic, or some extension thereof, provides the right extension of the logical consequence relation. However, together with naïve but intuitive principles about semantic notions such as truth, denotation, satisfaction, and possibly validity and other naïve logical properties, classical logic quickly leads to inconsistency, and indeed triviality. At least since the publication of Kripke’s Outline of a theory of truth , an increasingly popular diagnosis has been to restore consistency, or at least non-triviality, by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Monism: The One True Logic.Stephen Read - 2006 - In David DeVidi & Tim Kenyon (eds.), A Logical Approach to Philosophy: Essays in Memory of Graham Solomon. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Logical pluralism is the claim that different accounts of validity can be equally correct. Beall and Restall have recently defended this position. Validity is a matter of truth-preservation over cases, they say: the conclusion should be true in every case in which the premises are true. Each logic specifies a class of cases, but differs over which cases should be considered. I show that this account of logic is incoherent. Validity indeed is truth-preservation, provided this is properly understood. Once understood, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Hugh maccoll: eine bibliographische erschließung seiner hauptwerke und notizen zu ihrer rezeptionsgeschichte.Shahid Rahman - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (3):165-183.
    The work of Hugh MacColl (1837–1909) suffered the same fate after his death as before it:despite being vaguely alluded to and in part even commended, on the whole it has remained an unknown quantity. Even worse, those of his ideas which have played a decisive role in the history of logic have been credited to his successors; this is especially the case with the definition of strict implication and the first formal development of formal modal logic. This paper takes an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Paraconsistent logic.Graham Priest - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   182 citations  
  • The pure calculus of entailment.Alan Ross Anderson & Nuel D. Belnap - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (1):19-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Variable-Sharing as Relevance.Shawn Standefer - 2024 - In Andrew Tedder, Shawn Standefer & Igor Sedlar (eds.), New Directions in Relevant Logic. Springer.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Mereological Reading of the Dictum de Omni et Nullo.Phil Corkum - forthcoming - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
    When Aristotle introduces the perfect moods, he refers back to the dictum de omni et nullo, a semantic condition for universal affirmations and negations. There recently has been renewed interest in the question whether the dictum validates the assertoric syllogistic. I rehearse evidence that Aristotle provides a mereological semantics for universal affirmations and negations, and note that this semantics entails a nonstandard reading of the dictum, under which the dictum, in the presence of a minimal logical apparatus, indeed validates the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Logical Approach to Philosophy: Essays in Memory of Graham Solomon.David DeVidi & Tim Kenyon (eds.) - 2006 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    Graham Solomon, to whom this collection is dedicated, went into hospital for antibiotic treatment of pneumonia in Oc- ber, 2001. Three days later, on Nov. 1, he died of a massive stroke, at the age of 44. Solomon was well liked by those who got the chance to know him—it was a revelation to?nd out, when helping to sort out his a?airs after his death, how many “friends” he had whom he had actually never met, as his email included correspondence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Relevant entailment and logical ground.Pierre Saint-Germier, Peter Verdée & Pilar Terrés Villalonga - 2024 - Philosophical Studies 181 (9).
    According to an intuitive picture of relevant entailment, an entailment is relevant if all the formulas it contains contribute to its validity. In this paper, we provide a ground-theoretic analysis of this notion of contribution, and as a result of relevant entailment. We build a system of bilateral logical grounding within which we can derive classical entailment and analyze the contribution of premises and conclusions, in terms of a certain type of connection between their respective logical grounds. The resulting framework (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Substructural approaches to paradox: an introduction to the special issue.Elia Zardini - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3):493-525.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A non-transitive relevant implication corresponding to classical logic consequence.Peter Verdée, Inge De Bal & Aleksandra Samonek - 2019 - Australasian Journal of Logic 16 (2):10-40.
    In this paper we first develop a logic independent account of relevant implication. We propose a stipulative denition of what it means for a multiset of premises to relevantly L-imply a multiset of conclusions, where L is a Tarskian consequence relation: the premises relevantly imply the conclusions iff there is an abstraction of the pair such that the abstracted premises L-imply the abstracted conclusions and none of the abstracted premises or the abstracted conclusions can be omitted while still maintaining valid (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Reinflating Logical Consequence.Owen Griffiths - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Logic (1):1-9.
    Shapiro (Philos Q 61:320–342, 2011) argues that, if we are deflationists about truth, we should be deflationists about logical consequence. Like the truth predicate, he claims, the logical consequence predicate is merely a device of generalisation and more substantial characterisation, e.g. proof- or model-theoretic, is mistaken. I reject his analogy between truth and logical consequence and argue that, by appreciating how the logical consequence predicate is used as well as the goals of proof theory and model theory, we can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A proof-theoretic approach to entailment.N. Tennant - 1980 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 9 (2):185 - 209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Perfect validity, entailment and paraconsistency.Neil Tennant - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (1-2):181 - 200.
    This paper treats entailment as a subrelation of classical consequence and deducibility. Working with a Gentzen set-sequent system, we define an entailment as a substitution instance of a valid sequent all of whose premisses and conclusions are necessary for its classical validity. We also define a sequent Proof as one in which there are no applications of cut or dilution. The main result is that the entailments are exactly the Provable sequents. There are several important corollaries. Every unsatisfiable set is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • The equivalence of tautological and “strict” entailment: Proof of an amended conjecture of Lewy's. [REVIEW]Michael Clark - 1980 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 9 (1):9 - 15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A guide to logical pluralism for non-logicians.Zach Weber - 2017 - Think 16 (47):93-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (1 other version)Tautological entailments.Alan Ross Anderson & Nuel D. Belnap - 1962 - Philosophical Studies 13 (1-2):9 - 24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Connectives stranger than tonk.Heinrich Wansing - 2006 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (6):653 - 660.
    Many logical systems are such that the addition of Prior's binary connective tonk to them leads to triviality, see [1, 8]. Since tonk is given by some introduction and elimination rules in natural deduction or sequent rules in Gentzen's sequent calculus, the unwanted effects of adding tonk show that some kind of restriction has to be imposed on the acceptable operational inferences rules, in particular if these rules are regarded as definitions of the operations concerned. In this paper, a number (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Relevance for the Classical Logician.Ethan Brauer - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):436-457.
    Although much technical and philosophical attention has been given to relevance logics, the notion of relevance itself is generally left at an intuitive level. It is difficult to find in the literature an explicit account of relevance in formal reasoning. In this article I offer a formal explication of the notion of relevance in deductive logic and argue that this notion has an interesting place in the study of classical logic. The main idea is that a premise is relevant to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Negation as cancellation, and connexive logic.Graham Priest - 1999 - Topoi 18 (2):141-148.
    Of the various accounts of negation that have been offered by logicians in the history of Western logic, that of negation as cancellation is a very distinctive one, quite different from the explosive accounts of modern "classical" and intuitionist logics, and from the accounts offered in standard relevant and paraconsistent logics. Despite its ancient origin, however, a precise understanding of the notion is still wanting. The first half of this paper offers one. Both conceptually and historically, the account of negation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Compatibility and relevance: Bolzano and Orlov.Werner Stelzner - 2002 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 10:137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)Does the Traditional Treatment of Enthymemes Rest on a Mistake?David Hitchcock - 1998 - Argumentation 12 (1):15-37.
    In many actual arguments, the conclusion seems intuitively to follow from the premisses, even though we cannot show that it follows logically. The traditional approach to evaluating such arguments is to suppose that they have an unstated premiss whose explicit addition will produce an argument where the conclusion does follow logically. But there are good reasons for doubting that people so frequently leave the premisses of their arguments unstated. The inclination to suppose that they do stems from the belief that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Infinite analysis.William Todd - 1962 - Philosophical Studies 13 (1-2):24 - 27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Logic and the classical theory of mind.Peter Novak - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (4):389-434.
    I extract several common assumptions in the Classical Theory of Mind (CTM) - mainly of Locke and Descartes - and work out a partial formalisation of the logic implicit in CTM. I then define the modal (logical) properties and relations of propositions, including the modality of conditional propositions and the validity of argument, according to the principles of CTM: that is, in terms of clear and distinct ideas, and without any reference to either possible worlds, or deducibility in an axiomatic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A sieve for entailments.J. Michael Dunn - 1980 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 9 (1):41 - 57.
    The validity of an entailment has nothing to do with whether or not the components are true, false, necessary, or impossible; it has to do solely with whether or not there is a necessary connection between antecedent and consequent. Hence it is a mistake (we feel) to try to build a sieve which will “strain out” entailments from the set of material or strict “implications” present in some system of truth-functions, or of truth-functions with modality. Anderson and Belnap (1962, p. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Vagueness as an epiphenomenon, and non-transitivity.Vangelis Triantafyllou - 2022 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 32 (2-3):156-186.
    ABSTRACT This paper deals with the linguistic phenomenon of vagueness. Based on certain observations regarding the intuitions and linguistic practices of the philosophically informed speaker, we make a series of assumptions concerning the nature and characteristics of the phenomenon. Vagueness is treated as an emerging phenomenon, caused, in essence, by the messy way in which linguistic communities reach classificatory equilibria. Any talk of ‘meaning’, ‘truth’, and such is treated as an indirect way of attempting to describe such equilibria, and it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Robust Non-transitive Logic.Alan Weir - 2015 - Topoi 34 (1):1-9.
    Logicians interested in naive theories of truth or set have proposed logical frameworks in which classical operational rules are retained but structural rules are restricted. One increasingly popular way to do this is by restricting transitivity of entailment. This paper discusses a series of logics in this tradition, in which the transitivity restrictions are effected by a determinacy constraint on assumptions occurring in both the major and minor premises of certain rules. Semantics and proof theory for 3-valued, continuum-valued and surreal-valued (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A model of tolerance.Elia Zardini - 2008 - Studia Logica 90 (3):337-368.
    According to the naive theory of vagueness, the vagueness of an expression consists in the existence of both positive and negative cases of application of the expression and in the non- existence of a sharp cut-off point between them. The sorites paradox shows the naive theory to be inconsistent in most logics proposed for a vague language. The paper explores the prospects of saving the naive theory by revising the logic in a novel way, placing principled restrictions on the transitivity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  • (1 other version)Argumentation Theory and the conception of epistemic justification.Lilian Bermejo-Luque - 2009 - In Marcin Koszowy (ed.), Informal logic and argumentation theory. Białystok: University of Białystok. pp. 285--303.
    I characterize the deductivist ideal of justification and, following to a great extent Toulmin’s work The Uses of Argument, I try to explain why this ideal is erroneous. Then I offer an alternative model of justification capable of making our claims to knowledge about substantial matters sound and reasonable. This model of justification will be based on a conception of justification as the result of good argumentation, and on a model of argumentation which is a pragmatic linguistic reconstruction of Toulmin’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Relevant deduction and minimally inconsistent sets.Keith Lehrer - 1973 - Philosophia 3 (2-3):153-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Non-logical Consequence.David Hitchcock - 2009 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 16 (29).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Philosophical basis of relatedness logic.Douglas N. Walton - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 36 (2):115 - 136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A New Approach to Classical Relevance.Inge De Bal & Peter Verdée - 2015 - Studia Logica 103 (5):919-954.
    In this paper we present a logic that determines when implications in a classical logic context express a relevant connection between antecedent and consequent. In contrast with logics in the relevance logic literature, we leave classical negation intact—in the sense that the law of non-contradiction can be used to obtain relevant implications, as long as there is a connection between antecedent and consequent. On the other hand, we give up the requirement that our theory of relevance should be able to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Blurring: An Approach to Conflation.David Ripley - 2018 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 59 (2):171-188.
    I consider the phenomenon of conflation—treating distinct things as one—and develop logical tools for modeling it. These tools involve a purely consequence-theoretic treatment, independent of any proof or model theory, as well as a four-valued valuational treatment.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Local change.Sven Hansson & Renata Wassermann - 2002 - Studia Logica 70 (1):49 - 76.
    An agent can usually hold a very large number of beliefs. However, only a small part of these beliefs is used at a time. Efficient operations for belief change should affect the beliefs of the agent locally, that is, the changes should be performed only in the relevant part of the belief state. In this paper we define a local consequence operator that only considers the relevant part of a belief base. This operator is used to define local versions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Horseshoe, hook, and relevance.B. J. Copeland - 1984 - Theoria 50 (2-3):148-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (1 other version)Reinflating Logical Consequence.Owen Griffiths - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (1):171-179.
    Shapiro (Philos Q 61:320–342, 2011) argues that, if we are deflationists about truth, we should be deflationists about logical consequence. Like the truth predicate, he claims, the logical consequence predicate is merely a device of generalisation and more substantial characterisation, e.g. proof- or model-theoretic, is mistaken. I reject his analogy between truth and logical consequence and argue that, by appreciating how the logical consequence predicate is used as well as the goals of proof theory and model theory, we can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations