Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Scientific Theory Eliminativism.Peter Vickers - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (1):111-126.
    The philosopher of science faces overwhelming disagreement in the literature on the definition, nature, structure, ontology, and content of scientific theories. These disagreements are at least partly responsible for disagreements in many of the debates in the discipline which put weight on the concept scientific theory. I argue that available theories of theories and conceptual analyses of theory are ineffectual options for addressing this difficulty: they do not move debates forward in a significant way. Directing my attention to debates about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Logic of Pragmatic Truth.Newton C. A. Da Costa, Otávio Bueno & Steven French - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (6):603-620.
    The mathematical concept of pragmatic truth, first introduced in Mikenberg, da Costa and Chuaqui (1986), has received in the last few years several applications in logic and the philosophy of science. In this paper, we study the logic of pragmatic truth, and show that there are important connections between this logic, modal logic and, in particular, Jaskowski's discussive logic. In order to do so, two systems are put forward so that the notions of pragmatic validity and pragmatic truth can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Is mathematical rigor necessary in physics?Kevin Davey - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (3):439-463.
    Many arguments found in the physics literature involve concepts that are not well-defined by the usual standards of mathematics. I argue that physicists are entitled to employ such concepts without rigorously defining them so long as they restrict the sorts of mathematical arguments in which these concepts are involved. Restrictions of this sort allow the physicist to ignore calculations involving these concepts that might lead to contradictory results. I argue that such restrictions need not be ad hoc, but can sometimes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Inconsistency in classical electrodynamics.Mathias Frisch - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (4):525-549.
    I show that the standard approach to modeling phenomena involving microscopic classical electrodynamics is mathematically inconsistent. I argue that there is no conceptually unproblematic and consistent theory covering the same phenomena to which this inconsistent theory can be thought of as an approximation; and I propose a set of conditions for the acceptability of inconsistent theories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Is Classical Mathematics Appropriate for Theory of Computation?Farzad Didehvar - manuscript
    Throughout this paper, we are trying to show how and why our Mathematical frame-work seems inappropriate to solve problems in Theory of Computation. More exactly, the concept of turning back in time in paradoxes causes inconsistency in modeling of the concept of Time in some semantic situations. As we see in the first chapter, by introducing a version of “Unexpected Hanging Paradox”,first we attempt to open a new explanation for some paradoxes. In the second step, by applying this paradox, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Inconsistency and scientific realism.Juha Saatsi - 2014 - Synthese 191 (13):2941-2955.
    I erect a framework within the semantic view of theories for explaining the empirical success of internally inconsistent models and theories, with scientific realism in mind. The framework is an instance of the ‘content-driven’ approach to inconsistency, advocated by both Norton (Philos Sci 54:327–350, 1987) and Smith (Stud Hist Philos Sci 19:429–445, 1988a, In: Fine A, Leplin J (eds) PSA1988, 1988b), whose ideas my analysis aims to clarify and substantiate.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Inconsistencies and the dynamics of science.Joke Meheus - 2003 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 11:129-148.
    It is generally agreed upon today that scientific reasoning, like everyday reasoning, proceeds in a dynamic way: inferences derived at some stage in the reasoning process may at a later stage be rejected. This dynamics may be extrinsic or intrinsic. I shall call it extrinsic when previously derived conclusions are rejected on non-logical grounds, and intrinsic when their rejection is based on a purely logical analysis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On the Acceptance of Problem Solutions Derived from Inconsistent Constraints.Joke Meheus - 2000 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 8:33-46.
    In this paper, I discuss the main difficulties one encounters whensolving problems with inconsistent constraints. I argue that in order to meetthese difficulties we need an inconsistency-adaptive logic that enables one toderive as many consequences as possible, but that at the sametime allows one to determine which consequences can be accepted. I showthat the inconsistency-adaptive logic ANA satisfies these requirements.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deductive and ampliative adaptive logics as tools in the study of creativity.Joke Meheus - 1999 - Foundations of Science 4 (3):325-336.
    In this paper, I argue that logic hasan important role to play in the methodological studyof creativity. I also argue, however, that onlyspecial kinds of logic enable one to understand thereasoning involved in creative processes. I show thatdeductive and ampliative adaptive logics areappropriate tools in this respect.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Logically Equivalent—But Closer to the Truth.Roy A. Sorensen - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (2):287-297.
    Verisimilitude has the potential to deepen the understanding of mathematical progress, the principle of charity, and the psychology of regret. One obstacle is the widely held belief that two statements can vary in truthlikeness only if they vary in what they entail. This obstacle is removed with four types of counterexamples. The first concerns necessarily coextensive measurements that differ only with respect to their units. The second class of counterexamples is composed of mathematical falsehoods. The third class features inconsistent scientific (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Narrowing down suspicion in inconsistent premise sets.Diderik Batens - 2006 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 91 (1):185-209.
    Inconsistency-adaptive logics isolate the inconsistencies that are derivable from a premise set, and restrict the rules of Classical Logic only where inconsistencies are involved. From many inconsistent premise sets, disjunctions of contradictions are derivable no disjunct of which is itself derivable. Given such a disjunction, it is often justified to introduce new premises that state, with a certain degree of confidence, that some of the disjuncts are false. This is an important first step on the road to consistency: it narrows (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The theory of the process of explanation generalized to include the inconsistent case.Diderik Batens - 2005 - Synthese 143 (1-2):63 - 88.
    . This paper proposes a generalization of the theory of the process of explanation to include consistent as well as inconsistent situations. The generalization is strong, for example in the sense that, if the background theory and the initial conditions are consistent, it leads to precisely the same results as the theory from the lead paper (Halonen and Hintikka 2004). The paper presupposes (and refers to arguments for the view that) inconsistencies constitute problems and that scientists try to resolve them.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mathematical Rigor in Physics: Putting Exact Results in Their Place.Axel Gelfert - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):723-738.
    The present paper examines the role of exact results in the theory of many‐body physics, and specifically the example of the Mermin‐Wagner theorem, a rigorous result concerning the absence of phase transitions in low‐dimensional systems. While the theorem has been shown to hold for a wide range of many‐body models, it is frequently ‘violated’ by results derived from the same models using numerical techniques. This raises the question of how scientists regulate their theoretical commitments in such cases, given that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)The essential tension.Marta Fehér - 1990 - Studies in East European Thought 39 (3-4):231-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Paraconsistency and its relation to worldviews.Diderik Batens - 1998 - Foundations of Science 3 (2):259-283.
    The paper highlights the import of the paraconsistent movement, list some motivations for its origin, and distinguishes some stands with respect to para-consistency. It then discusses some sources of inconsistency that are specific for worldviews, and the import of the paraconsistent turn for the worldviews enterprise.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Independence from Future Theories: A Research Strategy in Quantum Theory.Alexander Rueger - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (1):202-211.
    Renormalization in Quantum Field Theory (QFT) has frequently been regarded, by philosophers as well as by scientists, as an exemplary case of bad methodological behavior. The feeling that renormalization was somehow an illegitimate way to extract results, an ad hoc maneuver without an independent rationale, was (and is) common among physicists and philosophers, who wonder, at the same time, about the unprecedented accuracy of the empirical results achieved by the illegitimate method. Teller (1989) has recently tried to dispel the air (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Scientific Disagreement and Evidential Pluralism: Lessons from the Studies on Hypercholesterolemia.Veli-Pekka Parkkinen, Federica Russo & Christian Wallmann - 2017 - Humana Mente 10 (32):75-116.
    Inconsistencies between scientific theories have been studied, by and large, from the perspective of paraconsistent logic. This approach considered the formal properties of theories and the structure of inferences one can legitimately draw from theories. However, inconsistencies can be also analysed from the perspective of modelling practices, in particular how modelling practices may lead scientists to form opinions and attitudes that are different, but not necessarily inconsistent. In such cases, it is preferable to talk about disagreement, rather than inconsistency. Disagreement (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Theory Eliminativism as a Methodological Tool.Peter Vickers - unknown
    Disagreements about the definition, nature, structure, ontology, and content of scientific theories are at least partly responsible for disagreements in other debates in the philosophy of science. I argue that available theories of theories and conceptual analyses of *theory* are ineffectual options for overcoming this difficulty. Directing my attention to debates about the properties of particular, named theories, I introduce ‘theory eliminativism’ as a certain type of debate-reformulation. As a methodological tool it has the potential to be a highly effective (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A new characterization of scientific theories.Jody Azzouni - 2014 - Synthese 191 (13):2993-3008.
    First, I discuss the older “theory-centered” and the more recent semantic conception of scientific theories. I argue that these two perspectives are nothing more than terminological variants of one another. I then offer a new theory-centered view of scientific theories. I argue that this new view captures the insights had by each of these earlier views, that it’s closer to how scientists think about their own theories, and that it better accommodates the phenomenon of inconsistent scientific theories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Complementary explanations.Max Urchs - 1999 - Synthese 120 (1):137-149.
    Scientific explanations arc subject to the occurrence of inconsistencies. To rule them out in many cases demands the construction of new theories. As the examples of complementary explanations show, that may take a while. Furthermore, even if possible in principle, it is not always reasonable to eliminate inconsistencies immediately, e.g., by bringing in a more sophisticated formal language. After all, under some circumstances a provisional, not fully coherent explanation may be better than none. In any case, we need a logically (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Holism, Inconsistency Toleration and Inconsistencies between Theory and Observation.María del Rosario Martínez-Ordaz - 2017 - Humana Mente 10 (32):117-147.
    It has recently been argued by Davey (2014) that inconsistency is never tolerated in science, but only discretely isolated. But when talking about inconsistencies in science, not much attention has been paid to the inconsistencies between theory and observation. Here I will argue that inconsistency toleration actually takes place in science, and that when we examine actual inconsistent theories, inconsistencies between theory and observation look anything but homogeneous. I will argue, appealing to certain properties of empirical theories, especially holism, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Need for Adaptative Logics in Epistemology.Diderik Batens - 2004 - In S. Rahman (ed.), Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 459-485.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • How multiplayer online battle arenas foster scientific reasoning.Carlos Castaño Díaz - 2017 - Dissertation, Ludwig Maximilians Universität, München
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Scientific Reasoning or Damage Control: Alternative Proposals for Reasoning with Inconsistent Representations of the World.Joel M. Smith - 1988 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988 (1):241-248.
    Logical analyses of scientific representations of the world have usually focused on axiomatized or axiomatizable theories. As practiced, science seldom employs such theories. Rather, we find aggregations of claims, the logical relations of which are not as neat as philosophers of science might like them to be. Indeed, a common feature of such aggregations is the presence of certain “theoretical anomalies,” statements that are in some way incompatible with the remainder of the corpus. Huygens’ description of light as exhibiting an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The Essential Tension.Marta Fehér - 1990 - Studies in Soviet Thought 39 (3):231-239.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The shape of science.M. Bryson Brown - 2014 - Synthese 191 (13):3079-3109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Erotetic arguments from inconsistent premises.Joke Meheus - 1999 - Logique Et Analyse 165 (166):49-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations