Switch to: References

Citations of:

Simplicity

Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press (1975)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The natural geometry of a behavioral homology.Ilan Golani - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):291-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dynamical systems theory and the mobility gradient: Information, homology and self-similar structure.Gary Goldberg - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):278-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • De Facto and De Jure in the Practice of Induction.Daniel Goldstick - 2020 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 33 (2):105-116.
    ‘Simplicity’ comes up in different senses in scientific methodology. The simplicity criterion at issue here is relied on in all inductive inference, it’s argued. Therefore, it cannot be inductively...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A mobility gradient in the organization of vertebrate movement: The perception of movement through symbolic language.Ilan Golani - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):249-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is the mobility gradient suitable for general application?George W. Barlow - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):267-268.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The environment modulates the mobility gradient, temporally if not sequentially.Charles H. M. Beck - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):268-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Structure and function in the CNS.Peter H. Klopfer - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):281-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Explanation in Biology: Let's Razor Ockham's Razor.Elliott Sober - 1990 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 27:73-93.
    When philosophers discuss the topic of explanation, they usually have in mind the following question: given the beliefs one has and some proposition that one wishes to explain, which subset of the beliefs constitutes an explanation of the target proposition? That is, the philosophical ‘problem of explanation’ typically has bracketed the issue of how one obtains the beliefs; they are taken as given. The problem of explanation has been the problem of understanding the relation ‘x explains y’. Since Hempel did (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The 'requirement of total evidence' and its role in phylogenetic systematics.Kirk Fitzhugh - 2006 - Biology and Philosophy 21 (3):309-351.
    The question of whether or not to partition data for the purposes of inferring phylogenetic hypotheses remains controversial. Opinions have been especially divided since Kluge's (1989, Systematic Zoology 38, 7–25) claim that data partitioning violates the requirement of total evidence (RTE). Unfortunately, advocacy for or against the RTE has not been based on accurate portrayals of the requirement. The RTE is a basic maxim for non-deductive inference, stipulating that evidence must be considered if it has relevance to an inference. Evidence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Sequence Data, Phylogenetic Inference, and Implications of Downward Causation.Kirk Fitzhugh - 2016 - Acta Biotheoretica 64 (2):133-160.
    Framing systematics as a field consistent with scientific inquiry entails that inferences of phylogenetic hypotheses have the goal of producing accounts of past causal events that explain differentially shared characters among organisms. Linking observations of characters to inferences occurs by way of why-questions implied by data matrices. Because of their form, why-questions require the use of common-cause theories. Such theories in phylogenetic inferences include natural selection and genetic drift. Selection or drift can explain ‘morphological’ characters but selection cannot be causally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Alternative taxonomies in movement: Not only possible but critical.John C. Fentress - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):277-278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connecting invertebrate behavior, neurophysiology and evolution with Eshkol-Wachman movement notation.Zen Faulkes & Dorothy Hayman Paul - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):276-277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moving beyond words.Robert Fagen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):275-276.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ideological parsimony.Sam Cowling - 2013 - Synthese 190 (17):3889-3908.
    The theoretical virtue of parsimony values the minimizing of theoretical commitments, but theoretical commitments come in two kinds : ontological and ideological. While the ontological commitments of a theory are the entities it posits, a theory’s ideological commitments are the primitive concepts it employs. Here, I show how we can extend the distinction between quantitative and qualitative parsimony, commonly drawn regarding ontological commitments, to the domain of ideological commitments. I then argue that qualitative ideological parsimony is a theoretical virtue. My (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • The mobility gradient from a comparative phylogenetic perspective.David Eilam - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):274-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A‐Rational Epistemological Disjunctivism.Santiago Echeverri - 2023 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 106 (3):692-719.
    According to epistemological disjunctivism (ED), in paradigmatic cases of perceptual knowledge, a subject, S, has perceptual knowledge that p in virtue of being in possession of reasons for her belief that p which are both factive and reflectively accessible to S. It has been argued that ED is better placed than both knowledge internalism and knowledge externalism to undercut underdetermination-based skepticism. I identify several principles that must be true if ED is to be uniquely placed to attain this goal. After (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Eshkol-Wachman movement notation and the evolution of locomotor patterns in vertebrates.Robert C. Eaton - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):272-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does a Parsimony Principle Entail a Simple World?Craig DeLancey - 2011 - Metaphysica 12 (2):87-100.
    Many scholars claim that a parsimony principle has ontological implications. The most common such claim is that a parsimony principle entails that the “world” is simple. This ontological claim appears to often be coupled with the assumption that a parsimony principle would be corroborated if the “world” were simple. I clarify these claims, describe some minimal features of simplicity, and then show that both these claims are either false or they depend upon an implausible notion of simplicity. In their stead, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Accuracy and ur-prior conditionalization.Nilanjan Das - 2019 - Review of Symbolic Logic 12 (1):62-96.
    Recently, several epistemologists have defended an attractive principle of epistemic rationality, which we shall call Ur-Prior Conditionalization. In this essay, I ask whether we can justify this principle by appealing to the epistemic goal of accuracy. I argue that any such accuracy-based argument will be in tension with Evidence Externalism, i.e., the view that agent's evidence may entail non-trivial propositions about the external world. This is because any such argument will crucially require the assumption that, independently of all empirical evidence, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)On universals: an extensionalist alternative to Quine’s resemblance theory. [REVIEW]Nathan Stemmer - 2005 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (1):75 - 90.
    The notion of similarity plays a central role in Quine’s theory of Universals and it is with the help of this notion that Quine intends to define the concept of kind which also plays a central role in the theory. But as Quine has admitted, his attempts to define kinds in terms of similarities were unsuccessful and it is mainly because of this shortcoming that Quine’s theory has been ignored by several philosophers (see, e.g., Armstrong, D. M. (1978a). Nominalism and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Striatal structures, dopamine and the mobility gradient model.Alexander R. Cools - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):271-272.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Revisiting the Scientific Nature of Multiverse Theories.Man Ho Chan - 2023 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 55 (1):137-151.
    Some scientists or philosophers argue that multiverse theories are unfalsifiable and thus not scientific. However, some advocates of multiverse theories have recently argued that although the multiverse is not observable, multiverse theories are indeed falsifiable in principle. Therefore, they share similar features with a conventional scientific theory. On the other hand, the proposals of an epistemic shift and nonempirical theory assessment have possibly revived the discussions of the scientific nature of multiverse theories. In this article, I revisit the falsifiable arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Utility and the Value of Persons: A Response to Professor Brandt's Comments.Claudia Card - 1984 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (1):39 - 43.
    I have four responses to make, the first three very brief and the last not much longer.On the face of it, it looks as though in attributing rights to people one is saying something about their moral position. This is so for both option-rights and welfare-rights. On H.L.A. Hart's account of rights to freedom, that is exactly what one is doing. One is asserting that those who have the right have a special kind of justification for limiting the freedom of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The mobility gradient: Useful, general, falsifiable?John A. Byers - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):270-271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Description and explanation: A plea for plurality.Marc Bekoff - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):269-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ockham's razor and the anti-superfluity principle.E. C. Barnes - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (3):353-374.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • How to Undermine Underdetermination?Prasanta S. Bandyopadhyay, John G. Bennett & Megan D. Higgs - 2015 - Foundations of Science 20 (2):107-127.
    The underdetermination thesis poses a threat to rational choice of scientific theories. We discuss two arguments for the thesis. One draws its strength from deductivism together with the existence thesis, and the other is defended on the basis of the failure of a reliable inductive method. We adopt a partially subjective/objective pragmatic Bayesian epistemology of science framework, and reject both arguments for the thesis. Thus, in science we are able to reinstate rational choice called into question by the underdetermination thesis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why Eshkol-Wachman behavioral notation is not enough.Colin Allen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):266-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Epistemic Simplicity—A Virtue or a Vice?Piotr Lichacz - 2021 - Metaphilosophy 52 (2):200-219.
    Simplicity was recently described in the philosophy of science as “perhaps the most controversial theoretical virtue” (Schindler 2018). It has been also argued that contrary to the standard view, simplicity is not merely a pragmatic virtue but also an epistemic one. Virtue epistemologists are also interested in epistemic virtues, but simplicity is usually absent in their discussions. This paper adduces several contemporary approaches to simplicity showing that in philosophy and in psychology it can be considered either as a virtue or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Aesthetics of Theory Selection and the Logics of Art.Ian O’Loughlin & Kate McCallum - 2018 - Philosophy of Science (2):325-343.
    Philosophers of science discuss whether theory selection depends on aesthetic judgments or criteria, and whether these putatively aesthetic features are genuinely extra-epistemic. As examples, judgments involving criteria such as simplicity and symmetry are often cited. However, other theory selection criteria, such as fecundity, coherence, internal consistency, and fertility, more closely match those criteria used in art contexts and by scholars working in aesthetics. Paying closer attention to the way these criteria are used in art contexts allows us to understand some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • (1 other version)Explanation—Opening Address.J. J. C. Smart - 1990 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 27:1-19.
    It is a pleasure for me to give this opening address to the Royal Institute of Philosophy Conference on ‘Explanation’ for two reasons. The first is that it is succeeded by exciting symposia and other papers concerned with various special aspects of the topic of explanation. The second is that the conference is being held in my old alma mater, the University of Glasgow, where I did my first degree. Especially due to C. A. Campbell and George Brown there was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • (1 other version)Models in Biology and Physics: What’s the Difference?Darrell Patrick Rowbottom - 2009 - Foundations of Science 14 (4):281-294.
    In Making Sense of Life, Keller emphasizes several differences between biology and physics. Her analysis focuses on significant ways in which modelling practices in some areas of biology, especially developmental biology, differ from those of the physical sciences. She suggests that natural models and modelling by homology play a central role in the former but not the latter. In this paper, I focus instead on those practices that are importantly similar, from the point of view of epistemology and cognitive science. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Animal motility: Gestalt or piecemeal assembly.Paul Leyhausen - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):282-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Common cause explanation.Elliott Sober - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (2):212-241.
    Russell (1948), Reichenbach (1956), and Salmon (1975, 1979) have argued that a fundamental principle of science and common sense is that "matching" events should not be chalked up to coincidence, but should be explained by postulating a common cause. Reichenbach and Salmon provided this intuitive idea with a probabilistic formulation, which Salmon used to argue for a version of scientific realism. Van Fraassen (1980, 1982) showed that the principle, so construed, runs afoul of certain results in quantum mechanics. In this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Linguistics and psychology.Scott Soames - 1984 - Linguistics and Philosophy 7 (2):155 - 179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Normativity in the Philosophy of Science.Marie I. Kaiser - 2019 - Metaphilosophy 50 (1-2):36-62.
    This paper analyzes what it means for philosophy of science to be normative. It argues that normativity is a multifaceted phenomenon rather than a general feature that a philosophical theory either has or lacks. It analyzes the normativity of philosophy of science by articulating three ways in which a philosophical theory can be normative. Methodological normativity arises from normative assumptions that philosophers make when they select, interpret, evaluate, and mutually adjust relevant empirical information, on which they base their philosophical theories. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What are voluntary movements made of?Ian Q. Whishaw - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):290-291.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The yin and yang of behavioral analysis.Sergio M. Pellis - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):286-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The functions of fossils: Inference and explanation in functional morphology.Derek Turner - 2000 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 31 (1):193-212.
    This paper offers an account of the relationship between inference and explanation in functional morphology which combines Robert Brandon's theory of adaptation explanation with standard accounts of inference to the best explanation. Inferences of function from structure, it is argued, are inferences to the best adaptation explanation. There are, however, three different approaches to the problem of determining which adaptation explanation is the best. The theory of inference to the best adaptation explanation is then applied to a case study from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Epistemic value.William G. Lycan - 1985 - Synthese 64 (2):137 - 164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Joule’s Nineteenth Century Energy Conservation Meta-law and the Twentieth Century Physics (Quantum Mechanics and Relativity): Twenty-First Century Analysis.Vladik Kreinovich & Olga Kosheleva - 2021 - Foundations of Science 26 (3):703-725.
    Joule’s Energy Conservation Law was the first “meta-law”: a general principle that all physical equations must satisfy. It has led to many important and useful physical discoveries. However, a recent analysis seems to indicate that this meta-law is inconsistent with other principles—such as the existence of free will. We show that this conclusion about inconsistency is based on a seemingly reasonable—but simplified—analysis of the situation. We also show that a more detailed mathematical and physical analysis of the situation reveals that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Models in Biology and Physics: What’s the Difference?Darrell Patrick Rowbottom - 2009 - Foundations of Science 14 (4):281-294.
    In Making Sense of Life , Keller emphasizes several differences between biology and physics. Her analysis focuses on significant ways in which modelling practices in some areas of biology, especially developmental biology, differ from those of the physical sciences. She suggests that natural models and modelling by homology play a central role in the former but not the latter. In this paper, I focus instead on those practices that are importantly similar, from the point of view of epistemology and cognitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Evolutionary theory and the ontological status of properties.Elliott Sober - 1981 - Philosophical Studies 40 (2):147 - 176.
    Quine has developed two reasons for thinking that our ontology should not include the ontological category of properties. His first point is that the criterion for individuating properties is unclear, and the second is that postulating the existence of properties would not explain anything. In what follows I critically examine these two themes, which I will call the clarity argument and the parsimony argument. Although I will suggest that these two arguments are defective, I also will try to show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The evolution of rationality.Elliott Sober - 1981 - Synthese 46 (January):95-120.
    How could the fundamental mental operations which facilitate scientific theorizing be the product of natural selection, since it appears that such theoretical methods were neither used nor useful "in the cave"-i.e., in the sequence of environments in which selection took place? And if these wired-in information processing techniques were not selected for, how can we view rationality as an adaptation? It will be the purpose of this paper to address such questions as these, and in the process to sketch some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • (1 other version)Selectivity and Theory Choice.Mattl Sintonen - 1986 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1):364-373.
    In his 1982 Presidential Address to the PSA Ernan McMullin proposed that the Kuhnian “revolution” in the philosophy of science amounts, in part, to the growing awareness that theory-appraisal is to be modelled on decisions and value judgments rather than rule-governed inferences (McMullin 1983). This viewpoint has its attractions but needs developing before it can satisfy skeptics, such as Larry Laudan. For Laudan complains that Kuhn has provided no general model to back up his value-geared account, and that the view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Simplicity of what? A case study from generative linguistics.Giulia Terzian & María Inés Corbalán - 2020 - Synthese 198 (10):9427-9452.
    The Minimalist Program in generative linguistics is predicated on the idea that simplicity is a defining property of the human language faculty, on the one hand; on the other, a central aim of linguistic theorising. Worryingly, however, justifications for either claim are hard to come by in the literature. We sketch a proposal that would allow for both shortcomings to be addressed, and that furthermore honours the program’s declared commitment to naturalism. We begin by teasing apart and clarifying the different (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When is a cladist not a cladist?Aleta Quinn - 2017 - Biology and Philosophy 32 (4):581-598.
    The term “cladist” has distinct meanings in distinct contexts. Communication between philosophers, historians, and biologists has been hindered by different understandings of the term in various contexts. In this paper I trace historical and conceptual connections between several broadly distinct senses of the term “cladist”. I propose seven specific definitions that capture distinct contemporary uses. This serves to disambiguate some cases where the meaning is unclear, and will help resolve apparent disagreements that in fact result from conflicting understandings of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Birdsong: Variations that follow rules.Dietmar Todt & Henrike Hultsch - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):289-290.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bayesianism and language change.Jon Williamson - 2003 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 12 (1):53-97.
    Bayesian probability is normally defined over a fixed language or eventspace. But in practice language is susceptible to change, and thequestion naturally arises as to how Bayesian degrees of belief shouldchange as language changes. I argue here that this question poses aserious challenge to Bayesianism. The Bayesian may be able to meet thischallenge however, and I outline a practical method for changing degreesof belief over changes in finite propositional languages.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On advancing simple hypotheses.Daniel N. Osherson & Scott Weinstein - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (2):266-277.
    We consider drawbacks to scientific methods that prefer simple hypotheses to complex ones that cover the same data. The discussion proceeds in the context of a precise model of scientific inquiry.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations