Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Analyticity versus fuzziness.John G. Kemeny - 1963 - Synthese 15 (1):57 - 80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Zermelo and set theory.Akihiro Kanamori - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):487-553.
    Ernst Friedrich Ferdinand Zermelo transformed the set theory of Cantor and Dedekind in the first decade of the 20th century by incorporating the Axiom of Choice and providing a simple and workable axiomatization setting out generative set-existence principles. Zermelo thereby tempered the ontological thrust of early set theory, initiated the delineation of what is to be regarded as set-theoretic, drawing out the combinatorial aspects from the logical, and established the basic conceptual framework for the development of modern set theory. Two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The mathematical development of set theory from Cantor to Cohen.Akihiro Kanamori - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):1-71.
    Set theory is an autonomous and sophisticated field of mathematics, enormously successful not only at its continuing development of its historical heritage but also at analyzing mathematical propositions cast in set-theoretic terms and gauging their consistency strength. But set theory is also distinguished by having begun intertwined with pronounced metaphysical attitudes, and these have even been regarded as crucial by some of its great developers. This has encouraged the exaggeration of crises in foundations and of metaphysical doctrines in general. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Law and logic.Stig Kanger - 1972 - Theoria 38 (3):105-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Gödel and set theory.Akihiro Kanamori - 2007 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):153-188.
    Kurt Gödel with his work on the constructible universeLestablished the relative consistency of the Axiom of Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis. More broadly, he ensured the ascendancy of first-order logic as the framework and a matter of method for set theory and secured the cumulative hierarchy view of the universe of sets. Gödel thereby transformed set theory and launched it with structured subject matter and specific methods of proof. In later years Gödel worked on a variety of set theoretic constructions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • A correspondence between Martin-löf type theory, the ramified theory of types and pure type systems.Fairouz Kamareddine & Twan Laan - 2001 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10 (3):375-402.
    In Russell''s Ramified Theory of Types RTT, two hierarchical concepts dominate:orders and types. The use of orders has as a consequencethat the logic part of RTT is predicative.The concept of order however, is almost deadsince Ramsey eliminated it from RTT. This is whywe find Church''s simple theory of types (which uses the type concept without the order one) at the bottom of the Barendregt Cube rather than RTT. Despite the disappearance of orders which have a strong correlation with predicativity, predicative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Truth in applicative theories.Reinhard Kahle - 2001 - Studia Logica 68 (1):103-128.
    We give a survey on truth theories for applicative theories. It comprises Frege structures, universes for Frege structures, and a theory of supervaluation. We present the proof-theoretic results for these theories and show their syntactical expressive power. In particular, we present as a novelty a syntactical interpretation of ID1 in a applicative truth theory based on supervaluation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A strong multi-typed intuitionistic theory of functionals.Farida Kachapova - 2015 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 80 (3):1035-1065.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Procedural semantics.Philip N. Johnson-Laird - 1977 - Cognition 5 (3):189-214.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Too naturalist and not naturalist enough: Reply to Horsten.Luca Incurvati - 2008 - Erkenntnis 69 (2):261 - 274.
    Leon Horsten has recently claimed that the class of mathematical truths coincides with the class of theorems of ZFC. I argue that the naturalistic character of Horsten’s proposal undermines his contention that this claim constitutes an analogue of a thesis that Daniel Isaacson has advanced for PA. I argue, moreover, that Horsten’s defence of his claim against an obvious objection makes use of a distinction which is not available to him given his naturalistic approach. I suggest a way out of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Explizite Definitionen einiger Eigenschaften von Zeichenreihen.Klaus Härtig - 1956 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 2 (10-15):177-203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • No future.Leon Horsten & Hannes Leitgeb - 2001 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 30 (3):259-265.
    The difficulties with formalizing the intensional notions necessity, knowability and omniscience, and rational belief are well-known. If these notions are formalized as predicates applying to (codes of) sentences, then from apparently weak and uncontroversial logical principles governing these notions, outright contradictions can be derived. Tense logic is one of the best understood and most extensively developed branches of intensional logic. In tense logic, the temporal notions future and past are formalized as sentential operators rather than as predicates. The question therefore (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Making computational sense of Montague's intensional logic.Jerry R. Hobbs & Stanley J. Rosenschein - 1977 - Artificial Intelligence 9 (3):287-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What is the axiomatic method?Jaakko Hintikka - 2011 - Synthese 183 (1):69-85.
    The modern notion of the axiomatic method developed as a part of the conceptualization of mathematics starting in the nineteenth century. The basic idea of the method is the capture of a class of structures as the models of an axiomatic system. The mathematical study of such classes of structures is not exhausted by the derivation of theorems from the axioms but includes normally the metatheory of the axiom system. This conception of axiomatization satisfies the crucial requirement that the derivation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Truth definitions, Skolem functions and axiomatic set theory.Jaakko Hintikka - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):303-337.
    §1. The mission of axiomatic set theory. What is set theory needed for in the foundations of mathematics? Why cannot we transact whatever foundational business we have to transact in terms of our ordinary logic without resorting to set theory? There are many possible answers, but most of them are likely to be variations of the same theme. The core area of ordinary logic is by a fairly common consent the received first-order logic. Why cannot it take care of itself? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Post-tarskian truth.Jaakko Hintikka - 2001 - Synthese 126 (1-2):17 - 36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • On tarski’s assumptions.Jaakko Hintikka - 2005 - Synthese 142 (3):353 - 369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On tarski’s assumptions.Jaakko Hintikka - 2005 - Synthese 142 (3):353-369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introduction and postcript.J. Hintikka - 2001 - Synthese 126 (1-2):1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A counterexample to Tarski-type truth-definitions as applied to natural languages.Jaakko Hintikka - 1975 - Philosophia 5 (3):207-212.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The completeness of the first-order functional calculus.Leon Henkin - 1949 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (3):159-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   111 citations  
  • Banishing the rule of substitution for functional variables.Leon Henkin - 1953 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (3):201-208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Vagueness and logic.Carl G. Hempel - 1939 - Philosophy of Science 6 (2):163-180.
    As is rather generally admitted today, the terms of our language in scientific as well as in everyday use, are not completely precise, but exhibit a more or less high degree of vagueness. It is the purpose of this paper to examine the consequences of this circumstance for a series of questions which belong to the field of logic. First of all, the meaning and the logical status of the concept of vagueness will be analyzed; then we will try to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Modality as many metalinguistic predicates.Allen Hazen - 1984 - Philosophical Studies 46 (2):271 - 277.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception, Intuition, and Reliability.Kai Hauser & Tahsİn Öner - 2018 - Theoria 84 (1):23-59.
    The question of how we can know anything about ideal entities to which we do not have access through our senses has been a major concern in the philosophical tradition since Plato's Phaedo. This article focuses on the paradigmatic case of mathematical knowledge. Following a suggestion by Gödel, we employ concepts and ideas from Husserlian phenomenology to argue that mathematical objects – and ideal entities in general – are recognized in a process very closely related to ordinary perception. Our analysis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Objectivity over objects: A case study in theory formation.Kai Hauser - 2001 - Synthese 128 (3):245 - 285.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Gödel's program revisited part I: The turn to phenomenology.Kai Hauser - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (4):529-590.
    Convinced that the classically undecidable problems of mathematics possess determinate truth values, Gödel issued a programmatic call to search for new axioms for their solution. The platonism underlying his belief in the determinateness of those questions in combination with his conception of intuition as a kind of perception have struck many of his readers as highly problematic. Following Gödel's own suggestion, this article explores ideas from phenomenology to specify a meaning for his mathematical realism that allows for a defensible epistemology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Truth and the Liar in De Morgan-Valued Models.Hannes Leitgeb - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (4):496-514.
    The aim of this paper is to give a certain algebraic account of truth: we want to define what we mean by De Morgan-valued truth models and show their existence even in the case of semantical closure: that is, languages may contain their own truth predicate if they are interpreted by De Morgan-valued models. Before we can prove this result, we have to repeat some basic facts concerning De Morgan-valued models in general, and we will introduce a notion of truth (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Substitutional Analysis of Logical Consequence.Volker Halbach - 2019 - Noûs 54 (2):431-450.
    A substitutional account of logical validity for formal first‐order languages is developed and defended against competing accounts such as the model‐theoretic definition of validity. Roughly, a substitution instance of a sentence is defined as the result of uniformly substituting nonlogical expressions in the sentence with expressions of the same grammatical category and possibly relativizing quantifiers. In particular, predicate symbols can be replaced with formulae possibly containing additional free variables. A sentence is defined to be logically true iff all its substitution (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Tarski hierarchies.Volker Halbach - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (3):339 - 367.
    The general notions of object- and metalanguage are discussed and as a special case of this relation an arbitrary first order language with an infinite model is expanded by a predicate symbol T0 which is interpreted as truth predicate for . Then the expanded language is again augmented by a new truth predicate T1 for the whole language plus T0. This process is iterated into the transfinite to obtain the Tarskian hierarchy of languages. It is shown that there are natural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On the unusual effectiveness of logic in computer science.Joseph Y. Halpern, Robert Harper, Neil Immerman, Phokion G. Kolaitis, Moshe Y. Vardi & Victor Vianu - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (2):213-236.
    In 1960, E. P. Wigner, a joint winner of the 1963 Nobel Prize for Physics, published a paper titled On the Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences [61]. This paper can be construed as an examination and affirmation of Galileo's tenet that “The book of nature is written in the language of mathematics”. To this effect, Wigner presented a large number of examples that demonstrate the effectiveness of mathematics in accurately describing physical phenomena. Wigner viewed these examples as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Editorial introduction.Volker Halbach - 2001 - Studia Logica 68 (1):3-20.
    I survey some important semantical and axiomatic theories of self-referential truth. Kripke's fixed-point theory, the revision theory of truth and appraoches involving fuzzy logic are the main examples of semantical theories. I look at axiomatic theories devised by Cantini, Feferman, Freidman and Sheard. Finally some applications of the theory of self-referential truth are considered.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A sense-based, process model of belief.Robert F. Hadley - 1991 - Minds and Machines 1 (3):279-320.
    A process-oriented model of belief is presented which permits the representation of nested propositional attitudes within first-order logic. The model (NIM, for nested intensional model) is axiomatized, sense-based (via intensions), and sanctions inferences involving nested epistemic attitudes, with different agents and different times. Because NIM is grounded upon senses, it provides a framework in which agents may reason about the beliefs of another agent while remaining neutral with respect to the syntactic forms used to express the latter agent's beliefs. Moreover, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conditionals in Theories of Truth.Anil Gupta & Shawn Standefer - 2017 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 46 (1):27-63.
    We argue that distinct conditionals—conditionals that are governed by different logics—are needed to formalize the rules of Truth Introduction and Truth Elimination. We show that revision theory, when enriched with the new conditionals, yields an attractive theory of truth. We go on to compare this theory with one recently proposed by Hartry Field.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Why Aristotle’s Sea-Battle Argument is Valid.Michael Groneberg - 2013 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 16 (1):331-345.
    The paper tries to demonstrate the validity of Aristotle’s sea-battle argument, which is still considered as invalid by many authors. The first part presents the usual reconstruction of Aristotle’s argument and the reason for its rejection. It presents the late antique adoption of the argument as valid and strong by Ammonios and Boethius as well as its modern defence. In the second part, the elements that together assure the validity of the argument are combined and cast in the form of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Frege on Truth, Assertoric Force and the Essence of Logic.Dirk Greimann - 2014 - History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (3):272-288.
    In a posthumous text written in 1915, Frege makes some puzzling remarks about the essence of logic, arguing that the essence of logic is indicated, properly speaking, not by the word ‘true’, but by the assertoric force. William Taschek has recently shown that these remarks, which have received only little attention, are very important for understanding Frege's conception of logic. On Taschek's reconstruction, Frege characterizes logic in terms of assertoric force in order to stress the normative role that the logical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Die idee hinter tarskis definition Von wahrheit.Dirk Greimann - 1997 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 28 (1):121-158.
    The Idea behind Tarski's Definition of Truth. In Tarski's presentations of his truth-definition, the steps of the construction are not sufficiently explained. It is not clear, on what general strategy the construction is based, what the fundamental ideas are, how some crucial steps work, and especially how the transition from the definition of satisfaction to the definition of truth should be understood. The paper shows that the account given in the model-theoretic literature, which is supported by Tarski's lemmata A and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Typology of Conceptual Explications.Dirk Greimann - 2012 - Disputatio 4 (34):645-670.
    Greimann-Dirk_A-typology-of-conceptual-explications.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Varieties of Self-Reference in Metamathematics.Balthasar Grabmayr, Volker Halbach & Lingyuan Ye - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (4):1005-1052.
    This paper investigates the conditions under which diagonal sentences can be taken to constitute paradigmatic cases of self-reference. We put forward well-motivated constraints on the diagonal operator and the coding apparatus which separate paradigmatic self-referential sentences, for instance obtained via Gödel’s diagonalization method, from accidental diagonal sentences. In particular, we show that these constraints successfully exclude refutable Henkin sentences, as constructed by Kreisel.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Omnipresence, Multipresence and Ubiquity: Kinds of Generality in and Around Mathematics and Logics. [REVIEW]I. Grattan-Guinness - 2011 - Logica Universalis 5 (1):21-73.
    A prized property of theories of all kinds is that of generality, of applicability or least relevance to a wide range of circumstances and situations. The purpose of this article is to present a pair of distinctions that suggest that three kinds of generality are to be found in mathematics and logics, not only at some particular period but especially in developments that take place over time: ‘omnipresent’ and ‘multipresent’ theories, and ‘ubiquitous’ notions that form dependent parts, or moments, of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Karl Popper for and against Bertrand Russell.I. Grattan-Guinness - 1998 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 18 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rereading Tarski on logical consequence.Mario Gómez-Torrente - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (2):249-297.
    I argue that recent defenses of the view that in 1936 Tarski required all interpretations of a language to share one same domain of quantification are based on misinterpretations of Tarski’s texts. In particular, I rebut some criticisms of my earlier attack on the fixed-domain exegesis and I offer a more detailed report of the textual evidence on the issue than in my earlier work. I also offer new considerations on subsisting issues of interpretation concerning Tarski’s views on the logical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Truth, reflection, and hierarchies.Michael Glanzberg - 2005 - Synthese 142 (3):289 - 315.
    A common objection to hierarchical approaches to truth is that they fragment the concept of truth. This paper defends hierarchical approaches in general against the objection of fragmentation. It argues that the fragmentation required is familiar and unprob-lematic, via a comparison with mathematical proof. Furthermore, it offers an explanation of the source and nature of the fragmentation of truth. Fragmentation arises because the concept exhibits a kind of failure of closure under reflection. This paper offers a more precise characterization of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • No facts without perspectives.Ramiro Glauer & Frauke Hildebrandt - 2020 - Synthese 199 (1-2):3825-3851.
    Perner and Roessler Causing human action: new perspectives on the causal theory of action, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 199–228, 2010) hold that children who do not yet have an understanding of subjective perspectives, i.e., mental states, explain actions by appealing to objective facts. In this paper, we criticize this view. We argue that in order to understand objective facts, subjects need to understand perspectives. By analysing basic fact-expressing assertions, we show that subjects cannot refer to facts if they do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Circularity, Definition and Truth.Michael Glanzberg - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):465-470.
    This is a collection of eighteen solicited papers on the topics of the title: circularity, definition, and truth. The papers are loosely connected in subject matter, but present a great variety of issues, theories, and approaches. Amongst the many subjects discussed are: the revision theory of truth and applications of revision rules, partiality and fixed point constructions, substitutional quantification, fuzzy logic, negation, belief revision, context dependence, hierarchies, Tarski on truth, deflationism, correspondence theories of truth, and normative aspects of truth. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A contextual–hierarchical approach to truth and the liar paradox.Michael Glanzberg - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (1):27-88.
    This paper presents an approach to truth and the Liar paradox which combines elements of context dependence and hierarchy. This approach is developed formally, using the techniques of model theory in admissible sets. Special attention is paid to showing how starting with some ideas about context drawn from linguistics and philosophy of language, we can see the Liar sentence to be context dependent. Once this context dependence is properly understood, it is argued, a hierarchical structure emerges which is neither ad (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Book Review: Keith Simmons. Universality and the Liar: An Essay on Truth and the Diagonal Argument. [REVIEW]Gian Aldo Antonelli - 1996 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 37 (1):152-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Incompleteness and truth definitions.G. Germano - 1971 - Theoria 37 (1):86-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two conceptions of truth? – Comment.V. Mc Gee - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 124 (1):71 - 104.
    Following Hartry Field in distinguishing disquotational truth from a conception that grounds truth conditions in a community's usage, it is argued that the notions are materially inequivalent (since the latter allows truth-value gaps) and that both are needed. In addition to allowing blanket endorsements ("Everything the Pope says is true"), disquotational truth facilitates mathematical discovery, as when we establish the Gödel sentence by noting that the theorems are all disquotationally true and the disquotational truths are consistent. We require a more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Ethical Nature of Karl Popper’s Solution to the Problem of Rationality.Stefano Gattei - 2002 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 32 (2):240-266.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations