Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Nicomachean Ethics

(ed.)
New York, N.Y.: Oxford University Press UK (1926)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Virtue Lost: Courage in Sport.John Corlett - 1996 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 23 (1):45-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Bearing and transcending suffering with nature and the world: a humanistic account.Rosa Hong Chen - 2011 - Journal of Moral Education 40 (2):203-216.
    To conceptualise moral education as ‘living and learning to bear suffering’ offers a humanistic vision for choices people make in the face of drastic threats to their existence. This essay proposes that bearing and transcending suffering—part of the human narrative—helps human beings to realise their ethical potential. Grounded in Eastern and Western metaphysics and ethics, I assess the human condition brought about by the 2008 earthquake disaster in China—in an attempt to come to terms with fundamental philosophical questions of existence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Virtue Ethics and Digital 'Flourishing': An Application of Philippa Foot to Life Online.Patrick Lee Plaisance - 2013 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 28 (2):91-102.
    The neo-Aristotelian virtue theory of Philippa Foot is presented here as an alternative framework that is arguably more useful than deontological approaches and that relies less on the assertions of moral claims about the intrinsic goodness of foundational principles. Instead, this project focuses more on cultivating a true ethic; that is, a set of tools and propositions to enable individuals to negotiate inevitable conflicts among moral values and challenges posed by cultural contexts and technology use. Foot's ?natural normativity? connects the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Responsibility in Childhood: Three Developmental Trajectories.Elinor Ochs & Carolina Izquierdo - 2009 - Ethos: Journal of the Society for Psychological Anthropology 37 (4):391-413.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The notion of the moral: the relation between virtue ethics and virtue epistemology.Christine Swanton - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 171 (1):121-134.
    In this paper I argue that virtue ethics should be understood as a form of ethics which integrates various domains of the practical in relation to which virtues are excellences. To argue this it is necessary to distinguish two senses of the “moral”: the broad sense which integrates the domains of the practical and a narrow classificatory sense. Virtue ethics, understood as above, believes that all genuine virtue should be understood as what I call virtues proper. To possess a virtue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are Human Rights Redundant in the Ethical Codes of Psychologists?Alfred Allan - 2013 - Ethics and Behavior 23 (4):251-265.
    The codes of ethics and conduct of a number of psychology bodies explicitly refer to human rights, and the American Psychological Association recently expanded the use of the construct when it amended standard 1.02 of the Ethical Principles of Psychologists and Code of Conduct. What is unclear is how these references to human rights should be interpreted. In this article I examine the historical development of human rights and associated constructs and the contemporary meaning of human rights. As human rights (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The ‘Physically Educated’ Person: Physical education in the philosophy of Reid, Peters and Aristotle.James MacAllister - 2013 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 45 (9):908-920.
    This article will derive a definition and account of the physically educated person, through an examination of the philosophy of Andrew Reid, Richard Peters and Aristotle. Initially, Reid’s interpretation of Peters’ views about the educational significance of practical knowledge (and physical education) will be considered. While it will be acknowledged that Peters was rather disparaging about the educational merit of some practical activities in Ethics and Education, it will be argued that he elsewhere suggests that such practical activities could be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Towards an evidence‐based 'Medicine of the Person': the contribution of psychiatry to health care provision.John L. Cox - 2008 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 14 (5):694-698.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Searching for excellence in education: knowledge, virtue and presence?James MacAllister, Gale Macleod & Anne Pirrie - 2013 - Ethics and Education 8 (2):153-165.
    This article addresses two main questions: what is excellence and should epistemic excellence be the main purpose of education? Though references to excellence have become increasingly frequent in the UK education policy, these questions are perhaps especially important in Scotland where the curriculum is explicitly for excellence. Following Hirst and Peters, it is hypothesised that if the term ‘education’ implies possession of a certain breadth of general knowledge and understanding, then the term ‘excellence’ may imply a deep grasp of a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Philia and pedagogy ‘side by side’: the perils and promise of teacher–student friendships.Amy B. Shuffelton - 2012 - Ethics and Education 7 (3):211-223.
    . Philia and pedagogy ‘side by side’: the perils and promise of teacher–student friendships. Ethics and Education: Vol. 7, Creating spaces, pp. 211-223. doi: 10.1080/17449642.2013.766541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Civic and Cosmopolitan Friendship.Kerri Woods - 2013 - Res Publica 19 (1):81-94.
    This article draws out two implications for cosmopolitan or global friendship from an examination of a recent work on civic friendship in the domestic sphere: (1) Insofar as it is the case that civic friendship, as defined by Schwarzenbach (On civic friendship: Including women in the state. Columbia University Press, New York, 2009) is necessary for justice in the state, it is also the case that the absence of global justice can be partially explained by the absence of what might (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Augustine's On the Good of Marriage and Infused Virtue in the Twelfth Century.Bonnie Kent - 2013 - Journal of Religious Ethics 41 (1):112-136.
    In the history of ethics, it remains remains unclear how Christians of the Middle Ages came to see God-given virtues as dispositions (habitus) created in the human soul. Patristic works could surely support other conceptions of the virtues given by grace. For example, one might argue that all such virtues are forms of charity, so that they must be affections of the soul, or that they consist in what the soul does, not anything the soul has. Scholars usually assume that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Moral Agency of Computers.Thomas M. Powers - 2013 - Topoi 32 (2):227-236.
    Can computer systems ever be considered moral agents? This paper considers two factors that are explored in the recent philosophical literature. First, there are the important domains in which computers are allowed to act, made possible by their greater functional capacities. Second, there is the claim that these functional capacities appear to embody relevant human abilities, such as autonomy and responsibility. I argue that neither the first (Domain-Function) factor nor the second (Simulacrum) factor gets at the central issue in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • How shall i compare thee? Comparing the prudential value of actual virtual friendship.Johnny Hartz Søraker - 2012 - Ethics and Information Technology 14 (3):209-219.
    It has become commonplace to hold the view that virtual surrogates for the things that are good in life are inferior to their actual, authentic counterparts, including virtual education, virtual skill-demanding activities and virtual acts of creativity. Virtual friendship has also been argued to be inferior to traditional, embodied forms of friendship. Coupled with the view that virtual friendships threaten to replace actual ones, the conclusion is often made that we ought to concentrate our efforts on actual friendships rather than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Fair or Temple: Two Possibilities for Olympic Sport.Irena Martínková - 2012 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 6 (2):166-182.
    This paper is based on the work of Pierre de Coubertin and his view of Olympism. It deals with Coubertin's distinction between two kinds of sport: Olympic sport and world championship sport. I shall examine these two possibilities with respect both to education through sport and to how one lives one's life, and I shall show the necessity of choosing between them, with reference to Coubertin's closing remarks in his speech at the 1925 Olympic Congress in Prague: ?Fair or temple (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Virtue Epistemology and the Philosophy of Education.James Macallister - 2012 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 46 (2):251-270.
    This article initially provides a brief overview of virtue epistemology; it thereafter considers some possible ramifications of this branch of the theory of knowledge for the philosophy of education. The main features of three different manifestations of virtue epistemology are first explained. Importantly, it is then maintained that developments in virtue epistemology may offer the resources to critique aspects of the debate between Hirst and Carr about how the philosophy of education ought to be carried out and by whom. Wilfred (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Moral Shallowness, Metaphysical Megalomania, and Compatibilist-Fatalism.Stefaan E. Cuypers - 2013 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 16 (1):173-188.
    In the debate on free will and moral responsibility, Saul Smilansky is a hard source-incompatibilist who objects to source-compatibilism for being morally shallow. After criticizing John Martin Fischer’s too optimistic response to this objection, this paper dissipates the charge that compatibilist accounts of ultimate origination are morally shallow by appealing to the seriousness of contingency in the framework of, what Paul Russell calls, compatibilist-fatalism. Responding to the objection from moral shallowness thus drives a wedge between optimists and fatalists within the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Habituation: A Method for Cultivating Starting Points in the Ethical Life.Jeannie Kerr - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 45 (4):643-655.
    The Aristotelian concept of habituation is receiving mounting and warranted interest in educational circles, but has also been subject to different lines of interpretation and critique. In this article, I bring forward Aristotle's words on habituation, and then clarify the two lines of interpretation that have developed in the contemporary philosophical literature. I argue that the mechanical interpretation contains an intellectualist bias and then argue a cognitivist view that positions habituation as the only method appropriate to cultivating the starting points (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Eudaimonist Virtue Ethics and Right Action: A Reassessment.Frans Svensson - 2011 - The Journal of Ethics 15 (4):321-339.
    My question in this paper concerns what eudaimonist virtue ethics (EVE) might have to say about what makes right actions right. This is obviously an important question if we want to know what (if anything) distinguishes EVE from various forms of consequentialism and deontology in ethical theorizing. The answer most commonly given is that according to EVE, an action is right if and only if it is what a virtuous person would do in the circumstances. However, understood as a claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Expertise as Argument: Authority, Democracy, and Problem-Solving. [REVIEW]Zoltan P. Majdik & William M. Keith - 2011 - Argumentation 25 (3):371-384.
    This article addresses the problem of expertise in a democratic political system: the tension between the authority of expertise and the democratic values that guide political life. We argue that for certain problems, expertise needs to be understood as a dialogical process, and we conceptualize an understanding of expertise through and as argument that positions expertise as constituted by and a function of democratic values and practices, rather than in the possession of, acquisition of, or relationship to epistemic materials. Conceptualizing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Holding an Aristotelian Mirror to Confucian Ethics?Yang Xiao - 2011 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 10 (3):359-375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Subjectivity and Universality of Virtues—An Investigation Based on Confucius’ and Aristotle’s Views.Shenbai Liao - 2011 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 6 (2):217-238.
    Philosophers today are inclined to propose virtues are either something subjective or something universal. However, Confucius and Aristotle, who made the most profound investigations into virtues, did not develop such theses. The deep-seated reason lies in their belief that there is always a possibility for a human being to become a man of practice, which cancels the need of proposing subjectivity thesis. The reason for their not raising the universality thesis of virtues is that they do not think that virtues (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Secular Spirituality and the Logic of Giving Thanks.John Bishop - 2010 - Sophia 49 (4):523-534.
    Some atheists are attracted to the idea of a secular spirituality that carries no commitment to the existence of God or anything similar. Is this a coherent possibility? This paper seeks to define what we mean by a ‘spirituality’ by examining Robert C. Solomon’s defence of spirituality for the religious skeptic, and pursues the question of its coherence by reflecting on what is implied by taking thankfulness to be a proper response to our existence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The source of the idea of equality in Confucian thought.Ruiquan Gao - 2010 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 5 (4):486-505.
    Although the traditional society in China was not necessarily a society of equality, and the classical Confucianism did not speak much about the principle of universal equality, in modern times, in the midst of a transformation of value systems, people still find correlating sources within the Confucian tradition that is connected to the modern idea of equality. This essay makes a detailed study on this correlation and points out that ancient Chinese society and the western feudal society are different in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • One Hundred Years since Hart's Birth.Enrico Pattaro - 2007 - Ratio Juris 20 (4):559-574.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human individuality and the gap between science and religion.Steven Reiss - 2005 - Zygon 40 (1):131-142.
    . Personality may play a role in disputes between religion and science. Personality is influenced by sixteen basic desires and core values, which provide the psychological foundation of meaningful experience. How we prioritize these sixteen desires is what makes us individuals. Religious persons may place a low priority on the desire for self‐reliance , whereas nonreligious scientists may place a high priority on self‐reliance. These differences may motivate religious persons to find meaning in images of psychologically supportive deities and may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Sixteen Strivings for God.Steven Reiss - 2004 - Zygon 39 (2):303-320.
    . A psychological theory of religious experiences, sensitivity theory, is proposed. Whereas other theories maintain that religious motivation is about a few overarching desires, sensitivity theory provides a multifaceted analysis consistent with the diversity, richness, and individuality of religious experiences. Sixteen basic desires show the psychological foundations of meaningful experience. Each basic desire is embraced by every person, but to different extents. How we prioritize the basic desires expresses our individuality and influences our attraction to various religious images and activities. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Cultivation of Moral Character: A Buddhist Challenge to Social Workers.Bjarne Øvrelid - 2008 - Ethics and Social Welfare 2 (3):243-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Using phronesis instead of 'research-based practice' as the guiding light for nursing practice.Don Flaming - 2001 - Nursing Philosophy 2 (3):251-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Technical rationality in Schön’s reflective practice: dichotomous or non‐dualistic epistemological position.Elizabeth Anne Kinsella - 2007 - Nursing Philosophy 8 (2):102-113.
    Donald Schön’s theory of reflective practice has received unprecedented attention as an approach to professional development in nursing and other health and social care professions. This paper examines technical rationality in Schön’s theory of reflective practice and argues that its critique is a broad and often overlooked epistemological underpinning in this work. This paper suggests that the popularity of Schön’s theory is tied in part to his critique of technical rationality, and to his acknowledgement of the significance of practitioner experience (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Atrocity Paradigm Revisited.Claudia Card - 2004 - Hypatia 19 (4):212 - 222.
    This essay reflects on issues raised by commentators regarding my book, The Atrocity Paradigm: A Theory of Evil (Oxford 2002). They are (1) Robin Schott's observation of the tension between my discussion of forgiveness and of castration fantasies; (2) Bat-Ami Bar On's questions regarding whether evil is ethical, political, or both; (3) Adam Morton's queries regarding the relative seriousness of evils and injustices; and (4) María Pía Lara's concerns regarding what is valuable in Kant's ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Theory of the Firm.John Dobson - 1994 - Economics and Philosophy 10 (1):73.
    I carved a massive cake of beeswax into bits and rolled them in my hands until they softened … Going forward I carried wax along the line, and laid it thick on their ears. They tied me up, then, plumb amidships, back to the mast, lashed to the mast, and took themselves again to rowing. Soon, as we came smartly within hailing distance, the two Sirens, noting our fast ship off their point, made ready, and they sang … The lovely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflection and moral maturity in a nurse's caring practice: A critical perspective.Jane Sumner - 2010 - Nursing Philosophy 11 (3):159-169.
    The likelihood of nurse reflection is examined from the theoretical perspectives of Habermas' Theory of Communicative Action and Moral Action and Sumner's Moral Construct of Caring in Nursing as Communicative Action, through a critical social theory lens. The argument is made that until the nurse reaches the developmental level of post-conventional moral maturity and/or Benner's Stage 5: expert, he or she is not capable of being inwardly directed reflective on self. The three developmental levels of moral maturity and Benner's stages (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • After Kohlberg: Virtue ethics and the recovery of the moral self.Vincent A. Punzo - 1996 - Philosophical Psychology 9 (1):7 – 23.
    A resurgence of interest in virtue ethics has engendered new insight into the fundamental link between selfhood and morality. In contradistinction to the currently ascendant justice-reasoning research paradigm, it appears that a virtue ethics approach to moral psychology provides a theoretical framework which is amenable to the empirical investigation of the nature and formation of the moral self. Six primary features of virtue ethics are delineated with a unifying emphasis throughout on the inextricable link between virtue and moral selfhood. Questions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The cultural roots of professional wisdom: Towards a broader view of teacher expertise.David Carr & Don Skinner - 2009 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 41 (2):141-154.
    Perhaps the most pressing issue concerning teacher education and training since the end of the Second World War has been that of the role of theory—or principled reflection—in professional expertise. Here, although the main post-war architects of a new educational professionalism clearly envisaged a key role for theory—considering such disciplines as psychology, sociology and philosophy as indispensable for reflective practice—there are nevertheless well-rehearsed difficulties about crediting such disciplines with quite the (applied) role in educational practice of (say) physiology or anatomy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dialectics and practical wisdom.Nanshi Wang - 2006 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 1 (2):245-253.
    Dialectics is essentially the method or logos in which categories of forms are combined to explain things. Dialectics was developed because reason faces difficulties in grasping the sensible world. Practical wisdom is knowledge about some things or certain person or persons because of its variable objects. But it is not entirely specific or only about a particular thing and without universality in any sense. As one kind of dialectics, it combines various elements to accord with the right logos, similar to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ethics in business and administration: An international and historical perspective. [REVIEW]Michael W. Small - 1993 - Journal of Business Ethics 12 (4):293 - 300.
    This is a study of ethical and moral behavior, or perhaps unethical behavior, in two different societies. One society, contemporary Australia and in particular the state of Western Australia, is currently undergoing an exhaustive Royal Commission into the shenanigans of a number of well-known business men and former leading politicians who seem to have been playing fast and loose with large amounts of other peoples' money. While this was initially the major focus of the paper, a secondary focus developed based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Just price and equal opportunity.Claes Hägg - 1983 - Journal of Business Ethics 2 (4):269-272.
    The purpose of this paper is to investigate if just price could be given a precise and relevant definition. First, the historical background is sketched. Then a definition is formulated which is based on a gradual interpretation of possibility. The meaning of the definition is, that the buyer and the seller are given equal opportunity of reaching a justified standard of living.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The body disciplined: Rewriting teaching competence and the doctrine of reflection.Peter Erlandson - 2005 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 39 (4):661–670.
    Shortly after the publication of The Reflective Practitioner (1983) and the sequel Educating the Reflective Practitioner (1987) ‘reflection-in-action’ became a major concept in teacher education. The concept has, however, been criticised on ontological/epistemological as well as practice oriented accounts (Van Manen, 1995; Newman, 1999; Erlandson, 1995). In this paper I argue that reflection-in-action is a theoretical construction that snatches the interacting, working, and producing bodies from their practices, and consequently, matters of politics, of discipline, of institutional interaction and of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Towards a phenomenology of ethical expertise.Hubert L. Dreyfus & Stuart E. Dreyfus - 1991 - Human Studies 14 (4):229 - 250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • What is an educational practice?Wilfred Carr - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 21 (2):163–175.
    Wilfred Carr; What is an Educational Practice?, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 21, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 163–175, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Theories of theory and practice.Wilfred Carr - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 20 (2):177–186.
    Wilfred Carr; Theories of Theory and Practice, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 20, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 177–186, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Critical theory and educational studies.Wilfred Carr - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 21 (2):287–295.
    Wilfred Carr; Critical Theory and Educational Studies, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 21, Issue 2, 30 May 2006, Pages 287–295, https://doi.org/10.11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations