Switch to: References

Citations of:

From Frege to Gödel

Cambridge,: Harvard University Press (1967)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Intuitionistic mathematics and wittgenstein.Wenceslao J. Gonzalez - 1991 - History and Philosophy of Logic 12 (2):167-183.
    The relation between Wittgenstein's philosophy of mathematics and mathematical Intuitionism has raised a considerable debate. My attempt is to analyse if there is a commitment in Wittgenstein to themes characteristic of the intuitionist movement in Mathematics and if that commitment is one important strain that runs through his Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. The intuitionistic themes to analyse in his philosophy of mathematics are: firstly, his attacks on the unrestricted use of the Law of Excluded Middle; secondly, his distrust (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Frege on sense identity.J. Van Heijenoort - 1977 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1):103-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Le « Wittgenstein intermédiaire » et les mathématiques modernes.Sören Stenlund & Anne-Marie Boisvert - 2012 - Philosophiques 39 (1):125-161.
    Dans cet article, j’essaie de montrer que le dépassement et le rejet du dogmatisme sont un aspect décisif du changement dans la pensée de Wittgenstein qui a eu lieu au début des années 30, quand il commence à mettre en valeur l’autonomie de la grammaire du langage et à parler d’images grammaticales et de jeux de langage en tant qu’objets de comparaison. En examinant certains traits fondamentaux de ce changement, je mettrai en évidence l’impulsion et les idées décisives que Wittgenstein (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paradoxes of denotation.Keith Simmons - 1994 - Philosophical Studies 76 (1):71 - 106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Ways of Hilbert's Axiomatics: Structural and Formal.Wilfried Sieg - 2014 - Perspectives on Science 22 (1):133-157.
    It is a remarkable fact that Hilbert's programmatic papers from the 1920s still shape, almost exclusively, the standard contemporary perspective of his views concerning (the foundations of) mathematics; even his own, quite different work on the foundations of geometry and arithmetic from the late 1890s is often understood from that vantage point. My essay pursues one main goal, namely, to contrast Hilbert's formal axiomatic method from the early 1920s with his existential axiomatic approach from the 1890s. Such a contrast illuminates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Reasoning, logic and computation.Stewart Shapiro - 1995 - Philosophia Mathematica 3 (1):31-51.
    The idea that logic and reasoning are somehow related goes back to antiquity. It clearly underlies much of the work in logic, as witnessed by the development of computability, and formal and mechanical deductive systems, for example. On the other hand, a platitude is that logic is the study of correct reasoning; and reasoning is cognitive if anything Is. Thus, the relationship between logic, computation, and correct reasoning makes an interesting and historically central case study for mechanism. The purpose of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Pasch’s philosophy of mathematics.Dirk Schlimm - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):93-118.
    Moritz Pasch (1843ber neuere Geometrie (1882), in which he also clearly formulated the view that deductions must be independent from the meanings of the nonlogical terms involved. Pasch also presented in these lectures the main tenets of his philosophy of mathematics, which he continued to elaborate on throughout the rest of his life. This philosophy is quite unique in combining a deductivist methodology with a radically empiricist epistemology for mathematics. By taking into consideration publications from the entire span of Paschs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Wittgenstein's inversion of gödel's theorem.Victor Rodych - 1999 - Erkenntnis 51 (2-3):173-206.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Peirce's Truth-functional Analysis and the Origin of the Truth Table.Irving H. Anellis - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (1):87 - 97.
    We explore the technical details and historical evolution of Charles Peirce's articulation of a truth table in 1893, against the background of his investigation into the truth-functional analysis of propositions involving implication. In 1997, John Shosky discovered, on the verso of a page of the typed transcript of Bertrand Russell's 1912 lecture on ?The Philosophy of Logical Atomism? truth table matrices. The matrix for negation is Russell's, alongside of which is the matrix for material implication in the hand of Ludwig (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Klassinen matematiikka ja logiikka.Panu Raatikainen - 1996 - In Christoffer Gefwert (ed.), Logiikka, matematiikka ja tietokone – Perusteet: historiaa, filosofiaa ja sovelluksia. Finnish Artificial Intelligence Society.
    Toisaalta ennennäkemätön äärettömien joukko-opillisten menetelmien hyödyntäminen sekä toisaalta epäilyt niiden hyväksyttävyydestä ja halu oikeuttaa niiden käyttö ovat ratkaisevasti muovanneet vuosisatamme matematiikkaa ja logiikkaa. Tämän kehityksen vaikutus nykyajan filosofiaan on myös ollut valtaisa; merkittävää osaa siitä ei voi edes ymmärtää tuntematta sen yhteyttä tähän matematiikan ja logiikan vallankumoukseen. Lähestymistapoja, jotka tavalla tai toisella hyväksyvät äärettömän matematiikan ja perinteisten logiikan sääntöjen (erityisesti kolmannen poissuljetun lain) soveltamisen myös sen piirissä, on tullut tavaksi kutsua klassiseksi matematiikaksi ja logiikaksi erotuksena nämä hylkäävistä radikaaleista intuitionistisista ja (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zermelo: Boundary numbers and domains of sets continued.Heinz-Dieter Ebbinghaus - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (4):285-306.
    Towards the end of his 1930 paper on boundary numbers and domains of sets Zermelo briefly discusses the questions of consistency and of the existence of an unbounded sequence of strongly inaccessible cardinals, deferring a detailed discussion to a later paper which never appeared. In a report to the Emergency Community of German Science from December 1930 about investigations in progress he mentions that some of the intended extensions of these topics had been worked out and were nearly ready for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mathematical roots of phenomenology: Husserl and the concept of number.Mirja Hartimo - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (4):319-337.
    The paper examines the roots of Husserlian phenomenology in Weierstrass's approach to analysis. After elaborating on Weierstrass's programme of arithmetization of analysis, the paper examines Husserl's Philosophy of Arithmetic as an attempt to provide foundations to analysis. The Philosophy of Arithmetic consists of two parts; the first discusses authentic arithmetic and the second symbolic arithmetic. Husserl's novelty is to use Brentanian descriptive analysis to clarify the fundamental concepts of arithmetic in the first part. In the second part, he founds the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On signing translation.Floyd Merrell - 2005 - Semiotica 2005 (157):539-570.
    1. Setting the stage Dinda Gorlée’s seminal On Translating Signs explores translation of texts under the guise of ‘semio-translation.’ In her previous book, Semiotics and the Problem of Translation, Gorlée originally coined the term semiotranslation, which subsequently gained some notoriety in translation theory circles. She sees no need to give up the term, in fact including it in hyphenated form in the subtitle of the book under review. For, semio-translation ‘retains an ongoing excitement and creates a niche in semiotic and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hilbert's Axiomatics as ‘Symbolic Form’?Rossella Lupacchini - 2014 - Perspectives on Science 22 (1):1-34.
    Both Hilbert's axiomatics and Cassirer's philosophy of symbolic forms have their roots in Leibniz's idea of a 'universal characteristic,' and grow on Hertz's 'principles of mechanics,' and Dedekind's 'foundations of arithmetic'. As Cassirer recalls in the introduction to his Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, it was the discovery of the analysis of infinity that led Leibniz to focus on "the universal problem inherent in the function of symbolism, and to raise his 'universal characteristic' to a truly philosophical plane." In Leibniz's view, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Natural Variant of Ackermann's Function.Hilbert Levitz & Warren Nichols - 1988 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 34 (5):399-401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Natural Variant of Ackermann's Function.Hilbert Levitz & Warren Nichols - 1988 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 34 (5):399-401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Comparatives in Context: Vallée on Relative Gradable Adjectives.Kepa Korta - 2022 - Disputatio 14 (66):239-255.
    In “Unarticulated Comparison Classes” 2018 [2009], Richard Vallée adopts John Perry’s (2012 [2001]) reflexive-referential theory of meaning and content as well as his concept of unarticulated constituents (Perry 1986) to deal with certain context-sensitive elements of the truth-conditions of statements containing relative gradable predicates. I am sympathetic both with the general framework and with the assumption that unarticulated constituents are involved in the truth-conditions of bare positives such as “Monica is tall.” I do not share, however, Vallée’s main conclusions on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychology in the foundations of logic and mathematics: the cases of boole, cantor and brouwer.I. Grattan-Guinness - 1982 - History and Philosophy of Logic 3 (1):33-53.
    In this paper I consider three mathematicians who allowed some role for menial processes in the foundations of their logical or mathematical theories. Boole regarded his Boolean algebra as a theory of mental acts; Cantor permitted processes of abstraction to play a role in his set theory; Brouwer took perception in time as a cornerstone of his intuitionist mathematics. Three appendices consider related topics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The manuscripts of emil L. post.I. Grattan-Guinness - 1990 - History and Philosophy of Logic 11 (1):77-83.
    Post's Nachlass has recently been made available to the public in an archive in the U.S.A. After a short summary of his life and career, this article indicates the character and content of the manuscripts, and their significance is assessed. Two short passages are transcribed; and. as a separate item, a paper of the 1930s on the paradoxes is reproduced.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On the Exhaustion of Mathematical Entities by Structures.Adrian Heathcote - 2014 - Axiomathes 24 (2):167-180.
    There has been considerable discussion in the literature of one kind of identity problem that mathematical structuralism faces: the automorphism problem, in which the structure is unable to individuate the mathematical entities in its domain. Shapiro (Philos Math 16(3):285–309, 2008) has partly responded to these concerns. But I argue here that the theory faces an even more serious kind of identity problem, which the theory can’t overcome staying within its remit. I give two examples to make the point.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Towards a theory of mathematical research programmes (II).Michael Hallett - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (2):135-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The truth and nothing but the truth, yet never the whole truth: Frege, Russell and the analysis of unities.Graham Stevens - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (3):221-240.
    It is widely assumed that Russell's problems with the unity of the proposition were recurring and insoluble within the framework of the logical theory of his Principles of Mathematics. By contrast, Frege's functional analysis of thoughts (grounded in a type-theoretic distinction between concepts and objects) is commonly assumed to provide a solution to the problem or, at least, a means of avoiding the difficulty altogether. The Fregean solution is unavailable to Russell because of his commitment to the thesis that there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Hilbert's philosophy of mathematics.Marcus Giaquinto - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (2):119-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Finitistic Arithmetic and Classical Logic.Mihai Ganea - 2014 - Philosophia Mathematica 22 (2):167-197.
    It can be argued that only the equational theories of some sub-elementary function algebras are finitistic or intuitive according to a certain interpretation of Hilbert's conception of intuition. The purpose of this paper is to investigate the relation of those restricted forms of equational reasoning to classical quantifier logic in arithmetic. The conclusion reached is that Edward Nelson's ‘predicative arithmetic’ program, which makes essential use of classical quantifier logic, cannot be justified finitistically and thus requires a different philosophical foundation, possibly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Gödelian Inferences.Curtis Franks - 2009 - History and Philosophy of Logic 30 (3):241-256.
    I attribute an 'intensional reading' of the second incompleteness theorem to its author, Kurt G del. My argument builds partially on an analysis of intensional and extensional conceptions of meta-mathematics and partially on the context in which G del drew two familiar inferences from his theorem. Those inferences, and in particular the way that they appear in G del's writing, are so dubious on the extensional conception that one must doubt that G del could have understood his theorem extensionally. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cut as Consequence.Curtis Franks - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (4):349-379.
    The papers where Gerhard Gentzen introduced natural deduction and sequent calculi suggest that his conception of logic differs substantially from the now dominant views introduced by Hilbert, Gödel, Tarski, and others. Specifically, (1) the definitive features of natural deduction calculi allowed Gentzen to assert that his classical system nk is complete based purely on the sort of evidence that Hilbert called ?experimental?, and (2) the structure of the sequent calculi li and lk allowed Gentzen to conceptualize completeness as a question (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The good, the bad and the ugly.Philip Ebert & Stewart Shapiro - 2009 - Synthese 170 (3):415-441.
    This paper discusses the neo-logicist approach to the foundations of mathematics by highlighting an issue that arises from looking at the Bad Company objection from an epistemological perspective. For the most part, our issue is independent of the details of any resolution of the Bad Company objection and, as we will show, it concerns other foundational approaches in the philosophy of mathematics. In the first two sections, we give a brief overview of the "Scottish" neo-logicist school, present a generic form (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Many-Valued Logics and Translations.Ítala M. Loffredo D'Ottaviano & Hércules de Araujo Feitosa - 1999 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 9 (1):121-140.
    This work presents the concepts of translation and conservative translation between logics. By using algebraic semantics we introduce several conservative translations involving the classical propositional calculus and the many-valued calculi of Post and Lukasiewicz.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Frege‘s Context Principle: its Role and Interpretation.Sorin Costreie - 2010 - Logos and Episteme 1 (2):287-301.
    The paper focuses on Gottlob Frege’s so called Context Principle (CP hereafter), which counts as one of the most controversial points of his philosophy. Due to its importance and centrality in Frege’s thought, a detailed discussion of the principle requires a detailed analysis of almost all aspects of his philosophy. Obviously, such a task cannot be successfully accomplished here. Thus I limit myself to address only two questions concerning the CP: what role does the principle play (in Grundlagen) and how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy and its children: logic, computation, and the emergence of natural and social science: Soames, Scott, The World Philosophy Made: From Plato to the digital age, Princeton University Press, 2019, xviii + 439 pages.John P. Burgess - 2021 - Philosophical Studies 179 (6):2087-2095.
    The middle chapters of Soames’s The World Philosophy Made are briefly summarized and examined. There are some local slips, but globally the work displays an impressive knowledge of and a distinctive viewpoint on a wide range of important intellectual disciplines and their original roots in and continuing connections with philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On some interpretations of classical logic.Branislav R. Boričić & B. R. Boričić - 1992 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 38 (1):409-412.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reflective inquiry and “The Fate of Reason”.William Boos - 2014 - Synthese 191 (18):4253-4314.
    What particular privilege has this little Agitation of the Brain which we call Thought, that we must make it the Model of the whole Universe? (Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, 1976, p. 168)******...at once it struck me, what quality went to form a Man (sic) of Achievement especially in Literature and which Shakespeare possessed so enormously—I mean Negative Capability, that is when someone is capable of being in uncertainties, Mysteries, doubts without any irritable reaching after fact and reason. (Keats 1959, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Weak and Post completeness in the Hilbert school.Víctor Aranda - 2019 - Humanities Journal of Valparaiso 14:449-466.
    The aim of this paper is to clarify why propositional logic is Post complete and its weak completeness was almost unnoticed by Hilbert and Bernays, while first-order logic is Post incomplete and its weak completeness was seen as an open problem by Hilbert and Ackermman. Thus, I will compare propositional and first-order logic in the Prinzipien der Mathematik, Bernays’s second Habilitationsschrift and the Grundzüge der Theoretischen Logik. The so called “arithmetical interpretation”, the conjunctive and disjunctive normal forms and the soundness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conceptions and paradoxes of sets.G. Aldo Antonelli - 1999 - Philosophia Mathematica 7 (2):136-163.
    This paper is concerned with the way different axiom systems for set theory can be justified by appeal to such intuitions as limitation of size, predicativity, stratification, etc. While none of the different conceptions historically resulting from the impetus to provide a solution to the paradoxes turns out to rest on an intuition providing an unshakeable foundation,'each supplies a picture of the set-theoretic universe that is both useful and internally well motivated. The same is true of more recently proposed axiom (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Origins of the Use of the Argument of Trivialization in the Twentieth Century.M. Andrés Bobenrieth - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (2):111-121.
    The origin of paraconsistent logic is closely related with the argument, ‘from the assertion of two mutually contradictory statements any other statement can be deduced’; this can be referred to as ex contradictione sequitur quodlibet (ECSQ). Despite its medieval origin, only by the 1930s did it become the main reason for the unfeasibility of having contradictions in a deductive system. The purpose of this article is to study what happened earlier: from Principia Mathematica to that time, when it became well (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • ALONZO: Deduktionsagenten höherer Ordnung für Mathematische Assistenzsysteme.Benzmüller Christoph - 2003
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark