Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Spatial motion perception requires the perception of distance.Michael Swanston - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):334-334.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Sensory” reference frames and the information for self-motion versus object motion.Thomas A. Stoffregen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):332-333.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Does the reference signal cancel visual field motion?Arnold E. Stoper - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):333-334.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computation without representation.Stephen P. Stich - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):152-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Computation and symbolization.William E. Smythe - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):151-152.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Whither cross-cultural perception?Daniel W. Smothergill - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):93-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What kind of indirect process is visual perception?Aaron Sloman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):401-404.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The idea that space perception involves more than eye movement signals and the position of the retinal image has come up before.Alexander A. Skavenski - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):331-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ecological efference mediation theory and motion perception during self-motion.Wayne L. Shebilske - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):330-331.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Abstract machine theory and direct perception.Robert Shaw & James Todd - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):400-401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Luminance controls the perceived 3-D structure of dynamic 2-D displays.Barry J. Schwartz & George Sperling - 1983 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 21 (6):456-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What does linear vection tell us about the optokinetic pathway?Xavier M. Sauvan - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):330-330.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There is more to psychological meaningfulness than computation and representation.Sverker Runeson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):399-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Spinning Shadows.Roy Sorensen - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2):345 - 365.
    If a spinning sphere casts a shadow, does the shadow also spin? This riddle is the point of departure for an investigation into the nature of shadow movement. A general theory of motion will encompass all moving things, not just physical objects. Ultimately, I argue that round shadows do indeed spin. Shadows are followers of the objects that cast them. Parts of the shadow correspond to parts of the leader, so motion of the caster's parts accounts for motions of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Many a slip 'twixt external and internal representation.David Rose - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):93-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Active and passive head and body movements.Helen E. Ross - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):329-330.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Some puzzling findings in multiple object tracking (MOT): II. Inhibition of moving nontargets.Zenon Pylyshyn - manuscript
    We present three studies examining whether multiple-object tracking (MOT) benefits from the active inhibition of nontargets, as proposed in (Pylyshyn, 2004). Using a probedot technique, the first study showed poorer probe detection on nontargets than on either the targets being tracked or in the empty space between objects. The second study used a matching nontracking task to control for possible masking of probes, independent of target tracking. The third study examined how localized the inhibition is to individual nontargets. The result (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Difficulties with a direct theory of perception.Irvin Rock - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):398-399.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • On time, memory and dynamic form.Stephen E. Robbins - 2004 - Consciousness and Cognition 13 (4):762-788.
    A common approach to explaining the perception of form is through the use of static features. The weakness of this approach points naturally to dynamic definitions of form. Considering dynamical form, however, leads inevitably to the need to explain how events are perceived as time-extended—a problem with primacy over that even of qualia. Optic flow models, energy models, models reliant on a rigidity constraint are examined. The reliance of these models on the instantaneous specification of form at an instant, t, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Functional architecture and model validation.Martin Ringle - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):150-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ego-centered and environment-centered perceptions of self-movement.John J. Rieser - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):328-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception of motion with respect to multiple criteria.Gary E. Riccio - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):326-328.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Penetrating the impenetrable.Georges Rey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):149-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information pickup is the activity of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):397-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cognitive representation and the process-architecture distinction.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):154-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundation of cognitive science.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):111-32.
    The computational view of mind rests on certain intuitions regarding the fundamental similarity between computation and cognition. We examine some of these intuitions and suggest that they derive from the fact that computers and human organisms are both physical systems whose behavior is correctly described as being governed by rules acting on symbolic representations. Some of the implications of this view are discussed. It is suggested that a fundamental hypothesis of this approach is that there is a natural domain of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   666 citations  
  • Why another alternative optokinetic model?Thomas Probst - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):325-326.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Animal-environment mutuality and direct perception.Sandra S. Prindle, Claudia Carello & M. T. Turvey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):395-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Inferring the visual reference.Fred H. Previc - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):324-325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How wrong is Gibson?K. Prazdny - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):394-395.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pylyshyn and perception.William T. Powers - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):148-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pictures, maybe; illusions, no.Robert H. Pollack - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):92-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explanations in theories of language and of imagery.Steven Pinker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plea for more exploration of cross-cultural cognitive space.David Piggins - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):91-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The archaeology of space: Real and representational.Christopher S. Peebles - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):91-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Criteria of cognitive impenetrability.Robert C. Moore - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):146-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Visual Perception and the Wages of Indeterminacy.Richard Montgomery - 1990 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (1):365-378.
    In Word and Object, W.V. Quine made thinkable the idea that speech and cognition bear a burden of semantic indeterminacy. On Quine’s account, the upshot of semantic indeterminacy is that meaning and mentalism resist successful naturalization, and thus fail the test of scientific respectibility. For Quine, semantic indeterminacy is a fatal shortcoming.Recent attempts to naturalize meaning in our thought and our talk (e.g. Dretske 1981, Fodor 1987), belonging to a tradition that has thrived in reaction to Quine, have sought to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Action-dependent perceptual invariants: From ecological to sensorimotor approaches.Matteo Mossio & Dario Taraborelli - 2008 - Consciousness and Cognition 17 (4):1324-1340.
    Ecological and sensorimotor theories of perception build on the notion of action-dependent invariants as the basic structures underlying perceptual capacities. In this paper we contrast the assumptions these theories make on the nature of perceptual information modulated by action. By focusing on the question, how movement specifies perceptual information, we show that ecological and sensorimotor theories endorse substantially different views about the role of action in perception. In particular we argue that ecological invariants are characterized with reference to transformations produced (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Cognitive penetrability: let us not forget about memory.James R. Miller - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):146-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computation, consciousness and cognition.George A. Miller - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):146-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Real space and represented space: Crosscultural convergences.Harry McGurk - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):90-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wertheim's “reference” signal: Successful in explaining perception of absolute motion, but how about relative motion?S. Mateeff & J. Hohnsbein - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):323-324.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perceptual activity and direct perception.William M. Mace - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):392-393.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are mediating representations the ghosts in the machine?Alan K. Mackworth - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):393-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Visual perception: the shifting domain of discourse.Geoffrey R. Loftus & Elizabeth F. Loftus - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):391-392.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interpreting image curve from multiframes.Chia-Hoang Lee - 1988 - Artificial Intelligence 35 (2):145-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functional architecture and free will.Henry E. Kyburg - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):143-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why argue about direct perception?J. J. Koenderink - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):390-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Action identity: Evidence from self-recognition, prediction, and coordination.Günther Knoblich & Rüdiger Flach - 2003 - Consciousness and Cognition 12 (4):620-632.
    Prior research suggests that the action system is responsible for creating an immediate sense of self by determining whether certain sensations and perceptions are the result of one's own actions. In addition, it is assumed that declarative, episodic, or autobiographical memories create a temporally extended sense of self or some form of identity. In the present article, we review recent evidence suggesting that action (procedural) knowledge also forms part of a person's identity, an action identity, so to speak. Experiments that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The elusive visual processing mode: Implications of the architecture/algorithm distinction.Roberta L. Klatzky - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):142-143.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark