Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Semantic activation without conscious identification in dichotic listening, parafoveal vision, and visual masking: A survey and appraisal.Daniel Holender - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):1-23.
    When the stored representation of the meaning of a stimulus is accessed through the processing of a sensory input it is maintained in an activated state for a certain amount of time that allows for further processing. This semantic activation is generally accompanied by conscious identification, which can be demonstrated by the ability of a person to perform discriminations on the basis of the meaning of the stimulus. The idea that a sensory input can give rise to semantic activation without (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   451 citations  
  • The representing brain: Neural correlates of motor intention and imagery.Marc Jeannerod - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):187-202.
    This paper concerns how motor actions are neurally represented and coded. Action planning and motor preparation can be studied using a specific type of representational activity, motor imagery. A close functional equivalence between motor imagery and motor preparation is suggested by the positive effects of imagining movements on motor learning, the similarity between the neural structures involved, and the similar physiological correlates observed in both imaging and preparing. The content of motor representations can be inferred from motor images at a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   358 citations  
  • How direct is visual perception? Some reflections on Gibson's 'ecological approach'.Jerry A. Fodor & Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1981 - Cognition 9 (2):139-96.
    Examines the theses that the postulation of mental processing is unnecessary to account for our perceptual relationship with the world, see turvey etal. for a criticque.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   293 citations  
  • Ecological laws of perceiving and acting: In reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn.Michael T. Turvey, R. E. Shaw, Edward S. Reed & William M. Mace - 1981 - Cognition 9 (3):237-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   264 citations  
  • Processing of expected and unexpected events during conditioning and attention: A psychophysiological theory.Stephen Grossberg - 1982 - Psychological Review 89 (5):529-572.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   219 citations  
  • Ecological psychology is radical enough: A reply to radical enactivists.Miguel Segundo-Ortin, Manuel Heras-Escribano & Vicente Raja - 2019 - Philosophical Psychology 32 (7):1001-1023.
    Ecological psychology is one of the most influential theories of perception in the embodied, anti-representational, and situated cognitive sciences. However, radical enactivists claim that Gibsonians tend to describe ecological information and its ‘pick up’ in ways that make ecological psychology close to representational theories of perception and cognition. Motivated by worries about the tenability of classical views of informational content and its processing, these authors claim that ecological psychology needs to be “RECtified” so as to explicitly resist representational readings. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Perception and action: Alternative views.Susan Hurley - 2001 - Synthese 129 (1):3-40.
    A traditional view of perception and action makestwo assumptions: that the causal flow betweenperception and action is primarily linear or one-way,and that they are merely instrumentally related toeach other, so that each is a means to the other.Either or both of these assumptions can be rejected. Behaviorism rejects the instrumental but not theone-way aspect of the traditional view, thus leavingitself open to charges of verificationism. Ecologicalviews reject the one-way aspect but not theinstrumental aspect of the traditional view, so thatperception and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • The neural basis of cognitive development: A constructivist manifesto.Steven R. Quartz & Terrence J. Sejnowski - 1997 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (4):537-556.
    How do minds emerge from developing brains? According to the representational features of cortex are built from the dynamic interaction between neural growth mechanisms and environmentally derived neural activity. Contrary to popular selectionist models that emphasize regressive mechanisms, the neurobiological evidence suggests that this growth is a progressive increase in the representational properties of cortex. The interaction between the environment and neural growth results in a flexible type of learning: minimizes the need for prespecification in accordance with recent neurobiological evidence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Consciousness and processing: Choosing and testing a null hypothesis.Anthony J. Marcel - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):40-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Experimental indeterminacies in the dissociation paradigm of subliminal perception.Matthew Hugh Erdelyi - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):30-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Consciousness is a “subjective” state.Philip M. Merikle & Jim Cheesman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):42-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • How are grammers represented?Edward P. Stabler - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):391-402.
    Noam Chomsky and other linguists and psychologists have suggested that human linguistic behavior is somehow governed by a mental representation of a transformational grammar. Challenges to this controversial claim have often been met by invoking an explicitly computational perspective: It makes perfect sense to suppose that a grammar could be represented in the memory of a computational device and that this grammar could govern the device's use of a language. This paper urges, however, that the claim that humans are such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Structural constraints on cognitive development: Introduction to a special issue of cognitive science.Rochel Gelman - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14 (1):3-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • Perception is not all-purpose.Bence Nanay - 2021 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 17):4069-4080.
    I aim to show that perception depends counterfactually on the action we want to perform. Perception is not all-purpose: what we want to do does influence what we see. After clarifying how this claim is different from the one at stake in the cognitive penetrability debate and what counterfactual dependence means in my claim, I will give a two-step argument: one’s perceptual attention depends counterfactually on one’s intention to perform an action and one’s perceptual processing depends counterfactually on one’s perceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Priming without awareness: What was all the fuss about?Keith E. Stanovich & Dean G. Purcell - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):47-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Electrodermal responses to words in an irrelevant message: A partial reappraisal.Raymond S. Corteen - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):27-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Conscious identification: Where do you draw the line?Stephen J. Lupker - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):37-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Representation is representation of similarities.Shimon Edelman - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (4):449-467.
    Intelligent systems are faced with the problem of securing a principled (ideally, veridical) relationship between the world and its internal representation. I propose a unified approach to visual representation, addressing both the needs of superordinate and basic-level categorization and of identification of specific instances of familiar categories. According to the proposed theory, a shape is represented by its similarity to a number of reference shapes, measured in a high-dimensional space of elementary features. This amounts to embedding the stimulus in a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Jeannerod's representing brain: Image or illusion?Jean Pailhous & Mireille Bonnard - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):215-216.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • An Ontology of Affordances.John T. Sanders - 1997 - Ecological Psychology 9 (1):97-112.
    I argue that the most promising approach to understanding J.J. Gibson's "affordances" takes affordances themselves as ontological primitives, instead of treating them as dispositional properties of more primitive things, events, surfaces, or substances. These latter are best treated as coalescences of affordances present in the environment (or "coalescences of use-potential," as in Sanders (1994) and Hilditch (1995)). On this view, even the ecological approach's stress on the complementary organism/environment pair is seen as expressing a particular affordance relation between the world (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • 2. Information Processing Systems Which Embody Computational Rules: The Connectionist Approach.Glyn W. Humphreys - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (3):201-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • On the hypothesis that grammars are mentally represented.William Demopoulos & Robert J. Matthews - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):405-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • On private events and brain events.Norman F. Dixon - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):29-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Processing of the unattended message during selective dichotic listening.R. Näätänen - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):43-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The how and why of what went where in apparent motion: Modeling solutions to the motion correspondence problem.Michael R. Dawson - 1991 - Psychological Review 98 (4):569-603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Conceptual, experimental, and theoretical indeterminacies in research on semantic activation without conscious identification.Daniel Holender - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):50-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Approaches to consciousness: Psychophysics or philosophy?Richard Latto & John Campion - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):36-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Beyond the computer metaphor: Behaviour as interaction.Paul Cisek - 1999 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 6 (11-12):11-12.
    Behaviour is often described as the computation of a response to a stimulus. This description is incomplete in an important way because it only examines what occurs between the reception of stimulus information and the generation of an action. Behaviour is more correctly described as a control process where actions are performed in order to affect perceptions. This closed-loop nature of behaviour is de-emphasized in modern discussions of brain function, leading to a number of artificial mysteries. A notable example is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Extending the notion of affordance.Silvano Zipoli Caiani - 2014 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13 (2):275-293.
    Post-Gibson attempts to set out a definition of affordance generally agree that this notion can be understood as a property of the environment with salience for an organism’s behavior. According to this view, some scholars advocate the idea that affordances are dispositional properties of physical objects that, given suitable circumstances, necessarily actualize related actions. This paper aims at assessing this statement in light of a theory of affordance perception. After years of discontinuity between strands of empirical and theoretical research, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Embedded Seeing: Vision in the Natural World.Nicoletta Orlandi - 2011 - Noûs 47 (4):727-747.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The psychophysics of subliminal perception.Neil A. Macmillan - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):38-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Representation and content in some (actual) theories of perception.Gary Hatfield - 1988 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 19 (2):175-214.
    Recent discussions in the philosophy of psychology have examined the use and legitimacy of such notions as “representation”, “content”, “computation”, and “inference” within a scientific psychology. While the resulting assessments have varied widely, ranging from outright rejection of some or all of these notions to full vindication of their use, there has been notable agreement on the considerations deemed relevant for making an assessment. The answer to the question of whether the notion of, say, representational content may be admitted into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Against methodological solipsism: The ecological approach.Mark Rowlands - 1995 - Philosophical Psychology 8 (1):5-24.
    This paper argues that an ecological approach to psychology of the sort advanced by J. J. Gibson provides a coherent and powerful alternative to the computational, information-processing, paradigm. The paper argues for two principles. Firstly, one cannot begin to understand what internal information processing an organism must accomplish until one understands what information is available to the organism in its environment. Secondly, an organism can process information by acting on or manipulating physical structures in its environment. An attempt is made (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Two theories of the intentionality of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1983 - Synthese 54 (January):85-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Control your mind, make affordance available.Zheng Jin, Yang Lee & Jin Zhu - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On some fundamental distinctions of computationalism.William Demopoulos - 1987 - Synthese 70 (January):79-96.
    The following paper presents a characterization of three distinctions fundamental to computationalism, viz., the distinction between analog and digital machines, representation and nonrepresentation-using systems, and direct and indirect perceptual processes. Each distinction is shown to rest on nothing more than the methodological principles which justify the explanatory framework of the special sciences.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Colourful Whorfian ideas: Linguistic and cultural influences on the perception and cognition of colour, and on the investigation of them.Angus Gellatly - 1995 - Mind and Language 10 (3):199-225.
    The resent paper reviews three phases in the literature on cognition and colour, and also Luria's (1976) observations of the effects that literacy and/or schooling have on colour naming and colour categorization. It is argued that Luria's own interpretation of his findings is partiafly flawed by inconsistency, and by ethnocentric presuppositions concerning mediation and abstraction. A revised interpretation is proposed that draws on Gibson's (1950, 1966) contrast between direct and indirect perceptions. It is suggested that language usage and cultural practices (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Perceiving affordances in context: A reply to Chow.Harry Heft - 1990 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 20 (3):277–284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • James J. Gibson's revolution in perceptual psychology: A case study of the transformation of scientific ideas.Edward S. Reed - 1986 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 17 (1):65-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Nonconscious motor images.Giacomo Rizzolatti - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):220-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Prospects for direct social perception: a multi-theoretical integration to further the science of social cognition.Travis J. Wiltshire, Emilio J. C. Lobato, Daniel S. McConnell & Stephen M. Fiore - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8:100549.
    In this paper we suggest that differing approaches to the science of social cognition mirror the arguments between radical embodied and traditional approaches to cognition. We contrast the use in social cognition of theoretical inference and mental simulation mechanisms with approaches emphasizing a direct perception of others’ mental states. We build from a recent integrative framework unifying these divergent perspectives through the use of dual-process theory and supporting social neuroscience research. Our elaboration considers two complementary notions of direct perception: one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Unconscious semantic processing: The pendulum keeps on swinging.David A. Balota - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):23-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Identification, masking, and priming: Clarifying the issues.Lindsay J. Evett, Glyn W. Humphreys & Philip T. Quinlan - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):31-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Call it what it is: Motor memory.Joaquin M. Fuster - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):208-208.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Motor representations and reality.M. Jeannerod - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):229-245.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the relation between motor imagery and visual imagery.Roberta L. Klatzky - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):212-213.
    Jeannerod's target article describes support, through empirical and neurological findings, for the intriguing idea of motor imagery, a form of representation hypothesized to have levels of functional equivalence with motor preparation, while being consciously accessible. Jeannerod suggests that the subjectively accessible content of motor imagery allows it to be distinguished from motor preparation, which is unconscious. Motor imagery is distinguished from visual imagery in terms of content. Motor images are kinesthetic in nature; they are parametrized by variables such as force (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Intension and representation: Quine’s indeterminacy thesis revisited.Itay Shani - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (4):415 – 440.
    This paper re-addresses Quine's indeterminacy of translation/inscrutability of reference thesis, as a problem for cognitive theories of content. In contradistinction with Quine's behavioristic semantics, theories of meaning, or content, in the cognitivist tradition endorse intentional realism, and are prone to be unsympathetic to Quine's thesis. Yet, despite this fundamental difference, I argue that they are just as vulnerable to the indeterminacy. I then argue that the vulnerability is rooted in a theoretical commitment tacitly shared with Quine, namely, the commitment to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Reciprocal modelling of active perception of 2-d forms in a simple tactile-vision substitution system.John Stewart & Olivier Gapenne - 2004 - Minds and Machines 14 (3):309-330.
    The strategies of action employed by a human subject in order to perceive simple 2-D forms on the basis of tactile sensory feedback have been modelled by an explicit computer algorithm. The modelling process has been constrained and informed by the capacity of human subjects both to consciously describe their own strategies, and to apply explicit strategies; thus, the strategies effectively employed by the human subject have been influenced by the modelling process itself. On this basis, good qualitative and semi-quantitative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Action and attention.A. H. C. Van der Heijden & Bruce Bridgeman - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):225-226.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Motion perception during selfmotion: The direct versus inferential controversy revisited.Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):293-311.
    According to the traditional inferential theory of perception, percepts of object motion or stationarity stem from an evaluation of afferent retinal signals (which encode image motion) with the help of extraretinal signals (which encode eye movements). According to direct perception theory, on the other hand, the percepts derive from retinally conveyed information only. Neither view is compatible with a perceptual phenomenon that occurs during visually induced sensations of ego motion (vection). A modified version of inferential theory yields a model in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations