Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Political Philosophy of Hobbes: His Theory of Obligation

New York: Oxford University Press (1957)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Hobbes’s agnostic theology before Leviathan.Arash Abizadeh - 2017 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (5):714-737.
    Prior to 1651, Hobbes was agnostic about the existence of God. Hobbes argued that God’s existence could neither be demonstrated nor proved, so that those who reason about God’s existence will systematically vacillate, sometimes thinking God exists, sometimes not, which for Hobbes is to say they will doubt God’s existence. Because this vacillation or doubt is inherent to the subject, reasoners like himself will judge that settling on one belief rather than another is epistemically unjustified. Hobbes’s agnosticism becomes apparent once (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Thomas Hobbes: libertad y poder en la metamorfosis moderna.Diego Fernández Peychaux, Antonio David Rozenberg & Ramírez Beltrán Julián (eds.) - 2024 - Buenos Aires: Universidad de Buenos Aires Instituto de Investigaciones Gino Germani.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O problema das leis em Hobbes.Marcelo Gross Villanova - 2009 - Doispontos 6 (3).
    After the question “how could Hobbes write the natural law, if it is nowritten law?” I’ll try to approach the relationship between natural and civil law after the instauration of the commonwealth. In this sense, I’ll pay attention to the hobbesian distinction among “written law” and “written register” of law and a few consequences after this distinction. For example, if, how Hobbes says, the correct interpretation of natural law doesn’t depend on philosophers, but only on the authority of commonwealth, would (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Os dois deuses de Hobbes. Limites da obrigação política hobbesiana.Thamy Pogrebinschi - 2009 - Doispontos 6 (3).
    The aim of this paper is to critically inquire into some of the interpretations of what appears to me to be the core of Hobbes's political philosophy: his concept of political obligation. And in so doing I will provide a new way of reading the problem of obedience in Hobbes, one that does not dismiss the limits of political obligation and the theological context that surrounds it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Liberdade, lei natural e direito natural em Hobbes: limiar do direito e da política na modernidade.Natalia Maruyama - 2009 - Trans/Form/Ação 32 (2):45-62.
    Liberdade e poder são dois temas que se correlacionam ao longo da história da filosofia política moderna. Nos textos de Hobbes, a ideia da liberdade como ausência de impedimentos às ações ajuda-nos a pensar o dever de obediência ao poder soberano e as relações entre política e direito. Uma situação de vácuo jurídico, em que tudo é permitido, faz-se, contudo, impossível, de modo que a solução de Hobbes consiste em sustentar a ideia do direito natural como direito originário individual vinculado (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Exorcizing Demons: Thomas Hobbes and Balthasar Bekker on Spirits and Religion.Alissa Macmillan - 2014 - Philosophica 89 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thomas Hobbes and a chastened ‘global’ constitution the contested boundaries of the law.Anthony F. Lang Jr - 2016 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 19 (1):103-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hobbes's Struggle with Contractual Obligation. On the Status of the Laws of Nature in Hobbes's Work.Matthias Kiesselbach - 2010 - Hobbes Studies 23 (2):105-123.
    This paper argues that throughout his intellectual career, Hobbes remains unsatisfied with his own attempts at proving the invariant advisability of contract-keeping. Not only does he see himself forced to abandon his early idea that contractual obligation is a matter of physical laws. He also develops and retains doubts concerning its theoretical successor, the doctrine that the obligatoriness characteristic of contracts is the interest in self-preservation in alliance with instrumental reason - i.e. prudence. In fact, it is during his work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pyrrhonism in the Political Philosophy of Thomas Hobbes.James J. Hamilton - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (2):217-247.
    The importance of Pyrrhonism to Hobbes's political philosophy is much greater than has been recognized. He seems to have used Pyrrhonist arguments to support a doctrine of moral relativity, but he was not a sceptic in the Pyrrhonist sense. These arguments helped him to develop his teaching that there is no absolute good or evil; to minimise the purchase of natural law in the state of nature and its restrictions on the right of nature; virtually to collapse natural law into (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Religion of Thomas Hobbes: P. T. GEACH.Peter Geach - 1981 - Religious Studies 17 (4):549-558.
    In G. K. Chesterton's story The Doom of the Darnaways, Lord Darnaway put on the spines of dummy books in his library such empty designations as The Snakes of Ireland and The Religion of Frederick the Great : I too might appear to have chosen a non-subject for this paper. My coming to the contrary conclusion was the unwitting work of the man whom Balliol College employed to give us tutorials in political philosophy. I soon noticed that his interpretation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hobbes and game theory revisited: Zero-sum games in the state of nature.Daniel Eggers - 2011 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 49 (3):193-226.
    The aim of this paper is to critically review the game-theoretic discussion of Hobbes and to develop a game-theoretic interpretation that gives due attention both to Hobbes's distinction between “moderates” and “dominators” and to what actually initiates conflict in the state of nature, namely, the competition for vital goods. As can be shown, Hobbes's state of nature contains differently structured situations of choice, the game-theoretic representation of which requires the prisoner's dilemma and the assurance game and the so-called assurance dilemma. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Introduction.Steffen Ducheyne & Wim van Moer - 2014 - Philosophica 89 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thomas Hobbes.Stewart Duncan - 2009 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), whose current reputation rests largely on his political philosophy, was a thinker with wide ranging interests. In philosophy, he defended a range of materialist, nominalist, and empiricist views against Cartesian and Aristotelian alternatives. In physics, his work was influential on Leibniz, and lead him into disputes with Boyle and the experimentalists of the early Royal Society. In history, he translated Thucydides's History of the Peloponnesian War into English, and later wrote his own history of the Long Parliament. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What motive to virtue? Early modern empirical naturalist theories of moral obligation.Brady John Hoback - unknown
    In this dissertation, I argue for a set of interpretations regarding the relationship between moral obligation and reasons for acting in the theories of Hobbes, Hutcheson, and Hume. Several commentators have noted affinities between these naturalist moral theories and contemporary ethical internalism. I argue that attempts to locate internalist theses in these figures are not entirely successful in any clear way. I follow Stephen Darwall's suggestion that addressing the question “why be moral?” is one of the fundamental problems of modern (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interpreting Hobbes’s Moral Theory: Rightness, Goodness, Virtue, and Responsibility.S. A. Lloyd - 2021 - Journal of Ethical Reflections 1 (4):69-90.
    The paper argues that the moral philosophy of Thomas Hobbes is unified by a complex conception of reason that imposes consistency norms of both rationality and reasonableness. Hobbes’s conceptions of rightness as reciprocity, and moral goodness as sociability belong to an original and attractive moral theory that is neither teleological nor classically deontological, nor as interpreters have variously argued, subjectivist, contractarian, egoist, or dependent on divine command.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral and Political Obligation in “Possessive Individualism”: The Problem of Manners.Gabriela Ratuela - 2014 - Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy 6 (2):598-617.
    Usually, the interpreters of Hobbes and Locke have discussed the two systems of political philosophy from the perspective of liberal political doctrine, meaning the opposition between unliberal absolute monarchy, which Hobbes promotes, and liberal parliamentary democracy, asserted by Locke. However, some interpreters have pointed out that, beyond the political matter, the two philosophies are first grounded in the culture of the 17th century and in the structure of English society. From this point of view, even Hobbes would keep in his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Surreptitious Leviathan: Concealing the Beast of Scientific Reason.David W. Cheely - 2013 - Lyceum 12 (1).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Justice et tolérance. La question du hobbisme du jeune Locke.Gabriela Ratuela - 2015 - Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy 7 (1):166-186.
    This article treats about the influence of Hobbes on the early writings of John Locke, Two Tracts on Government. These Tracts don’t have a particular importance in understanding Locke’s work, but they are important for understanding the spirit of the time and the intellectual development of the author of the Second Treatise. In the Two Tracts, Locke defends a conservative position in the matter of government’s role in regulating the religious policy. Locke was a puritan, but he was part of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Liar Paradox in Plato.Richard McDonough - 2015 - Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy (1):9-28.
    Although most scholars trace the Liar Paradox to Plato’s contemporary, Eubulides, the paper argues that Plato builds something very like the Liar Paradox into the very structure of his dialogues with significant consequences for understanding his views. After a preliminary exposition of the liar paradox it is argued that Plato builds this paradox into the formulation of many of his central doctrines, including the “Divided Line” and the “Allegory of the Cave” and the “Ladder of Love”. Thus, Plato may have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hobbes and Human Irrationality.Sandra Field - 2015 - Global Discourse 5 (2):207-220.
    Hobbes’s science of politics rests on a dual analysis of human beings: humans as complex material bodies in a network of mechanical forces, prone to passions and irrationality; and humans as subjects of right and obligation, morally exhortable by appeal to the standards of reason. The science of politics proposes an absolutist model of politics. If this proposal is not to be idle utopianism, the enduring functioning of the model needs to be compatible with the materialist analysis of human behaviour. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Political trembling and Leviathan's theodicy.Alexander Filippov - 2011 - Russian Sociological Review 10 (3):180-186.
    This article is a reply to Carlo Ginzburg’s Max-Weber Lecture delivered at the European University Institute. The author agrees with Ginzburg in many important points. However, he insists that terror produced by the state cannot be interpreted as the highest degree of the usual fears of ordinary people. It is not even identical with the simple death fear.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Antilogy in the Iuspositivism and the Iusnaturalism in Thomas Hobbes.Patricia Nakayama - 2016 - Las Torres de Lucca: Revista Internacional de Filosofía Política 5 (9):119-144.
    This study aims to present a new interpretation about the controversy in the Hobbesian reception about its affiliation to the natural law or the positive law. According to Norberto Bobbio, these positions are mutually exclusive. In the first place, we will present the textual passages that enable Hobbes to be considered, on the one hand, as a supporter of iusnaturalism in accordance with the paradigmatic readings of Howard Warrender and Norberto Bobbio and, on the other, or of iuspositivism, according to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Manda quem pode, obedece quem tem juízo”: ou sobre a (des)obediência e a razão em Hobbes.Rita Helena Sousa Ferreira Gomes - 2011 - Princípios 18 (29):99-116.
    Normal 0 21 false false false MicrosoftInternetExplorer4 Partindo do dito popular “manda quem pode, obedece quem tem juízo” o presente artigo tem como objetivo defender a tese de que o Estado hobbesiano sustenta-se tanto pela força quanto pela razáo. Dentro desta perspectiva, será analisada a noçáo de desobediência e, ao final, mostrar-se-á que o adágio referido só pode ser tido como verdadeiro de acordo com a filosofia política de Thomas Hobbes após feitas certas ressalvas.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark