Switch to: References

Citations of:

Realism bei Frege: Reply to Burge

Synthese 102 (3):363 - 382 (1995)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Unity of Wittgenstein's Philosophy: Necessity, Intelligibility, and Normativity.José Medina - 2002 - State University of New York Press.
    Explores the stable core of Wittgenstein's philosophy as developed from the Tractatus to the Philosophical Investigations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Consistency, Models, and Soundness.Matthias Schirn - 2010 - Axiomathes 20 (2):153-207.
    This essay consists of two parts. In the first part, I focus my attention on the remarks that Frege makes on consistency when he sets about criticizing the method of creating new numbers through definition or abstraction. This gives me the opportunity to comment also a little on H. Hankel, J. Thomae—Frege’s main targets when he comes to criticize “formal theories of arithmetic” in Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik (1884) and the second volume of Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (1903)—G. Cantor, L. E. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Critical study: Recent work on Frege.Fredrik Stjernberg - 2000 - Theoria 66 (3):273-288.
    Book reviewed in this article: GILEAD BAR‐ELLI, The Sense of Reference. Internationality in Frege, W. de Gruyter, BerliaNew York MICHAEL BEANEY, Frege: Making Sense, Duckworth, London.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Frege and Carnap on the normativity of logic.Florian Steinberger - 2017 - Synthese 194 (1):143-162.
    In this paper I examine the question of logic’s normative status in the light of Carnap’s Principle of Tolerance. I begin by contrasting Carnap’s conception of the normativity of logic with that of his teacher, Frege. I identify two core features of Frege’s position: first, the normative force of the logical laws is grounded in their descriptive adequacy; second, norms implied by logic are constitutive for thinking as such. While Carnap breaks with Frege’s absolutism about logic and hence with the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Metaphysical separatism and epistemological autonomy in Frege’s philosophy and beyond.Jim Hutchinson - 2022 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 30 (6):1096-1120.
    Commentators regularly attribute to Frege realist, idealist, and quietist responses to metaphysical questions concerning the abstract objects he calls ‘thoughts’. But despite decades of effort, the evidence offered on behalf of these attributions remains unconvincing. I argue that Frege deliberately avoids commitment to any of these positions, as part of a metaphysical separatist policy motivated by the fact that logic is epistemologically autonomous from metaphysics. Frege’s views and arguments prove relevant to current attempts to argue for epistemological autonomy, particularly that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Frege's puzzle about the cognitive function of truth.Dirk Greimann - 2004 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 47 (5):425-442.
    The aim of this paper is to give a detailed reconstruction of Frege's solution to his puzzle about the cognitive function of truth, which is this: On the one hand, the concept of truth seems to play an essential role in acquiring knowledge because the transition from the mere hypothetical assumption that p to the acknowledgement of its truth is a crucial step in acquiring the knowledge that p, while, on the other hand, this concept seems to be completely redundant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Antirrealismo e Expressivismo Lógico.Acácio Ferreira & Marcos Silva - 2021 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 25 (1).
    Em sua obra, Robert Brandom apresenta uma teoria expressivista da lógica. Segundo o autor, a lógica tem o papel expressivo de tornar explı́citas as relações inferenciais implı́citas em nossas práticas linguı́sticas. Estas relações inferenciais conferem conteúdo aos conceitos. Neste artigo, exploraremos a tese de que o expressivismo lógico de Brandom é uma teoria antirrealista acerca da lógica. Realistas lógicos costumam defender a existência independente de fatos lógicos em relação a nossas práticas cognitivas e linguı́sticas, de modo que a lógica, uma (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fregowska kategoria Bedeutung.Krystian Bogucki - 2018 - Analiza I Egzystencja 43 (2): 83 - 112.
    Bogusław Wolniewicz – polski tłumacz Pism semantycznych Gottloba Fregego – przełożył termin Bedeutung na język polski jako „znaczenie”, zauważając w przypisie, że wątpliwości, jakie może budzić w tym przypadku użycie tego słowa, budzi również użycie w języku niemieckim przez Fregego słowa Bedeutung. Jednocześnie Wolniewicz, w tym samym przypisie, twierdzi, że „to, co Frege nazywa znaczeniem znaku, pokrywa się z tym, co w dzisiejszej terminologii semantycznej zwykło się nazywać »denotacją« albo »denotatem«” (Frege, 2014a, s. 62, przypis 27). W niniejszym artykule postaram (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quine’s proxy-function argument for the indeterminacy of reference and frege’s caesar problem.Dirk Greimann - 2020 - Manuscrito 44 (3):70-108.
    In his logical foundation of arithmetic, Frege faced the problem that the semantic interpretation of his system does not determine the reference of the abstract terms completely. The contextual definition of number, for instance, does not decide whether the number 5 is identical to Julius Caesar. In a late writing, Quine claimed that the indeterminacy of reference established by Frege’s Caesar problem is a special case of the indeterminacy established by his proxy-function argument. The present paper aims to show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger's Logico-Semantic Strikeback.Alberto Voltolini - 2015 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 22:19-38.
    In (1959), Carnap famously attacked Heidegger for having constructed an insane metaphysics based on a misconception of both the logical form and the semantics of ordinary language. In what follows, it will be argued that, once one appropriately (i.e., in a Russellian fashion) reads Heidegger’s famous sentence that should paradigmatically exemplify such a misconception, i.e., “the nothing nothings”, there is nothing either logically or semantically wrong with it. The real controversy as to how that sentence has to be evaluated—not as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Scientific phenomena and patterns in data.Pascal Ströing - 2018 - Dissertation, Lmu München
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark