Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Defining “Cosmology” in the Early Modern System of Knowledge, 1530–1621.Dario Tessicini - 2022 - Perspectives on Science 30 (5):826-850.
    This article seeks to revise the common scholarly assumption that in early modern Europe there was no single word for the study of the universe as a whole until the word “cosmology” appeared in Christian Wolff’s Cosmologia generalis methodo scientifica pertractata (1731). In fact, the term “cosmology” had circulated in both Latin and European languages since at least the 1530s in the context of critical appraisals of the largely dominant Aristotelian and scholastic frameworks. The aim of this study is to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Abstract considerations: disciplines and the incoherence of Newton’s natural philosophy.Rob Iliffe - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (3):427-454.
    Historians have long sought putative connections between different areas of Newton’s scientific work, while recently scholars have argued that there were causal links between even more disparate fields of his intellectual activity. In this paper I take an opposite approach, and attempt to account for certain tensions in Newton’s ‘scientific’ work by examining his great sensitivity to the disciplinary divisions that both conditioned and facilitated his early investigations in science and mathematics. These momentous undertakings, exemplified by research that he wrote (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Role of Comets in The Copernican Revolution.Peter Barker - 1988 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 19 (3):299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Working Knowledges Before and After circa 1800.John V. Pickstone - 2007 - Isis 98 (3):489-516.
    ABSTRACT Historians of science, inasmuch as they are concerned with knowledges and practices rather than institutions, have tended of late to focus on case studies of common processes such as experiment and publication. In so doing, they tend to treat science as a single category, with various local instantiations. Or, alternatively, they relate cases to their specific local contexts. In neither approach do the cases or their contexts build easily into broader histories, reconstructing changing knowledge practices across time and space. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Discourse of Pious Science.Rivka Feldhay & Michael Heyd - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (1):109-142.
    The ArgumentThis paper, an attempt at an institutional history of ideas, compares patterns of reproduction of scientific knowledge in Catholic and Protestant educational institutions. Franciscus Eschinardus'Cursus Physico-Mathematicusand Jean-Robert Chouet'sSyntagma Physicumare examined for the strategies which allow for accommodation of new contents and new practices within traditional institutional frameworks. The texts manifest two different styles of inquiry about nature, each adapted to the peculiar constraints implied by its environment. The interpretative drive of Eschinardus and a whole group of “modern astronomers” is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • “This Comet or New Star”: Theology and the Interpretation of the Nova of 1572.Charlotte Methuen - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (4):499-515.
    This article examines a set of letters and observational reports that passed between Ludwig of Württemberg and Wilhelm of Hesse in response to the nova of 1572. Discussing the terminology used in this debate, it demonstrates that the terms “star” and “comet” were not unambiguous for sixteenth-century authors. A consideration of the relationship between accuracy of observation and the accuracy of the conclusions drawn from them, judged in the terms of twentieth-century astronomy, shows that those observers with the best instruments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kepler’s optics without hypotheses.Sven Dupré - 2012 - Synthese 185 (3):501-525.
    This paper argues that Kepler considered his work in optics as part of natural philosophy and that, consequently, he aimed at change within natural philosophy. Back-to-back with John Schuster’s claim that Descartes’ optics should be considered as a natural philosophical appropriation of innovative results in the tradition of practical and mixed mathematics the central claim of my paper is that Kepler’s theory of optical imagery, developed in his Paralipomena ad Vitellionem (1604), was the result of a move similar to Descartes’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Defining astronomical community in early modern Europe.Aviva Rothman - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (1):231-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The pen and the Sword: Recovering the disciplinary identity of physiology and anatomy before 1800 - I: Old physiology-the pen.Andrew Cunningham - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (4):631-665.
    It is argued that the disciplinary identity of anatomy and physiology before 1800 are unknown to us due to the subsequent creation, success and historiographical dominance of a different discipline-experimental physiology. The first of these two papers deals with the identity of physiology from its revival in the 1530s, and demonstrates that it was a theoretical, not an experimental, discipline, achieved with the mind and the pen, not the hand and the knife. The physiological work of Jean Fernel, Albrecht von (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The pen and the Sword: Recovering the disciplinary identity of physiology and anatomy before 1800 - II: Old anatomy-the Sword.A. Cunningham - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 34 (1):51-76.
    Following the exploration of the disciplinary identity of physiology before 1800 in the previous paper of this pair, the present paper seeks to recover the complementary identity of the discipline of anatomy before 1800. The manual, artisanal character of anatomy is explored via some of its practitioners, with special attention being given to William Harvey and Albrecht von Haller. Attention is particularly drawn to the important role of experiment in anatomical research and practice-which has been misread by historians as physiological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Could Lakatos, even with Zahar's criterion for novel fact, evaluate the copernican research programme?Neil Thomason - 1992 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (2):161-200.
    Why did Copernicus's research programme supersede Ptolemy's?’, Lakatos and Zahar argued that, on Zahar's criterion for ‘novel fact’, Copernican theory was objectively scientifically superior to Ptolemaic theory. They are mistaken, Lakatos and Zahar applied Zahar's criterion to ‘a historical thought-experiment’—fictional rather than real history. Further, in their fictional history, they compared Copernicus to Eudoxus rather than Ptolemy, ignored Tycho Brahe, and did not consider facts that would be novel for geostatic theories. When Zahar's criterion is applied to real history, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the frontlines of the scientific revolution: How mersenne learned to love Galileo.Daniel Garber - 2004 - Perspectives on Science 12 (2):135-163.
    : Marin Mersenne was central to the new mathematical approach to nature in Paris in the 1630s and 1640s. Intellectually, he was one of the most enthusiastic practitioners of that program, and published a number of influential books in those important decades. But Mersenne started his career in a rather different way. In the early 1620s, Mersenne was known in Paris primarily as a writer on religious topics, and a staunch defender of Aristotle against attacks by those who would replace (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Realism and instrumentalism in sixteenth century astronomy: A reappraisal.Peter Barker & Bernard R. Goldstein - 1998 - Perspectives on Science 6 (3):232-258.
    : We question the claim, common since Duhem, that sixteenth century astronomy, and especially the Wittenberg interpretation of Copernicus, was instrumentalistic rather than realistic. We identify a previously unrecognized Wittenberg astronomer, Edo Hildericus (Hilderich von Varel), who presents a detailed exposition of Copernicus's cosmology that is incompatible with instrumentalism. Quotations from other sixteenth century astronomers show that knowledge of the real configuration of the heavens was unattainable practically, rather than in principle. Astronomy was limited to quia demonstrations, although demonstration propter (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Francis Bacon and astronomical inquiry.Antonio Pérez-Ramos - 1990 - British Journal for the History of Science 23 (2):197-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the Ironic Specimen of the Doctor of Philosophy.William Clark - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (1):97-137.
    The ArgumentThe Doctor of Philosophy, a nonmedieval academic figure who spread throughout the globe in the Modern Era, and who emblemized the transformation of academic knowledge into the “pursuit of research,” emerged through a long and tortuous path in the early modern Germanies. The emergence and recognition of the Doctor of Philosophy would be correlative with the nineteenth-century professionalization of the arts and sciences. Throughout the Early Modern Era, the earlier Doctors and older “professional” faculties from the medieval university — (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Science and Patronage in England, 1570–1625: A Preliminary Study.Stephen Pumfrey & Frances Dawbarn - 2004 - History of Science 42 (2):137-188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Apenas um lado do jogo: Kepler condicionado por seu tempo?Claudemir Roque Tossato - 2006 - Scientiae Studia 4 (4):627-640.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Copernicus, the orbs, and the equant.Peter Barker - 1990 - Synthese 83 (2):317 - 323.
    I argue that Copernicus accepted the reality of celestial spheres on the grounds that the equant problem is unintelligible except as a problem about real spheres. The same considerations point to a number of generally unnoticed liabilities of Copernican astronomy, especially gaps between the spheres, and the failure of some spheres to obey the principle that their natural motion is to rotate. These difficulties may be additional reasons for Copernicus's reluctance to publish, and also stand in the way of strict (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Regiomontanus on ptolemy, physical orbs, and astronomical fictionalism: Goldsteinian themes in the "defense of theon against George of trebizond".Michael H. Shank - 2002 - Perspectives on Science 10 (2):179-207.
    : To honor Bernard Goldstein, this article highlights in the "Defense of Theon against George of Trebizond" by Regiomontanus (1436-1476) themes that resonate with leading strands of Goldstein's scholarship. I argue that, in this poorly-known work, Regiomontanus's mastery of Ptolemy's mathematical astronomy, his interest in making astronomy physical, and his homocentric ideals stand in unresolved tension. Each of these themes resonates with Gold- stein's fundamental work on the Almagest, the Planetary Hypotheses, and al-Bitruji's Principles of Astronomy. I flesh out these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A sabedoria humana de Pierre Charron: a ciência e o exercício cético do espírito forte.Estéfano Luís de Sá Winter - 2013 - Filosofia Do Renascimento E Moderna (Encontro Nacional Anpof).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards Solomon’s House: Rival Strategies for Reforming the Early Royal Society.Michael Hunter & Paul B. Wood - 1986 - History of Science 24 (1):49-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Jean Pena (1528‐58) and Stoic Physics in the Sixteenth Century.Peter Barker - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (S1):93-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mimush Sheep and the Spectre of Inbreeding: Historical Background for Festetics’s Organic and Genetic Laws Four Decades Before Mendel’s Experiments in Peas.Péter Poczai, Jorge A. Santiago-Blay, Jiří Sekerák, István Bariska & Attila T. Szabó - 2022 - Journal of the History of Biology 55 (3):495-536.
    The upheavals of late eighteenth century Europe encouraged people to demand greater liberties, including the freedom to explore the natural world, individually or as part of investigative associations. The Moravian Agricultural and Natural Science Society, organized by Christian Carl André, was one such group of keen practitioners of theoretical and applied scientific disciplines. Headquartered in the “Moravian Manchester” Brünn, the centre of the textile industry, society members debated the improvement of sheep wool to fulfil the needs of the Habsburg armies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The pen and the sword: recovering the disciplinary identity of physiology and anatomy before 1800.Andrew Cunningham - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (4):631-665.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Gender and the historiography of science.Ludmilla Jordanova - 1993 - British Journal for the History of Science 26 (4):469-483.
    The production of big pictures is arguably the most significant sign of the intellectual maturity of a field. It suggests both that the field's broad contours, refined over several generations of scholarship, enjoy the approval of practitioners, and that audiences exist with an interest in or need for overviews. The situation is somewhat more complicated in the history of science, since the existence of big historical pictures precedes that of a well-defined scholarly field by about two centuries. Broadly conceived histories (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Distance and velocity in Kepler's astronomy.Peter Barker & Bernard R. Goldstein - 1994 - Annals of Science 51 (1):59-73.
    We will examine Kepler's use of a relation between velocity and distance from a centre of circular motion. This relation plays an essential role, through a derivation in chapter 40 of the Astronomia Nova, in the presentation of the Area Law of planetary motion. Kepler transcends ancient and contemporary applications of the distance-velocity relation by connecting it with his metaphysical commitment to the causal role of the Sun. His second main innovation is to replace the astronomical models of his predecessors (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The importance of historical accuracy in philosophy of science: The case of Curd's conception of copernican rationality.Keith A. Nier - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (3):372-394.
    General discussions of the appropriate relations between history and philosophy of science must be complemented by examinations of particular studies involving both fields. Martin Curd's attempt to illuminate the rationality of theory change through analysis of the Copernican Revolution is such a study; his work is undercut by serious flaws and actually displays an ahistorical approach. The result misleads both about the Copernican Revolution and the general problem of theory change in science. The study does illustrate several types of failing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cultural History of Science: An Overview with Reflections.Peter Dear - 1995 - Science, Technology and Human Values 20 (2):150-170.
    The increased popularity of the label "cultural" within science studies, especially in relation to "cultural studies, " invites consideration of how it is and can be used in historical work. A lot more seems now to be invested in the notion of "cultural history. " This article examines some recent historiography of science as a means of considering what counts as cultural history in that domain and attempts to coordinate it with the sociologically informed studies of the past ten orfifteen (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Jesuit mathematical science and the reconstitution of experience in the early seventeenth century.Peter Dear - 1987 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 18 (2):133-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Ideology, Inevitability, and the Scientific Revolution.John Henry - 2008 - Isis 99 (3):552-559.
    ABSTRACT Looking in particular at the Scientific Revolution, this essay argues that, for all their differences, positivist commentators on science and contextualist historians of science ought to be committed to the view that counterfactual changes in the history of science would have made no significant difference to its historical development. Assumptions about the history of science as an inexorable march toward the truth commit the positivist to the view that, even if things had been different, scientific knowledge would still have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The Social Status of Italian Mathematicians, 1450–1600.Mario Biagioli - 1989 - History of Science 27 (1):41-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Copernicus's Development in Context: Politics, Astrology, Cosmology and a Prince-Bishopric.Geoffrey Blumenthal - 2014 - Science in Context 27 (1):1-32.
    ArgumentDuring the two decades before the turning point in Copernicus's personal and scientific development in 1510, he had experience of political activity which has been largely ignored by the existing Copernicus literature but part of which is reconstructed in outline in this paper. Given the close linkage between politics and astrology, Copernicus's likely reaction to astrology is re-examined here. This reconstruction also suggests that the turning point in 1510, when Copernicus left his post as secretary to his uncle Lucas Watzenrode (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What Did Mathematics Do to Physics?Yves Gingras - 2001 - History of Science 39 (4):383-416.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Galileo's French correspondents.Frederic J. Baumgartner - 1988 - Annals of Science 45 (2):169-182.
    This paper examines the correspondence and contacts between Galileo and a number of French intellectuals. It demonstrates that exchanges between Galileo and those Frenchmen did much to stimulate an interest in new scientific ideas in France, especially in astronomy; for example, Galileo provided a number of good telescopic lenses that did much to establish observational astronomy in France. The Frenchmen for their part provided Galileo with considerable useful information. Several were very active in his support after the condemnation of 1633 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mathematical practitioners and instruments in Elizabethan England.Stephen Johnston - 1991 - Annals of Science 48 (4):319-344.
    Summary A new culture of mathematics was developed in sixteenth-century England, the culture of ?the mathematicalls?. Its representatives were the self-styled mathematical practitioners who presented their art as a practical and worldly activity. The careers of two practitioners, Thomas Bedwell and Thomas Hood, are used as case studies to examine the establishment of this culture of the mathematicalls. Both practitioners self-consciously used mathematical instruments as key resources in negotiating their own roles. Bedwell defined his role in contrast to mechanicians and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Jean Pena (1528-58) and stoic physics in the sixteenth century.Peter Barker - 1985 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (S1):93-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • ‘Mathematics Made No Contribution to the Public Weal’: Why Jean Fernel (1497-1558) Became a Physician.John Henry - 2011 - Centaurus 53 (3):193-220.
    This paper offers a caution that emphasis upon the importance of mathematics in recent historiography is in danger of obscuring the historical fact that, for the most part, mathematics was not seen as important in the pre-modern period. The paper proceeds by following a single case study, and in so doing offers the first account of the mathematical writings of Jean Fernel (1497–1558), better known as a leading medical innovator of the 16th century. After establishing Fernel's early commitment to mathematics, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Impetus Mechanics as a Physical Argument for Copernicanism Copernicus, Benedetti, Galileo.Michael Wolff - 1987 - Science in Context 1 (2):215-256.
    The ArgumentOne of the earliest arguments for Copernicanism was a widely accepted fact: that on a horizontal plane a body subject to no external resistance can be set in motion by the smallest of all possible forces. This fact was contrary to Aristotelian physics; but it was a physical argument (by abduction) for the possibility of the Copernican world system. For it would be explained if that system was true or at least possible.Galileo argued: only nonviolent motions can be caused (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Towards a Richer Model of Man: A Critique of Laudan’s Progress and Its Problems.Robert S. Westman - 1978 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978 (2):492-504.
    In setting forth a new theory of the growth of scientific knowledge, Larry Laudan shows that any account of scientific change has consequences for the relationship between the history, philosophy and sociology of science. It is a laudable feature of his work that he does not treat any of these disciplines as undifferentiated monoliths. In fact, one of his main goals is to show that his account of progress requires specific ways of doing and relating these three disciplines. As an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reply to Michael Shank.Robert S. Westman - 2014 - Isis 105 (1):177-184.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Publish or Perish: Legal Contingencies and the Publication of Kepler's Astronomia nova.James R. Voelkel - 1999 - Science in Context 12 (1):33-59.
    The ArgumentThe publication of Johannes Kepler's brilliant and revolutionary Astronomia nova has hitherto been viewed as somehow inevitable. This paper argues that, on the contrary, the book's very existence and a measure of its unusual form and content are in fact highly contingent, and derive from a legal dispute between Kepler and Tycho's heirs over the right to capitalize on his astronomical legacy. On Tycho's death, Kepler rather accidentally found himself in charge of Tycho's posthumous astronomical publications, especially the highly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tycho Brahe and the Separation of Astronomy from Astrology: The Making of a New Scientific Discourse.Gábor Almási - 2013 - Science in Context 26 (1):3-30.
    ArgumentThe subject of the paper is the shift from an astrology-oriented astronomy towards an allegedly more objective, mathematically grounded approach to astronomy. This shift is illustrated through a close reading of Tycho Brahe's scientific development and the contemporaneous changes in his communicational strategies. Basing the argument on a substantial array of original sources it is claimed that the Danish astronomer developed a new astronomical discourse in pursuit of credibility, giving priority to observational astronomy and natural philosophical questions. The abandonment of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Astrological reform, Calvinism, and Cartesianism: Copernican astronomy in the Low Countries, 1550–1650.Steven Vanden Broecke - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (2):363-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Melanchthon Circle's English Epicycle.Katherine A. Tredwell - 2006 - Centaurus 48 (1):23-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Out of the margins: readers and the early modern (re-)emergence of mathematics.Kevin Gerard Tracey - forthcoming - Intellectual History Review.
    Reading Galileo: Scribal Technologies and The Two New Sciences, by Renée Raphael, Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press, 2017, ix + 265 pp., figs., bibl., index, £40.50 (cloth), ISBN 9781421421...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Incomensurabilidade, comparabilidade e objetividade.Claudemir Roque Tossato - 2012 - Scientiae Studia 10 (3):489-504.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Censoring Science in Sixteenth-Century Italy: Recent (and Not-So-Recent) Research.Neil Tarrant - 2014 - History of Science 52 (1):1-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Development of the Principle of Virtual Laws and its Conceptual Framework in Mechanics as Fundamental Relationship between Physics and Mathematics.Pisano Raffaele - 2017 - Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science 2:166.
    Generally speaking, virtual displacement or work concerns to a timely idea according to which a motion of a certain body is not the unique possible motion. The process of reducing this motion to a particular magnitude and concept, eventually minimizing as a hypothesis, can be traced back to the Aristotelian school. In the history and philosophy of science one finds various enunciations of the Principle of Virtual Laws and its virtual displacement or work applications, i.e., from Aristotle to Leibniz’s vis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Blood money: Harvey's De motu cordis as an exercise in accounting.Michael J. Neuss - 2018 - British Journal for the History of Science 51 (2):181-203.
    William Harvey's famous quantitative argument fromDe motu cordis about the circulation of blood explained how a small amount of blood could recirculate and nourish the entire body, upending the Galenic conception of the blood's motion. This paper argues that the quantitative argument drew on the calculative and rhetorical skills of merchants, including Harvey's own brothers. Modern translations ofDe motu cordisobscure the language of accountancy that Harvey himself used. Like a merchant accounting for credits and debits, intake and output, goods and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The rhetoric of utility: avoiding occult associations for mathematics through profitability and pleasure.Katherine Neal - 1999 - History of Science 37 (116):151-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations