Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Rules regulating inbreeding and marriage: Evolutionary or socioeconomic?Sam Glucksberg - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):269-270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intersocietal variation in the mate preferences of males and females.Norval D. Glenn - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):21-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Do gossip and lack of grooming make us human?Ilya I. Glezer & Warren G. Kinzey - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):704-705.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The advantages of simple systems in neuroethology.Raymon M. Glantz - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):221-221.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Missing link in mate preference studies: Reproduction.Brian A. Gladue - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):21-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Christian philosophical anthropology. A reformation perspective.Gerrit Glas - 2010 - Philosophia Reformata 75 (2):141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Abundant nature's long-term openness to humane biocultural designs.Robert B. Glassman - 2009 - Zygon 44 (2):355-388.
    Not by Genes Alone excellently explains Peter J. Richerson and Robert Boyd's important ideas about human gene-culture co-evolution to a broader audience but remains short of a larger vision of civilization. Several decades ago Ralph Burhoe had seen that fertile possibility in Richerson and Boyd's work. I suggest getting past present reductionistic customs to a scientific perspective having an integral place for virtue. Subsystem agency is part of this view, as is the driving role of abundance, whose ultimate origins are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A framework for the unification of the behavioral sciences.Herbert Gintis - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (1):1-16.
    The various behavioral disciplines model human behavior in distinct and incompatible ways. Yet, recent theoretical and empirical developments have created the conditions for rendering coherent the areas of overlap of the various behavioral disciplines. The analytical tools deployed in this task incorporate core principles from several behavioral disciplines. The proposed framework recognizes evolutionary theory, covering both genetic and cultural evolution, as the integrating principle of behavioral science. Moreover, if decision theory and game theory are broadened to encompass other-regarding preferences, they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Me, you, and us: Distinguishing “egoism,” “altruism,” and “groupism”.Margaret Gilbert - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):621-622.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Maximizing the past minimizes the future.John Gibbon - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):322-323.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genetically determined neural modules versus mental constructional acts in the genesis of human intelligence.Kathleen R. Gibson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):308-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Edward O. Wilson and the Organicist Tradition.Abraham H. Gibson - 2013 - Journal of the History of Biology 46 (4):599-630.
    Edward O. Wilson’s recent decision to abandon kin selection theory has sent shockwaves throughout the biological sciences. Over the past two years, more than a hundred biologists have signed letters protesting his reversal. Making sense of Wilson’s decision and the controversy it has spawned requires familiarity with the historical record. This entails not only examining the conditions under which kin selection theory first emerged, but also the organicist tradition against which it rebelled. In similar fashion, one must not only examine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Toward an individualistic ontology for cultural evolution.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):242-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The bioeconomics of phenotypic selection.Michael T. Ghiselin & Francesco M. Scudo - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):194-195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Species are individuals: Therefore human nature is a metaphysical delusion.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):77-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the evolution of play by means of artificial selection.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (1):165-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is sex sufficient?Michael T. Ghiselin - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (2):187-189.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Darwinism versus neo-Darwinism in the study of human mate preferences.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):20-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Are libraries intelligent?Michael T. Ghiselin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):78-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral and nonmoral innate constraints.Kathryn Paxton George - 1992 - Biology and Philosophy 7 (2):189-202.
    Charles J. Lumsden and E.O. Wilson, in their writings together and individually, have proposed that human behaviors, whether moral or nonmoral, are governed by innate constraints (which they have termed epigenetic rules). I propose that if a genetic component of moral behavior is to be discovered, some sorting out of specifically moral from nonmoral innate constraints will be necessary. That some specifically moral innate constraits exist is evidenced by virtuous behaviors exhibited in nonhuman mammals, whose behavior is usually granted to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why there are no objective values: A critique of ethical intuitionism from an evolutionary point of view. [REVIEW]Gebhard Geiger - 1992 - Biology and Philosophy 7 (3):315-330.
    Using concepts of evolutionary game theory, this paper presents a critique of ethical intuitionism, or non-naturalism, in its cognitivist and objectivist interpretation. While epistemological considerations suggest that human rational learning through experience provides no basis for objective moral knowledge, it is argued below that modern evolutionary theory explains why this is so, i.e., why biological organisms do not evolve so as to experience objective preferences and obligations. The difference between the modes of the cognition of objective and of valuative environmental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Synthesis of theories through parametrisation of laws.Gebhard Geiger - 1988 - Erkenntnis 29 (3):343 - 355.
    The paper presents an example of unified theory bearing interest from both a historical and systematic point of view. The example is chosen from evolutionary population genetics (neo-Darwinian synthetic theory). It exhibits various aspects of theoretical change in science that have been shown in Part I (Geiger, 1988) to be characteristic of syntheses of theories.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Evolutionary anthropology and the non-cognitive foundation of moral validity.Gebhard Geiger - 1993 - Biology and Philosophy 8 (2):133-151.
    This paper makes an attempt at the conceptual foundation of descriptive ethical theories in terms of evolutionary anthropology. It suggests, first, that what human social actors tend to accept to be morally valid and legitimate ultimately rests upon empirical authority relations and, second, that this acceptance follows an evolved pattern of hierarchical behaviour control in the social animal species. The analysis starts with a brief review of Thomas Hobbes'' moral philosophy, with special emphasis on Hobbes'' authoritarian view of moral validity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The use and abuse of sociobiology.Steven J. C. Gaulin - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):193-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Behavioral dominance from an ecological perspective.Sidney A. Gauthreaux - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):441-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Successful is Naturalism?Georg Gasser (ed.) - 2007 - Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.
    The aim of the present volume is to draw the balance of naturalism's success so far.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Androgens and aggression.Ronald Gandelman - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):220-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The wider context of selection by consequences.Thomas J. Gamble - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):488-489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dominance: Measure first and then define.Fred H. Gage - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):440-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Putting sociobiology in its place.Andrew Futterman & Garland E. Allen - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (1):76-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genes or culture? A marxist perspective on humankind.Ivan T. Frolov - 1986 - Biology and Philosophy 1 (1):89-107.
    Intense interest has long been shown in the nature of humankind. Are we the products of genes? Are we the products of culture? Or are we something in between? The Marxist position, stressing the dominant significance of social methods for studying humans, is sketched. Then, a number of Western, biologically influenced views are discussed and criticised. Although there are important insights in the writings of the holders of these views, ultimately they produce only a semiscience.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is Unified theories of cognition good strategy?Nico H. Frijda & Jan Elshout - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):445-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An organisational approach to biological communication.Ramiro Frick, Leonardo Bich & Alvaro Moreno - 2019 - Acta Biotheoretica (2):103-128.
    This paper aims to provide a philosophical and theoretical account of biological communication grounded in the notion of organisation. The organisational approach characterises living systems as organised in such a way that they are capable to self-produce and self-maintain while in constant interaction with the environment. To apply this theoretical framework to the study of biological communication, we focus on a specific approach, based on the notion of influence, according to which communication takes place when a signal emitted by a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Preculture versus culture?Daniel G. Freedman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):107-108.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On incestuous attraction and natural selection between populations.Daniel G. Freedman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):269-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Group structure and group size among humans and other primates.Linton C. Freeman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):703-704.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Methodological Consilience of Evolutionary Ethics and Cognitive Science of Religion.Juraj Franek - 2016 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 16 (1-2):144-170.
    For the larger part of modern western intellectual history, it has been assumed that the study of morality and religion requires special methodology, insulated from, and in some important aspects incongruent with, the scientific method commonly used in the realm of natural sciences. Furthermore, even if it would be granted that moral and religious behavior is amendable to scientific analysis, the prospects of using evolutionary theory in particular to do the heavy lifting in explanation of these phenomena have been bleak, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there anything new in the neurophysiology of aggression for social psychologists?Adam Fraczek - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (2):219-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Group selection and “genuine” altruism.Robert H. Frank - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):620-621.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Causes, proximate and ultimate.Richard C. Francis - 1990 - Biology and Philosophy 5 (4):401-415.
    Within evolutionary biology a distinction is frequently made between proximate and ultimate causes. One apparently plausible interpretation of this dichotomy is that proximate causes concern processes occurring during the life of an organism while ultimate causes refer to those processes (particularly natural selection) that shaped its genome. But ultimate causes are not sought through historical investigations of an organisms lineage. Rather, explanations referring to ultimate causes typically emerge from functional analyses. But these functional analyses do not identify causes of any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Paternity irrelevance and matrilineal descent.Robin Fox - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):674-675.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Fitness by any other name.Robin Fox - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):192-193.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Male Sexual Orientation and Avuncularity in Canada: Implications for the Kin Selection Hypothesis.Deanna L. Forrester, Jessica L. Parker, Paul L. Vasey & Doug P. VanderLaan - 2011 - Journal of Cognition and Culture 11 (3-4):339-352.
    Androphilia refers to sexual attraction and arousal to adult males, whereas gynephilia refers to sexual attraction and arousal to adult females. The Kin Selection Hypothesis posits that genes for male androphilia can persist if androphilic males offset the fitness costs of not reproducing directly by enhancing indirect fitness. In theory, by directing altruistic behavior toward kin, androphilic males can increase the reproduction of kin, thereby enhancing indirect fitness. Evidence supporting the KSH has been documented in Samoa. Samoan transgendered, androphilic males, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ecological and social variance and the evolution of increased neocortical size.R. A. Foley - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):702-703.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sociobiology and IQ trends over time.James R. Flynn - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):192-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How can evolutionary theory help explain inheritance practices?Mark V. Flinn - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):673-674.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Natural selection and the problem of evil: An evolutionary model with application to an ancient debate.Robert K. Fleck - 2011 - Zygon 46 (3):561-587.
    Abstract. Since Darwin, scholars have contemplated what our growing understanding of natural selection, combined with the fact that great suffering occurs, allows us to infer about the possibility that a benevolent God created the universe. Building on this long line of thought, I develop a model that illustrates how undesirable characteristics of the world (stylized “evils”) can influence long-run outcomes. More specifically, the model considers an evolutionary process in which each generation faces a risk from a “natural evil” (e.g., predation, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dominance: Cause or description of social relationships?Kevin J. Flannelly & Robert J. Blanchard - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):438-440.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • An evolutionary perspective of the family.Harold D. Fishbein - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (3):384-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computo ergo Sum.Piera Filippi - 2014 - Biological Theory 9 (1):115-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark