Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. politeness: Towards an evaluative and embodied approach.Chaoqun Xie - 2008 - Pragmatics and Cognition 16 (1):151-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Wonder of Colors and the Principle of Ariadne.Walter Carnielli & Carlos di Prisco - 2017 - In Walter Carnielli & Carlos di Prisco (eds.), The Wonder of Colors and the Principle of Ariadne. Springer. pp. 309-317.
    The Principle of Ariadne, formulated in 1988 ago by Walter Carnielli and Carlos Di Prisco and later published in 1993, is an infinitary principle that is independent of the Axiom of Choice in ZF, although it can be consistently added to the remaining ZF axioms. The present paper surveys, and motivates, the foundational importance of the Principle of Ariadne and proposes the Ariadne Game, showing that the Principle of Ariadne, corresponds precisely to a winning strategy for the Ariadne Game. Some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Review of "Clarity and Confusion in Social Theory" by Leonidas Tsilipakos. [REVIEW]Robert Vinten - 2015 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4 (2):153-156.
    Book review of Tsilipakos, Leonidas: Clarity and Confusion in Social Theory: Taking Concepts Seriously. Farnham : Ashgate Publishing Limited, 2015.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The view from outside: On a distinctively cinematic achievement.Mario De Caro & Enrico Terrone - 2016 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 42 (2):154-170.
    What aesthetic interest do we have in watching films? In a much debated paper, Roger Scruton argued that this interest typically comes down to the interest in the dramatic representations recorded by such films. Berys Gaut and Catharine Abell criticized Scruton’s argument by claiming that films can elicit an aesthetic interest also by virtue of their pictorial representation. In this article, we develop a different criticism of Scruton’s argument. In our view, a film can elicit an aesthetic interest that does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and Spengler.William James DeAngelis - 1994 - Dialogue 33 (1):41-.
    In 1931, writing in a personal journal, Wittgenstein enumerated the names of those thinkers whom he deemed to have been his most important intellectual influences. He makes the strong claim that these are thinkers whose seminal ideas he has taken over, further elaborated and incorporated into his own work. Here are the names he lists in their order of appearance: Boltzmann, Hertz, Schopenhauer, Frege, Russell, Kraus, Loos, Weininger, Spengler, Sraffa. At the time of the first publication of this list in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein—A Religious Point of View? Thoughts on Norman Malcolm's Last Philosophical Project.William James Deangelis - 1997 - Dialogue 36 (4):819-.
    Do Wittgenstein's late philosophical writings represent a religious point of view? There is a good deal of evidence—including a number of Wittgenstein's own avowals—for an affirmative answer. Against this, there is the stark fact that Wittgenstein's late philosophical writings never directly discuss questions of God and religion. So, if they do represent a religious viewpoint, a correct account of it would, it seems, need to address subtleties and hidden tendencies. While a number of philosophical authors have offered such accounts, nothing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Did you hear the One about the Philosopher Writing a Book on Humour?Simon Critchley - 2002 - Think 1 (2):103-112.
    Simon Critchley, Professor of Philosophy at the University of Essex, investigates humour. And tells some pretty good jokes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Passions and Religious Belief.John Cottingham - 2019 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 85:57-74.
    Much contemporary philosophy of religion suffers from an overly abstract and intellectualized methodology. A more ‘humane’ approach would acknowledge the vital contribution of the emotions and passions to a proper cognitive grasp of the nature of the cosmos and our place within it. The point is illustrated by reference to a number of writers, including Descartes, whose path to knowledge of God, often thought to depend on dispassionate argument alone, in fact relies on a synergy between intellect and emotions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Detachment, Rationality and Evidence: Towards a More Humane Religious Epistemology.John Cottingham - 2017 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 81:87-100.
    Some truths cannot be accessed ‘cold’, from a detached and impersonal standpoint, but require personal commitment and even moral change in order for the relevant evidence to come to light. The truths of religion may be of this kind. Moreover, recent work in psychology and neurophysiology suggests that our knowledge of the world comes in different forms, the detached critical scrutiny associated with ‘the left-brain’ and the more intuitive and holistic awareness mediated by the ‘right brain’. Much contemporary philosophy privileges (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein, Heidegger and Humility.David E. Cooper - 1997 - Philosophy 72 (279):105-123.
    In 1929, doubtless to the discomfort of his logical positivist host Moritz Schlick, Wittgenstein remarked, ‘To be sure, I can understand what Heidegger means by Being and Angst’. I return to what Heidegger meant and Wittgenstein could understand later. I begin with that remark because it has had an instructive career. When the passage which it prefaced was first published in 1965, the editors left it out—presumably to protect a hero of ‘analytic’ philosophy from being compromised by an expression of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What, After All, Is the Work of Culture?Vincent Colapietro - 2021 - Metaphilosophy 52 (1):27-48.
    This paper offers an overview of Joseph Margolis’s philosophy of culture, highlighting how Margolis’s radical historicism is not inconsistent with our realistic intuitions regrading facts and objectivity. While Margolis identifies interpretation as the work of culture, the paper suggests that a much more basic sense of human labor needs to be thematized more fully than Margolis does in any defensible account of culture. Margolis of course appreciates work in this sense, but he does not consistently make it integral to his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When do Empirical Methods By-pass ‘The Problems Which Trouble Us’?Frank Cioffi - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 16:155-172.
    His discussion of aesthetics was mingled in a curious way with criticism of assumptions which he said were made by Frazer in The Golden Bough and also with criticisms of Freud ’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When do Empirical Methods By-pass ‘The Problems Which Trouble Us’?Frank Cioffi - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 16:155-172.
    His discussion of aesthetics was mingled in a curious way with criticism of assumptions which he said were made by Frazer in The Golden Bough and also with criticisms of Freud ’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The propaedeutic delusion: what can 'ethogenic science' add to our pre-theoretic understanding of 'loss of dignity, humiliation and expressive failure'?Frank Cioffi - 2000 - History of the Human Sciences 13 (1):108-123.
    This article assembles reasons for holding that the propaedeutic rationale for much of the discourse produced by ‘ethogenic science’ is inadequate. One reason is that the interactional principles that are the pretext for assembling the situational vignettes, which are the staple of ethogenics, are truisms and do not require documentation. Our familiarity with the risks and rewards of social life is already considerable and it is not clear how, or to what end, ethogenic science can augment them. Moreover ethogenic theorists (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To Mental Illness via a Rhyme for the Eye.T. S. Champlin - 1996 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 41:165-189.
    The intellectual journey on which I am about to embark, although not an unusual one in philosophy, may at first seem strange to those who are in the habit of looking to science for the answers to their big questions, including their philosophical questions. For I propose to shed light on the problematic relationship between two things, namely, mental illness and physical illness, by comparing their relationship to the relationship between two other things, namely, a rhyme for the eye—which will (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Zahavi’s Husserl and the Legacy of Phenomenology: A Critical Notice of Husserl’s Legacy: Phenomenology, Metaphysics, and Transcendental Philosophy, by Dan Zahavi.David R. Cerbone - 2020 - Mind 129 (514):603-620.
    As the title – Husserl’s Legacy – and subtitle – Phenomenology, Metaphysics, and Transcendental Philosophy – make clear, Dan Zahavi’s new book is centrally concerned with developing and defending a particular account of Husserl’s legacy. Rather than tracing lines of influence or measuring the impact of various of Husserl’s ideas, Zahavi is interested in Husserl’s legacy in a different and more demanding sense that pertains to what he refers to as ‘the overarching aims and ambitions of Husserlian phenomenology’. He is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Calling Solomon’s Bluff: Ethics, Aspect‐Perception and the Unity of the Tractatus.Michael Campbell - 2020 - Philosophical Investigations 43 (3):223-253.
    In this paper, I consider how we ought to read the aspect‐perception passages in the Tractatus Logico‐Philosophicus (TLP) in the light of its ethics. I engage with a recent proposal, of Genia Schönbaumsfeld's, that we should replace the TLP account of aspect‐perception with that which Wittgenstein puts forward in the Philosophical Investigations (PI). I show that, far from helping us to grasp the ethical vision contained in the TLP, this proposal obscures it. I go on to draw some conclusions from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Religious Diversity and Conceptual Schemes: Critically Appraising Internalist Pluralism.Mikel Burley - 2019 - Sophia 58 (2):283-299.
    Is a philosophical theory needed to ‘underwrite’ attitudes of toleration and respect in a multicultural and religiously diverse world? Many philosophers of religion have thought so, including Victoria Harrison. This article interrogates Harrison’s theory of internalist pluralism, which, though offering a welcome alternative to other theories, such as John Hick’s ‘pluralistic hypothesis’, nevertheless faces problems. Questioning the coherence of the theory’s account of how the existence of objects of worship can avoid being fully conceptual-scheme dependent, and raising doubts about its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Immortality and Meaning: Reflections on the Makropulos Debate.Mikel Burley - 2009 - Philosophy 84 (4):529-547.
    This article reflects upon the debate, initiated by Bernard Williams in 1973, concerning the desirability of immortality, where the latter expression is taken to mean endless bodily life as a human or humanoid being. Williams contends that it cannot be desirable; others have disputed this contention. I discuss a recent response from Timothy Chappell and attempt to pinpoint the central disagreement between Chappell and Williams. I propose that neither side in the debate has firm grounds for its claims, and then (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Dislocating the Eschaton? Appraising Realized Eschatology.Mikel Burley - 2017 - Sophia 56 (3):435-452.
    Was Jesus Christ a deluded prophet who expected an imminent collapse of the world followed by the dawning of a kingdom that has never eventuated? Some who reject Christianity think that he was, and as a consequence are highly suspicious about any other claims that are attributed to Jesus. However, other interpretations of the apparently eschatological pronouncements in the New Testament exist, one of which is realized eschatology, this being the idea, roughly, that the kingdom or reign of God was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Believing in Reincarnation.Mikel Burley - 2012 - Philosophy 87 (2):261-279.
    Is it absurd to believe that, in the absence of bodily continuity, personal identity could be retained? Bernard Williams argued for an affirmative answer to this question partly on the basis of a well-known thought experiment. Some other philosophers, including D. Z. Phillips, have accepted, or appear to have accepted, Williams' conclusion.Yet the argument has the consequence of dismissing as absurd the sorts of reincarnation beliefs which, within their proper contexts, have a meaningful role in the lives of many millions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Aquinas’ “First Way”: An Exposition and Wittgensteinian Assessment.William H. Brenner - 2016 - New Blackfriars 97 (1072).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On engaging with others: A Wittgensteinian approach to (some) problems with deeply held beliefs.Tracy Bowell - 2018 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 50 (5):478-488.
    My starting point for this paper is a problem in critical thinking pedagogy—the difficult of bringing students to a point where they are able, and motivated, critically to evaluate their own deeply held beliefs. I first interrogate the very idea of a deeply held belief, drawing upon Wittgenstein’s idea of a framework belief—a belief that forms part of a ‘scaffolding’ for our thoughts—or of a belief that functions as a hinge around which other beliefs pivot. I then examine the role (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Aesthetic Factor in Art and Religion.Richard H. Bell - 1986 - Religious Studies 22 (2):181 - 192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein: Spiritual Practices.Gordon C. F. Bearn - 2019 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 53 (4):701-714.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Careful becomings: Foucault, Deleuze, and Bergson.Gordon C. F. Bearn - 2017 - Human Affairs 27 (4):400-415.
    This essay argues for a convergence between, on the one side, Foucault’s characterization of the care of the self as a way of overcoming the traps of anthropological sleep, and on the other side, Deleuze’s characterization of initiating becomings as a way of fleeing the traps of organization, a line of flight, becoming becoming. This convergence is defended on the basis of a Bergsonian ontology of becoming, and in particular, Bergson’s opposition to what he calls the retrograde motion of truth. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical autobiography.Julian Baggini - 2002 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 45 (3):295 – 312.
    An examination of the genre of philosophical autobiography sheds light on the role of personal judgment alongside objective rationality in philosophy. Building on Monk's conception of philosophical biography, philosophical autobiography can be seen as any autobiography that reveals some interplay between life and thought. It is argued that almost all autobiographies by philosophers are philosophical because the recounting of one's own life is almost invariably a form of extended speech act of self-revelation. When a philosopher is the autobiographer, this self-revelation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Much Ado about a Point of View.Lance Ashdown - 2004 - Dialogue 43 (4):685-706.
    RésuméQue voulait dire Wittgenstein lorsqu'ilaremarqué: «Je ne suispas un homme religieux, maisje nepuis m'empecher de voir tout problème d'un point de me religieux»? La thèse de Malcom, c'est que cette remarque pointe du doigt les analogies entre la perspective philosophique de Wittgenstein et une vision religieuse de la vie. En revanche, Winch fait valoir que la remarque de Wittgenstein peut être interprétée comme ne faisant pas référence aux problèmes exclusivement philosophiques; Wittgenstein exprimait plutôt sa propre perspective quasi religieuse sur la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Religious Certainty: Peculiarities and Pedagogical Considerations.José María Ariso - 2020 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 39 (6):657-669.
    This paper presents the concept of ‘religious certainty’ I have developed by drawing inspiration from Wittgenstein’s notion of ‘certainty’. After describing the particular traits of religious certainty, this paper addresses two difficulties derived from this concept. On the one hand, it explains why religious certainty functions as such even though all its consequences are far from being absolutely clear; on the other hand, it clarifies why, unlike the rest of certainties, the loss of religious certainty does not result in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Can Certainties Be Acquired at Will? Implications for Children's Assimilation of a World‐picture.José María Ariso - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 50 (4):573-586.
    After describing Wittgenstein's notion of ‘certainty’, in this article I provide four arguments to demonstrate that no certainty can be acquired at will. Specifically, I argue that, in order to assimilate a certainty, it is irrelevant whether the individual concerned has found a ground that seemingly justifies that certainty; has a given mental state; is willing to accept the certainty on the proposal of a persuader; or tries to act according to the certainty involved. Lastly, I analyse how each of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Who Discovered the Binary System and Arithmetic? Did Leibniz Plagiarize Caramuel?J. Ares, J. Lara, D. Lizcano & M. A. Martínez - 2018 - Science and Engineering Ethics 24 (1):173-188.
    Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz is the self-proclaimed inventor of the binary system and is considered as such by most historians of mathematics and/or mathematicians. Really though, we owe the groundwork of today’s computing not to Leibniz but to the Englishman Thomas Harriot and the Spaniard Juan Caramuel de Lobkowitz, whom Leibniz plagiarized. This plagiarism has been identified on the basis of several facts: Caramuel’s work on the binary system is earlier than Leibniz’s, Leibniz was acquainted—both directly and indirectly—with Caramuel’s work and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aspect-Perception as a Philosophical Method.Reshef Agam-Segal - 2015 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 4 (1):93-121.
    Inducing aspect-experiences – the sudden seeing of something anew, as when a face suddenly strikes us as familiar – can be used as a philosophical method. In seeing aspects, I argue, we let ourselves experience what it would be like to conceptualize something in a particular way, apart from any conceptual routine. We can use that experience to examine our ways of conceptualizing things, and re-evaluate the ways we make sense of them. I claim that we are not always passive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein, Modern Music, and the Myth of Progress.Eran Guter - 2017 - In Niiniluoto Ilkka & Wallgren Thomas (eds.), On the Human Condition – Essays in Honour of Georg Henrik von Wright’s Centennial Anniversary, Acta Philosophica Fennica vol. 93. Societas Philosophica Fennica. pp. 181-199.
    Georg Henrik von Wright was not only the first interpreter of Wittgenstein, who argued that Spengler’s work had reinforced and helped Wittgenstein to articulate his view of life, but also the first to consider seriously that Wittgenstein’s attitude to his times makes him unique among the great philosophers, that the philosophical problems which Wittgenstein was struggling, indeed his view of the nature of philosophy, were somehow connected with features of our culture or civilization. -/- In this paper I draw inspiration (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Jews as a Metaphysical Species.Yuval Lurie - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (249):323 - 347.
    There are certain remarks in Culture and Value in which Wittgenstein writes about Jews and about what he describes as their ‘Jewish mind’. In these remarks he appears to be trying to make a distinction between two different spiritual forces which operate in Western culture and which give rise to two different types of artists and works of art. On one side of the divide are Jews and works of art imbued with Jewish spirit. On the other side are men (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Meditation on Wittgenstein’s Lecture on Ethics.Louis E. Wolcher - 1998 - Law and Critique 9 (1):3-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What if the private linguist were a poet? Iris Murdoch on privacy and ethics.Rachael Wiseman - 2020 - European Journal of Philosophy 28 (1):224-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A Philosophy of Seeing: The Work of the Eye/‘I’ in Early Years Educational Practice.E. Jayne White - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 50 (3):474-489.
    The work of the eye has a powerful influence across culture and philosophy—not least in Goethe's approach to understanding. Aligned to aesthetic appreciation, seeing has the potential to offer an authorial gift of ‘other-ness’ when brought to bear on evaluative relationships. Yet this penetrating gaze might also be seen as limiting when put to work in the services of ‘other’. From the subtle sideways glance, to the lingering gaze of lovers, a look can mean many things. But the eye does (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The sacred fire: Wittgenstein, Pseudo-Denys, and transparency to the divine.Ed Watson - 2021 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 82 (2):136-154.
    ABSTRACT In order to explore what it means to pursue philosophical investigations for theological reasons, this paper argues that Ludwig Wittgenstein continues and corrects Pseudo-Denys’ project in The Divine Names. I first argue that The Divine Names should be interpreted as attempting to render human thought transparent to the divine by relativizing our concepts. The success of this project is compromised because the concept of ‘unity’ is not relativized. I then develop the claim that Wittgenstein does relativize unity in a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical Autobiography: St Augustine and John Stuart Mill.Martin Warner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 16:189-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical Autobiography: St Augustine and John Stuart Mill.Martin Warner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 16:189-210.
    Many classic philosophical debates converge on the twin questions ‘What is man?’ and ‘What is his place in nature?’, in the sense that taking up a position in those debates normally commits one to a certain range of answers to these questions. Such answers typically lie near the centre of one's web of belief, deeply entrenched in the structure of one's concepts, and thus remain remarkably resistant to the standard techniques of confirmation and refutation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Peter Winch and the idea of immanent transcendence.Peter Vogt - 2023 - Philosophical Investigations 46 (3):289-313.
    The idea of immanent transcendence is constitutive for Winch's philosophy of religion and his ethics. Winch's philosophy of religion insists on the ‘immanent’ dimension of religion. His ethics insists on the ‘transcendent’ dimension of ethics. In this sense, both religion and ethics embody a perspective ‘beyond’ this world and yet must have practical consequences in this world. Transcendence without immanence is idle, and immanence without transcendence is empty—this is the kernel of Winch's philosophy of religion and of his ethics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein, Guilt And Western Buddhism.Robert Vinten - 2020 - Contemporary Buddhism 21 (2):284-303.
    Whereas Christians often give guilt a prominent role, Buddhists are encouraged not to dwell on feelings of guilt. Leading members of the Triratna organisation – Sangharakshita, Subhuti and Subhadramati – characterise guilt as a negative emotion that hinders spiritual growth. However, if we carefully examine the concept of guilt in the manner of Wittgenstein we find that the accounts of guilt given by leading members of Triratna mischaracterise it and so ignore its positive aspects. They should acknowledge the valuable role (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Paradox of Film: An Industry of Sex, a Form of Seduction (Notes on Jean Baudrillard's Seduction and the Cinema).Hunter Vaughan - 2010 - Film-Philosophy 14 (2):41-61.
    Jean Baudrillard, the misfit. Jean Baudrillard, who told us that the Gulf Warnever happened, who drew our attention to the perils of a civilization thatchoses to lead a virtual existence in an arena of images and simulacra - this isthe Baudrillard we are mostly familiar with. But Jean Baudrillard, thechampion of appearances? Baudrillard, more-feminist-than-the-feminists?This Baudrillard remains buried in the stacks of a prolific career spanningover forty years and involving some of the most radical systematicdeconstructions of Western culture, society and politics. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From fiction to friction: towards an ethics of hermeneutics in parent counselling.Luc Van den Berge - 2016 - Ethics and Education 11 (3):259-273.
    There seems to be an overall agreement that parents qua parents are, almost by definition, in need of support and hence that there is always a ‘parental deficit’. In order to help parents out many initiatives are taken, predominantly drawing from a technical conception of parenting. This particular conception defines the deficit as a shortage of practical and theoretical knowledge, and conceives of the predicament of parenting or upbringing as something that can be successfully dealt with. Two criticisms are developed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Religion and the Threat of Relativism.Roger Trigg - 1983 - Religious Studies 19 (3):297 - 310.
    Relativism has always proved tempting when people who had previously lived a settled and complacent life have suddenly been confronted with new and different ideas or practices. The obvious example is the ferment produced in ancient Athens when the contrast with Eastern ideas chronicled by Herodotus showed vividly that not everyone thought like the Athenians, or even the Greeks. The result was a far-reaching scepticism. Protagoras, according to Plato, maintained that man is the measure of all things and anything ‘is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From Doubt to Despair.Jasmin Trächtler - forthcoming - Nordic Wittgenstein Review.
    ‘Gaslighting’ describes a form of manipulation that induces doubt in someone’s perceptions, experiences, understanding of events or conception of reality in general. But what kind of doubt is it? How do ‘ordinary’ epistemic doubts differ from those doubts that can lead to despair and the feeling of losing one’s mind? The phenomenon of ‘gaslighting’ has been attracting public attention for some time and has recently found its way into philosophical reflections that address moral, sexist and epistemic aspects of gaslighting. Little (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein's Artillery: Philosophy as Poetry, by James C. Klagge.Julia Tanney - forthcoming - Mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein Listens to Mahler: How to Do Philosophy and Compose Music in the Breakdown of Tradition?Béla Szabados - 2007 - Dialogue 46 (1):91-113.
    ABSTRACTThis article retrieves, situates, and interprets Ludwig Wittgenstein's overlooked remarks about the composer Gustav Mahler, and connects them with Wittgenstein's philosophical perspective and practice, as well as with his musical aesthetics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Was Wittgenstein An Anti-Semite? The Signicance of Anti-Semitism for Wittgensteins Philosophy.Béla Szabados - 1999 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (1):1-27.
    pour l'autre en nous et parmi nousAn apologia seeks to cover up the revolutionary moments in the course of history. The establishment of continuity is dear to its heart. It only gives importance to those elements of a work that have already generated an after-effect. It misses those points at which the transmission breaks down and thus misses those jags and crags that offer a handhold to someone who wishes to move beyond them.I am all the same convinced that these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • After Religion? Reflections on Nielsen's Wittgenstein.Béla Szabados - 2004 - Dialogue 43 (4):747-770.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations