Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A Pedagogy of Things.Gordon Bearn - 2020 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 54 (4):1098-1109.
    Journal of Philosophy of Education, EarlyView.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Empirical Investigations: Reflecting on Turing and Wittgenstein on Thinking Machines.Jonathan Livengood & Justin Sytsma - unknown
    In the opening paragraph of “Computing Machinery and Intelligence” Alan Turing famously notes that “if the meaning of the words ‘machine’ and ‘think’ are to be found by examining how they are commonly used it is difficult to escape the conclusion that the meaning and the answer to the question, ‘Can machines think?’ is to be sought in a statistical survey such as a Gallup poll.” He then immediately responds, “But this is absurd.” But why is this absurd, if indeed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentions, Deception, and Motivated Reasoning.John D. Banja - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 1 (1):65-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Training and Mastery of Techniques in Wittgenstein's Later Philosophy: A response to Michael Luntley.Jeff Stickney - 2008 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 40 (5):678-694.
    Responding to Michael Luntley's article, ‘Learning, Empowerment and Judgement’, the author shows he cannot successfully make the following three moves: (1) dissolve the analytic distinction between learning by training and learning by reasoning, while advocating the latter; (2) diminish the role of training in Wittgenstein's philosophy, nor attribute to him a rationalist model of learning; and (3) turn to empirical research as a way of solving the philosophical problems he addresses through Wittgenstein. Drawing on José Medina's analysis of the fundamental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • After Religion? Reflections on Nielsen's Wittgenstein.Béla Szabados - 2004 - Dialogue 43 (4):747-770.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Post-Positivist Dispute in Social Studies of Science and its Bearing on Social Theory.Nigel Pleasants - 1997 - Theory, Culture and Society 14 (3):143-156.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The ethics of reading Wittgenstein.Michael A. Peters - 2018 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 51 (6):546-558.
    The worst readers are those who behave like plundering troops: they take away a few things they can use, dirty and confound the remainder, and revile the whole.–Nietzsche (1879) Human, All Too Huma...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Later Wittgenstein on Expressive Moral Judgements.Jordi Fairhurst - 2023 - Philosophical Quarterly 74 (1):208-228.
    This paper shows that Wittgenstein's later explorations of the meaning of expressive moral judgements reach far deeper than has so far been noticed. It is argued that an adequate description of the meaning of expressive moral judgements requires engaging in a grammatical investigation that focuses on three interwoven components within specific language-games. First, the ethical reactions expressed by moral words and the additional purpose they may fulfil. Second, the features of the actions which are bound up with moral words and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rule‐Following and Objective Spirit.Thomas J. Spiegel - 2022 - Philosophical Investigations 46 (1):76-98.
    This paper deals with Wittgenstein’s rule-following paradox, focussing on the infinite rule-regress as featured in Kripke’s Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. I argue that one of the most salient and popular proposed solutions (championed by John McDowell), which argues that rule-following is grounded in “custom,” “practice” or “form of life, remains unsatisfactory because part of this proposal is the rejection of further “theory” (commonly attributed to Wittgenstein) which seemingly makes it impossible to substantiate the claim of how customs, practices (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein Listens to Mahler: How to Do Philosophy and Compose Music in the Breakdown of Tradition?Béla Szabados - 2007 - Dialogue 46 (1):91-113.
    ABSTRACTThis article retrieves, situates, and interprets Ludwig Wittgenstein's overlooked remarks about the composer Gustav Mahler, and connects them with Wittgenstein's philosophical perspective and practice, as well as with his musical aesthetics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Education, educational research, and the 'grammar' of understanding: a response to David Bridges.Paul Smeyers - 2009 - Ethics and Education 4 (2):125-129.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • “Good” Philosophical Reasons for “Bad” Editorial Philology? On Rhees and Wittgenstein'sPhilosophical Grammar.Christian Erbacher - 2019 - Philosophical Investigations 42 (2):111-145.
    Using new archival material, this article reconstructs the editorial history of Philosophical Grammar, an edition that Rush Rhees crafted from Wittgenstein's papers. Contrasting the often‐held view that Rhees, in editing Philosophical Grammar, arbitrarily interfered with Wittgenstein's Big Typescript, the article illuminates the work, motives and reasons that underlie Rhees’ editing. Although recent philological evidence supports his editorial decisions, Rhees, at the time, made them based on his desire to do justice to his understanding of Wittgenstein's philosophical orientation. Against this background, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The re-enchantment of the world: McDowell, Scruton and Heidegger.George Reynolds - unknown
    In a recent discussion of disenchantment and re-enchantment Charles Taylor suggests that it is possible to respond to the disenchanted view of the world, in which meaning and value are understood as subjective projections, by articulating a re-enchanted sense of nature or the universe from the perspective of human ‘agency-in-the-world’, in which meaning and value are objective. The question I address in this thesis is, what could it mean to articulate a re-enchantment from within our ‘agency-in-the-world’? In Chapter One I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant’s Emergence and Sellarsian Cognitive Science.Richard McDonough - 2014 - Open Journal of Philosophy 4 (1):44-53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on the Gulf Between Believers and Non-Believers.Paolo Tripodi - 2013 - Philosophia 41 (1):63-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Are we our brains?Stephen Burwood - 2009 - Philosophical Investigations 32 (2):113-133.
    My aim in this paper is to destabilise the brain-is-self thesis, something that is now regarded in some quarters as philosophical commonsense. My contention is that it is the epithelial body that enters into the formation of our sense of self and that largely bears the burden of personal identity as well as playing the key role in grounding our psychological ascriptions. Lacking any sensorimotor or social presence of its own, the brain by itself cannot "underlie" selfhood, but only as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Wittgenstein's metaphysical use and Derrida's metaphysical appurtenance.Mireille M. Truong Rootham - 1996 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 22 (2):27-46.
    Everything about Derrida suggests that he is for a radical reform or transformation of language, whilst Wittgenstein seems to vindicate a fidelity to ordinary language and to want to 'expunge' from language the 'metaphysical use' of words. But just how opposed are they? My contention in this paper is that Wittgenstein does not 'deconstruct', as some critics have rather loosely suggested, because, as we shall see, the expunging of metaphysical use favoured by Wittgenstein does not amount to the deconstruction of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and Meaning.Charles Freeman-Core - 2021 - Philosophical Investigations 44 (4):403-425.
    Philosophical Investigations, Volume 44, Issue 4, Page 403-425, October 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflective Equilibrium from a Wittgensteinian Perspective.Hiroshi Ohtani - 2021 - Philosophia 49 (4):1631-1649.
    The lingering mystery of John Rawls’s reflective equilibrium is that its nature is unclear. Rawls at times suggests he is merely describing people’s conceptions of justice, whereas at other times he implies that his reflective equilibrium is a way to justify his conception of justice. Faced with seemingly conflictual passages, most scholars privilege the justificatory ones. However, I argue that this is not an effective strategy because understanding how the descriptive and justificatory aspects of reflective equilibrium fit together is the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reification and immaterial production.Dimitris Gakis - 2019 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 46 (6):676-702.
    Reification, a central theme in radical social/political theory from the 1920s onward, has started falling out of fashion since the 1970s, a period when a number of crucial alterations in the compo...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Unbearable Lightness of Representing ‘Reality’ in Science Education: A response to Schulz.Michalinos Zembylas - 2008 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 40 (4):494-514.
    This article responds to Schulz's criticisms of an earlier paper published in Educational Philosophy and Theory. The purpose in this paper is to clarify and extend some of my earlier arguments, to indicate what is unfortunate (i.e. what is lost) from a non‐charitable, modernist reading of Lyotardian postmodernism (despite its weaknesses), and to suggest what new directions are emerging in science education from efforts to move beyond an either/or dichotomy of foundationalism and relativism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The musical horizon of religion : Blumenberg's Matthäuspassion.Bruce Krajewski - 1993 - History of the Human Sciences 6 (4):81-95.
    Compassion is a sign of superficiality: broken destinies and unrelenting misery either make you scream or turn you to stone. Pity is not only inefficient; it is also insulting. And besides, how can you pity another when you yourself suffer ignominiously? Compassion is as common as it is because it does not bind you to anything! Nobody in this world has yet died from another's suffering. And the one who said that he died for us did not die; he was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Citizens, Denizens and the Res Publica: Environmental Ethics, Structures of Feeling and Political Expression.Mick Smith - 2005 - Environmental Values 14 (2):145 - 162.
    Environmental ethics should be understood as a radical project that challenges the limits of contemporary ethical and political expression, a limit historically defined by the concept of the citizen. This dominant model of public being, frequently justified in terms of a formal or procedural rationally, facilitates an exclusionary ethos that fails to properly represent our concerns for the non-human world. It tends to regard emotionally mediated concerns for others as a source of irrational and subjective distortions in an otherwise rationally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Revolution, rupture, rhetoric.Chris Fleming & John O’Carroll - 2012 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 38 (1):39-57.
    This article traces certain rhetorics of knowledge-change as well as a few models of such change. In particular, it focuses on models that emphasize novelty and sudden transformation. To this end, the works of Thomas Kuhn, and the debates surrounding his celebrated modeling of the paradigm, are explored. Having established – at least in an illustrative fashion – the role of novelty in Kuhn’s philosophy of science, we then look more briefly at the mid-career work of Michel Foucault (his Order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Education and the possibility of outsider understanding.David Bridges - 2009 - Ethics and Education 4 (2):105-123.
    In education issues to do with insider and outsider understanding arise in debates about religious education and about certain areas of research, and in argument about education for international understanding. Here I challenge the dichotomy between insider and outsider, arguing that a more collectivist view of human identity combined with elements of 'the self which we share with our fellows' means that we always stand in part as an insider and in part as an outsider in relation to others. I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Our Natural Constitution: Wolterstorff on Reid and Wittgenstein.Bob Plant - 2003 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 1 (2):157-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • One’s Own’ in the Other and the Other in ‘One’s Own.Jasmin Trächtler - 2022 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 99 (1):99-123.
    The questions of how we can understand others and how we can know what they feel, think and sense have repeatedly preoccupied Wittgenstein since the 1930s and especially in his last writings. In this article, the author will tackle these questions by focusing on the other as other or strange. For it is also the strangeness of others, their otherness as such, that makes it difficult and even impossible to recognize and understand their inner life. As she will show, such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein's New Way of Talking to Himself.C. J. Higgins - 2022 - Philosophical Investigations 46 (1):22-49.
    A lack of consensus persists as to whom exactly the dialogues of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations are between: Wittgenstein and an interlocutor? Or perhaps a variety of interlocutors, none of whom can be identified with Wittgenstein himself? I argue here that this lack of consensus is possibly due to an ambiguity in the ordinary concept of “talking to oneself,” and that a new concept of “talking to oneself” appropriate to Wittgenstein's dialogues is needed to properly understand them. Wittgenstein is talking to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hamann's Influence on Wittgenstein.Lauri Juhana Olavinpoika Snellman - 2018 - Nordic Wittgenstein Review 7 (1):59-82.
    The paper examines Johann Georg Hamann’s influence on Ludwig Wittgenstein’s late philosophy. Wittgenstein’s letters, diaries and Drury’s memoirs show that Wittgenstein read Hamann’s writings in the early 1930s and 1950s. Wittgenstein’s diary notes and the Cambridge lectures show that Wittgenstein’s discussion of Hamann’s views in 1931 corresponds to adopting a Hamannian view of symbols and rule-following. The view of language as an intertwining of signs, objects and meanings in use forms a common core in the philosophies of Hamann and Wittgenstein. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical Autobiography: St Augustine and John Stuart Mill.Martin Warner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 16:189-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical Autobiography: St Augustine and John Stuart Mill.Martin Warner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 16:189-210.
    Many classic philosophical debates converge on the twin questions ‘What is man?’ and ‘What is his place in nature?’, in the sense that taking up a position in those debates normally commits one to a certain range of answers to these questions. Such answers typically lie near the centre of one's web of belief, deeply entrenched in the structure of one's concepts, and thus remain remarkably resistant to the standard techniques of confirmation and refutation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein's metaphysical use and Derrida's metaphysical appurtenance.Mireille M. Truong Rootham - 1996 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 22 (2):27-46.
    Everything about Derrida suggests that he is for a radical reform or transformation of language, whilst Wittgenstein seems to vindicate a fidelity to ordinary language and to want to 'expunge' from language the 'metaphysical use' of words. But just how opposed are they? My contention in this paper is that Wittgenstein does not 'deconstruct', as some critics have rather loosely suggested, because, as we shall see, the expunging of metaphysical use favoured by Wittgenstein does not amount to the deconstruction of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein: A Feminist Interpretation.Peg O'Connor - 2006 - Hypatia 21 (3):207-210.
    In this new book, Alessandra Tanesini demonstrates that feminist thought has a lot to offer to the study of Wittgenstein's philosophical work, and that -at the same time-that work can inspire feminist reflection in new directions. In Wittgenstein, Tanesini offers a highly original interpretation of several themes in Wittgenstein's philosophy. She argues that when we look at his work through feminist eyes we discover that he is not primarily concerned with providing solutions to technical problems in the philosophy of mind, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Conversion in Philosophy: Wittgenstein's “Saving Word”.Antonia Soulez - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    Wittgenstein raises the notion of “conversion” in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical “grammar,” in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries and from the history of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conversion in Philosophy: Wittgenstein's "Saving Word".Antonia Soulez & Melissa McMahon - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):127-150.
    Wittgenstein raises the notion of "conversion" in philosophy through his claims that philosophical understanding is a matter of the will rather than the intellect. Soulez examines this notion in Wittgenstein's philosophy through a series of reflections on the aims and methodology of his philosophical "grammar," in relation to comparable models among Wittgenstein's contemporaries and from the history of philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Necessity for Particularity in Education and Child-Rearing: the moral issue.Paul Smeyers - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 26 (1):63-73.
    The justification debate has always been a major issue within philosophy of education. In this study Wittgensteinian interpretation of this matter is offered. It is argued that in using his framework justification itself has to be thought of differently, i.e. as making explicit the bedrock of the form of life the educator finds him or herself in. But Wittgenstein’s insights highlight too the particularity of the ethical and therefore also of the educational situation. The paper argues that educators cannot but (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The tightrope Walker.Severin Schroeder - 2007 - Ratio 20 (4):442-463.
    Contrary to a widespread interpretation, Wittgenstein did not regard credal statements as merely metaphorical expressions of an attitude towards life. He accepted that Christian faith involves belief in God's existence. At the same time he held that although as a hypothesis, God's existence is extremely implausible, Christian faith is not unreasonable. Is that a consistent view? According to Wittgenstein, religious faith should not be seen as a hypothesis, based on evidence, but as grounded in a proto‐religious attitude, a way of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The texture of embodiment: Foundation for medical ethics. [REVIEW]David Schenck - 1986 - Human Studies 9 (1):43 - 54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Capturing the World — sub specie aeternitatis.Thirunalan Sasitharan - 2017 - Philosophy of Management 16 (3):211-216.
    How should the artist manage his time and work? Art practice is a complex, diverse and multifaceted enterprise. The premium on innovation and creativity is unusually high, the return on investment is almost impossible to calculate and the value, when it is truly successful, is priceless. Yet like any form of organized, analyzable work which produces material output, art practice is governed by specific task-orientated, rule-bound skills pertaining to technique, craft and presentation which are culture-specific and a tradition unto themselves. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psyches Therapeia: Therapeutic Dimensions in Heidegger and Wittgenstein.Robert Sanchez Jr & Robert Stolorow - 2013 - Comparative and Continental Philosophy 5 (1):67-80.
    This article explores the philosophies of Heidegger and Wittgenstein to illustrate the thesis that philosophy is a human activity exhibiting a unity of investigative and therapeutic aims. For both philosophers, the purpose of philosophical concepts is to point toward a path of transformation rather than to explain. For both, a first step on this path is the recognition of constraining illusions, whether conventional or metaphysical. For both, such illusions are sedimented in linguistic practices, and for both, philosophical investigation is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Leaving everything as it is: Political inquiry after Wittgenstein.John G. Gunnell - 2013 - Contemporary Political Theory 12 (2):80-101.
    The assumed difference and continuing estrangement between political philosophy and political science is a relatively recent development. Both fields sprang from closely entwined concerns about democracy and matters of social and political justice, and today both must still confront their practical as well as cognitive relationship to their subject matter. This issue, however, has receded into the background of these discourses. Ludwig Wittgenstein's vision of philosophy is in effect a vision of social inquiry. His work, when viewed from this perspective, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Between Home and World: Agnes Heller's the Concept of the Beautiful.David Roberts - 1999 - Thesis Eleven 59 (1):95-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Qur'anic Recitation and The Aesthetics of Piety.Rita Elizabeth Risser - 2018 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76 (3):309-318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Notes on saying and showing, beauty, and other ideas of interest to art and education, with reference to Ludwig Wittgenstein.Stuart Richmond - 2008 - Paideusis: Journal of the Canadian Philosophy of Education Society 17 (2):81-90.
    Conventionally, it is true an essay has a structure that moves progressively and logically from a beginning to a conclusion. In this group of small essays, I would like to explore my interests in the arts and education by working more with broad strokes, letting meanings emerge from passages in a less linear way, more like a collage, for example. Perhaps such an approach will be congenial for the arts, which are elusive, felt and expressive as much as conceptual.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and post‐analytic philosophy of education: Rorty or Lyotard?Michael Peters - 1997 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 29 (2):1-32.
    I was thinking about my philosophical work and saying to myself: ‘I destroy, I destroy, I destroy…’Context: The ‘linguistic turn’ of Western philosophy ; and correlatively, the decline of universalist discourses. The weariness with regard to ‘theory’, and the miserable slackening that goes along with it. The time has come to philosophize.…there is no danger of philosophy's ‘coming to an end’. Religion did not come to an end in the Enlightenment, nor painting in Impressionism. Even if the period from Plato (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Composition, improvisation, constitution: Forms of life in the music of Pierre boulez and ornette Coleman.Timothy S. Murphy - 1998 - Angelaki 3 (2):75 – 102.
    (1998). Composition, improvisation, constitution: forms of life in the music of pierre boulez and ornette coleman. Angelaki: Vol. 3, The love of music, pp. 75-102.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sinsentido e ironía: la estrategia de auto- refutación en Wittgenstein y el concepto de comunicación indirecta en Kierkegaard.Shlomy Mualem - 2017 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 53:203-228.
    En el prefacio al Tractatus, Wittgenstein establece que la cuestión del sinsentido tiene que ver con trazar los límites del lenguaje. Las expresiones sinsentido van más allá de los límites del lenguaje significativo y residen “del otro lado” de lo que puede ser dicho. Aún así, al final del libro declara que sus propias proposiciones son, hablando de manera estricta, sinsentidos. El presente trabajo pretende analizar la estrategia de auto-refutación del primer Wittgenstein como un modo de trascender los límites del (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Allowing the Fly to Leave: The Chance Meeting of Wittgenstein and Buñuel at a Mexican Dinner Table.Michael T. Miller & James Batcho - 2018 - Film-Philosophy 22 (3):384-405.
    Within Luis Buñuel's classic surrealist film The Exterminating Angel is a philosophical motif which expresses, demonstrates, and develops two of Ludwig Wittgenstein's central concepts: language lays traps for the unwary that can lead to illogical thought and mind-bending quests; and any picture of the world is formed through cultural habits that cannot be rationally expressed but can be changed. This article argues that what we find in Buñuel's Angel is a “picture” that is at one level rational and habitual and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fairness, Epistemology, and Rules: A Prolegomenon to a Philosophy of Officiating?Graham McFee - 2011 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 38 (2):229-253.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Audiences Appreciating Dances.Graham McFee - 2019 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 44 (1):92-116.
    Midwest Studies In Philosophy, Volume 44, Issue 1, Page 92-116, December 2019.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark