Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Logic and Aristotle's “Rhetoric” and “Poetics” in Medieval Arabic Philosophy.Deborah L. Black - 1990 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 54 (1):131-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Some Aspects of Avicenna's Theory of God's Knowledge of Particulars.Michael E. Marmura - 1962 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 82 (3):299-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Scientific Methodologies in Medieval Islam.Jon McGinnis - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):307-327.
    : The present study considers Ibn Sînâ's (Lat. Avicenna) account of induction (istiqra') and experimentation (tajriba). For Ibn Sînâ induction purportedly provided the absolute, necessary and certain first principles of a science. Ibn Sînâ criticized induction, arguing that it can neither guarantee the necessity nor provide the primitiveness required of first principles. In it place, Ibn Sînâ developed a theory of experimentation, which avoids the pitfalls of induction by not providing absolute, but conditional, necessary and certain first principles. The theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The human soul's individuation and its survival after the body's death: Avicenna on the causal relation between body and soul: Thérèse-Anne Druart.Thérèse-Anne Druart - 2000 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 10 (2):259-273.
    As for Avicenna the human soul is a complete substance which does not inhere in the body nor is imprinted in it, asserting its survival after the death of the body seems easy. Yet, he needs the body to explain its individuation. The paper analyzes Avicenna's arguments in the De anima sections, V, 3 & 4, of the Shifā ' in order to explore the exact causal relation there is between the human soul and its body and confronts these arguments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes on Intellect.Herbert A. Davidson - 1994 - Philosophy East and West 44 (3):580-582.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Meno's Paradox and De Re Knowledge in Aristotle's Theory of Demonstration.Michael Ferejohn - 1988 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 5 (2):99 - 117.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Al-Kindi and the reception of Greek philosophy.Peter Adamson - 2004 - In Peter Adamson & Richard C. Taylor (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 32--51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Avicenna's Metaphysics in Context.Robert Wisnovsky - 2003 - Cornell University Press.
    The eleventh-century philosopher and physician Abu Ali ibn Sina was known in the West by his Latinized name Avicenna. An analysis of the sources and evolution of Avicenna's metaphysics, this book focuses on the answers he and his predecessors gave to two fundamental pairs of questions: what is the soul and how does it cause the body; and what is God and how does He cause the world? To respond to these challenges, Avicenna invented new concepts and distinctions and reinterpreted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Al-Kindi, De radiis.M. -T. D'alverny & F. Hudry - 1974 - Archives d'Histoire Doctrinale et Littéraire du Moyen Âge 41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Re-examination of Aristotle's Philosophy of Science.Bas C. van Fraassen - 1980 - Dialogue 19 (1):20-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Knowledge of the Universal and Knowledge of the Particular in Aristotle.Walter Leszl - 1972 - Review of Metaphysics 26 (2):278 - 313.
    ACCORDING TO MANY of the most authoritative interpreters and commentators of Aristotle, there is in his thought "a discrepancy between the real and the intelligible," that is to say, a failure to reconcile the requirements of his ontology with those of his logic and epistemology. From the point of view of his ontology, the individual, in effect the substance provided with matter, is basic, while the universal is derivative. From the point of view of his logic and epistemology, only the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations